C. D. Broad

{{Short description|English philosopher (1887–1971)}}

{{Use dmy dates|date=January 2020}}

{{EngvarB|date=January 2020}}

{{Infobox philosopher

| region = Western philosophy

| era = 20th-century philosophy

| name = C. D. Broad

| honorific_suffix = {{post-nominals|country=GBR|FBA|size=100%}}

| image = C. D. Broad philosopher.png

| caption =Broad in 1959

| birth_name = Charlie Dunbar Broad

| birth_date = {{birth date|df=y|1887|12|30}}

| birth_place = Harlesden, Middlesex, England

| death_date = {{death date and age|df=y|1971|3|11|1887|12|30}}

| death_place = Cambridge, Cambridgeshire, England

| alma_mater = Trinity College, Cambridge

| institutions = Trinity College, Cambridge

| school_tradition = Analytic

| main_interests = Metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, philosophy of mind, logic

| notable_ideas = Growing block universe
Rate of passage argumentC. D. Broad (1978), "Ostensible temporality." In Richard M. Gale (ed.), The Philosophy of Time: A Collection of Essays, Humanities Press.Ned Markosian, "How fast does time pass?", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53(4):829–844 (1993).
The "critical philosophy" and "speculative philosophy" distinctionC. D. Broad. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/csp.html "Critical and Speculative Philosophy"]. In Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements (First Series), ed. J. H. Muirhead (London: G. Allen and Unwin, 1924): 77–100.
The "occurrent causation" and "non-occurrent causation" distinction

| academic_advisors = J. M. E. McTaggart

| doctoral_students = Knut Erik TranøyKnut E. Tranøy, "Wittgenstein in Cambridge 1949–1951: Some Personal Recollections", in: F. A. Flowers III, Ian Ground (eds.), Portraits of Wittgenstein: Abridged Edition, Bloomsbury Academic, 2018, p. 452.

}}

Charlie Dunbar Broad {{post-nominals|country=GBR|FBA}} (30 December 1887 – 11 March 1971), usually cited as C. D. Broad, was an English epistemologist, historian of philosophy, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, and writer on the philosophical aspects of psychical research. He was known for his thorough and dispassionate examinations of arguments in such works as Scientific Thought (1923), The Mind and Its Place in Nature (1925), and Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy (2 vols., 1933–1938).

Broad's essay on "Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism" in Ethics and the History of Philosophy (1952) introduced the philosophical terms occurrent causation and non-occurrent causation, which became the basis for the contemporary distinction between "agent-causal" and "event-causal" in debates on libertarian free will.

Biography

Broad was born in Harlesden, in Middlesex, England.Harlesden was part of Middlesex until 1965; today it is part of the London Borough of Brent in Greater London.

He was educated at Dulwich College from 1900 until 1906. He gained a scholarship in 1906 to study at Trinity College, Cambridge, graduating in 1910 with First-Class Honours, with distinction.Hodges, S. 1981. God's Gift: A Living History of Dulwich College. London: Heinemann. p. 87. He became a Fellow of Trinity College the following year.

= Career =

As his fellowship at Trinity College was a non-residential position, he was also able to accept a position as an assistant lecturer that he had applied for at St Andrews University, where he remained until 1920. That year, he was appointed professor at Bristol University, working there until 1923, when he returned to Trinity as a lecturer. From 1926 until 1931, he was a lecturer in 'moral science' at Cambridge University's Faculty of Philosophy.

Later at Cambridge, he was appointed in 1931 as 'Sidgwick Lecturer', a role he would keep until 1933, when he was appointed Knightbridge Professor of Moral Philosophy at the university, a position he held for twenty years (until 1953).{{cite web|title=Charlie Dunbar Broad|website=Trinity College Chapel|url=http://trinitycollegechapel.com/about/memorials/brasses/broad/}} In 1927 he gave the British Academy's Master-Mind Lecture, entitled "Sir Isaac Newton."{{cite journal |author=Broad, C. D. |year=1927 |title=Sir Isaac Newton |journal=Proceedings of the British Academy |volume=13 |pages=173–202}} Annual Lecture on a Master Mind. Henriette Hertz Trust. Read July 15, 1927. Reprinted in Ethics and the history of philosophy, pp. 3–28.

In addition, Broad was President of the Aristotelian Society from 1927 to 1928, and again from 1954 to 1955. He was also President of the Society for Psychical Research in 1935 and 1958.

= Personal life =

Broad was openly homosexual at a time when homosexual acts were illegal. In March 1958, Broad along with fellow philosophers A. J. Ayer and Bertrand Russell, writer J.B. Priestley and 27 others sent a letter to The Times which urged the acceptance of the Wolfenden Report's recommendation that homosexual acts should "no longer be a criminal offence."N. G. Annan, Attlee, A. J. Ayer, Robert Boothby, C. M. Bowra, C. D. Broad, David Cecil, L. John Collins, Alex Comfort, A. E. Dyson, Robert Exon, Geoffrey Faber, Jacquetta Hawkes, Trevor Huddleston, C. R. Julian Huxley, C. Day-Lewis, W. R. Niblett, J. B. Priestley, Russell, Donald O. Soper, Stephen Spender, Mary Stocks, A. J. P. Taylor, E. M. W. Tillyard, Alec R. Vidler, Kenneth Walker, Leslie D. Weatherhead, C. V. Wedgwood, Angus Wilson, John Wisdom, and Barbara Wootton. 7 March 1958. "Letter to the Editor." The Times.

Theory

= Psychical research =

Broad argued that if research could demonstrate that psychic events occur, this would challenge philosophical theories of "basic limiting principles" in at least five ways:{{Cite journal|last1=Broad|first1=C. D.|year=1949|title=The Relevance of Psychical Research to Philosophy|url=http://www.stafforini.com/broad/Broad%20-%20The%20relevance%20of%20psychical%20research%20to%20philosophy.pdf|journal=Philosophy|volume=24|issue=91|pages=291–309|doi=10.1017/S0031819100007452|s2cid=144880410 }}

  1. Backward causation (i.e., the future affecting the past) is rejected by many philosophers, but would be shown to occur if, for example, people could predict the future.
  2. One common argument against dualism (i.e., the belief that, while bodies are physical entities, minds are a different, non-physical sort of entity) is that physical and non-physical things cannot interact. However, this would be shown to be possible if people can move physical objects by thought (telekinesis).
  3. Similarly, philosophers tend to be skeptical about claims that non-physical 'stuff' could interact with anything. This would also be challenged if minds are shown to be able to communicate with each other, as would be the case if mind-reading is possible.
  4. Philosophers generally accept that we can only learn about the world through reason and perception. This belief would be challenged if people were able to psychically perceive events in other places.
  5. Physicalist philosophers believe that there cannot be persons without bodies. If ghosts were shown to exist, this view would be challenged.

In his 1949 paper, Broad examined the implications of research by British parapsychologist Samuel Soal, who claimed to have discovered a subject, Basil Shackleton, capable of guessing the identity of Zener cards with odds of 'billions to one'. However, the validity of these findings was later questioned by Betty Markwick, following testimony from a colleague suggesting that Soal had manipulated both data and experiment methods.{{Cite journal |last=Markwick |first=Betty |date=1978 |title=The Soal-Goldney experiments with Basil Shackelton: New evidence of data manipulation. |journal=Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research |volume=56 |pages=250–277}}

= Free will =

In his essay "Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism", Broad argued for non-occurrent causation as "literally determined by the agent or self." The agent could be considered as a substance or continuant, and not by a total cause which contains as factors events in and dispositions of the agent. Thus, our efforts would be completely determined, but their causes would not be prior events. New series of events would then originate, which he called "continuants", which are essentially causa sui.

Peter van Inwagen says that Broad formulated an excellent version of what van Inwagen has called the "Consequence Argument" in defence of incompatibilism.{{Cite journal|last=van Inwagen|first=Peter|date=2008-09-01|title=How to Think about the Problem of Free Will|url=https://andrewmbailey.com/pvi/How_to_Think_About_Free_Will.pdf|journal=The Journal of Ethics|language=en|volume=12|issue=3|pages=337|doi=10.1007/s10892-008-9038-7|s2cid=144635471|issn=1572-8609}}

=Metaphilosophy and science=

Broad distinguished between critical philosophy and speculative philosophy. He described critical philosophy as analysing "unanalysed concepts in daily life and in science" and then "expos[ing] them to every objection that we can think of". While speculative philosophy's role is to "take over all aspects of human experience, to reflect upon them, and to try to think out a view of Reality as a whole which shall do justice to all of them".{{cite book |last=Broad |first=C. D. |url=https://archive.org/details/contemporarybrit0000unse_m4z2 |title=Contemporary British Philosophy Personal Statements · Volume 20 |date=1953 |publisher=London, Allen & Unwin |pages=87–100 |chapter=Critical and Speculative Philosophy |orig-year=1924 |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.46370/page/n73/mode/1up |url-access=registration}}

One aspect of critical philosophy was the Principle of Exceptional Cases, whereby everyday concepts are considered in highly abnormal cases, so as to "clear up the meaning" of a concept.

Broad saw philosophy and science as supplemental to one another. Scientists who ignore philosophy expose themselves to a "danger to which the natural scientist is peculiarly liable. The extraordinary success of physics and chemistry within their own sphere tempts men to think that the world is simply a physico-chemical system". Whereas philosophers who ignore science are ignoring properties which are "very pervasive" and can shed light on things.

In terms of empirical propositions Broad distinguished between inspective empirical propositions which he defined "one which asserts of some particular existent with which the mind is acquainted at the time some property which the mind can notice by inspection to belong to it" and inferred empirical propositions which are "derived from a number of perceptual propositions either directly by pure inductive generalization, or indirectly by deduction from one or more inductive generalizations".

Works

  • 1914. Perception, Physics and Reality. An Enquiry into the Information that Physical Science can Supply about the Real. London: Cambridge University Press.
  • 1923. Scientific Thought. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.
  • 1925. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/mpn/mpn-con.html The Mind and Its Place in Nature]. London: Kegan.
  • 1926. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/bacon.html The Philosophy of Francis Bacon]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • 1930. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/ftet/ftet.html Five Types of Ethical Theory] . New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.
  • 1931. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/war.html War Thoughts in Peace Time]. London: Humphrey Milford.
  • 1933. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/mc/mc.html Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy]. Vol. 1. Cambridge University Press.
  • 1934. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/dil.html Determinism, Indeterminism, and Libertarianism]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • 1938. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/mc/mc.html Examination of McTaggart's Philosophy]. Vol. 2. Cambridge University Press.
  • 1943. Berkeley's Argument about Material Substance. Annual Philosophical Lecture, Henriette Hertz Trust, British Academy
  • 1952/2000. Ethics and the History of Philosophy. Routledge. {{ISBN|0-415-22530-2}}.
  • 1953/2000. Religion, Philosophy and Psychic Research. Routledge. {{ISBN|0-415-22558-2}}.
  • 1955. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/hpps.html Human Personality and the Possibility of Its Survival]. University of California Press.
  • 1958. [https://web.archive.org/web/20220223154644/https://www.imagomundi.biz/wp-content/uploads/2019/08/PNFL338-Personal_Identity_and_Survival.pdf Personal Identity and Survival]. London: Society for Psychical Research.
  • 1962. Lectures on Psychical Research. Incorporating the Perrott Lectures given in Cambridge University in 1959 and 1960. New York: Humanities Press.
  • contains [https://web.archive.org/web/20090706000602/http://www.survivalafterdeath.org.uk/articles/broad/elliott.htm Saltmarsh's Investigation of Mrs Warren Elliott's Mediumship]". Lectures on Psychical Research. Incorporating the Perrott Lectures given in Cambridge University in 1959 and 1960. New York: Humanities Press.
  • 1968. Induction, Probability, and Causation. Selected Papers of C. D. Broad. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  • 1971. Broad's Critical Essays in Moral Philosophy, New York: Humanities Press.
  • 1975. Leibniz: An Introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. {{ISBN|0-521-20691-X}}
  • 1976. [http://www.ditext.com/broad/berkeley2.html Berkeley's Argument].. Haskell House Pub Ltd.
  • 1978. Kant: An Introduction. (ed.) C. Lewy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. {{ISBN|0-521-21755-5}}
  • 1985. Ethics. (ed.) C. Lewy, Dordrecht: Nijhoff.
  • 2023. C. D. Broad: Key Unpublished Writings, (ed.) Joel Walmsley{{Cite book |last=Walmsley |first=Joel |url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781003081135 |title=C.D. Broad: Key Unpublished Writings |date=2022-06-13 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-003-08113-5 |edition=1 |location=London |language=en |doi=10.4324/9781003081135}}

Notes

{{Reflist|35em|group=lower-roman}}

References

{{reflist}}

Sources

Further reading

External links

{{wikiquote}}

  • [https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/broad/ Charlie Dunbar Broad] entry at The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • [http://www.stafforini.com/blog/c-d-broad-a-bibliography/ C. D. Broad: a bibliography]. Provides full pdf's of most of Broad's writings.
  • [http://ditext.com/broad/cdbroad.html C. D. Broad on Digital Text International]
  • [https://web.archive.org/web/20080210232918/http://rabbit.trin.cam.ac.uk/~jon/Broad/Broadframeset.html Papers of Charlie Dunbar Broad]

{{analytic philosophy}}

{{philosophy of mind}}

{{philosophy of science}}

{{Authority control}}

{{DEFAULTSORT:Broad, C. D.}}

Category:1887 births

Category:1971 deaths

Category:20th-century English male writers

Category:20th-century English philosophers

Category:20th-century English essayists

Category:Academics of the University of St Andrews

Category:Action theorists

Category:Alumni of Trinity College, Cambridge

Category:Analytic philosophers

Category:Aristotelian philosophers

Category:English ethicists

Category:English male essayists

Category:British consciousness researchers and theorists

Category:English essayists

Category:English gay writers

Category:English historians of philosophy

Category:English logicians

Category:English writers on paranormal topics

Category:British epistemologists

Category:Fellows of Trinity College, Cambridge

Category:George Berkeley scholars

Category:Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz scholars

Category:British historians of science

Category:Kant scholars

Category:British LGBTQ historians

Category:LGBTQ philosophers

Category:English LGBTQ rights activists

Category:English LGBTQ writers

Category:Libertarian theorists

Category:Metaphysics writers

Category:Ontologists

Category:British parapsychologists

Category:People educated at Dulwich College

Category:People from Harlesden

Category:British philosophers of logic

Category:British philosophers of mind

Category:English philosophers of religion

Category:English philosophers of science

Category:Philosophers of time

Category:Philosophers of war

Category:Presidents of the Aristotelian Society

Category:Probability theorists

Category:Writers about activism and social change

Category:Writers about religion and science

Category:Knightbridge Professors of Philosophy

Category:20th-century British psychologists