Conjunction elimination
{{Infobox mathematical statement
| name = Conjunction elimination
| type = Rule of inference
| field = Propositional calculus
| statement = If the conjunction and is true, then is true, and is true.
| symbolic statement =
| conjectured by =
| conjecture date =
| first stated by =
| first stated in =
| first proof by =
| first proof date =
| open problem =
| known cases =
| implied by =
| equivalent to =
| generalizations =
| consequences =
}}
{{Transformation rules}}
In propositional logic, conjunction elimination (also called and elimination, ∧ elimination,{{cite book | author=David A. Duffy | title=Principles of Automated Theorem Proving | location=New York | publisher=Wiley | year=1991 }} Sect.3.1.2.1, p.46 or simplification)Copi and Cohen{{cn|reason=Without title, this is hardly a useful reference.|date=February 2014}}Moore and Parker{{cn|date=February 2014}}Hurley{{cn|date=February 2014}} is a valid immediate inference, argument form and rule of inference which makes the inference that, if the conjunction A and B is true, then A is true, and B is true. The rule makes it possible to shorten longer proofs by deriving one of the conjuncts of a conjunction on a line by itself.
An example in English:
:It's raining and it's pouring.
:Therefore it's raining.
The rule consists of two separate sub-rules, which can be expressed in formal language as:
:
and
:
The two sub-rules together mean that, whenever an instance of "" appears on a line of a proof, either "" or "" can be placed on a subsequent line by itself. The above example in English is an application of the first sub-rule.
Formal notation
The conjunction elimination sub-rules may be written in sequent notation:
:
and
:
where is a metalogical symbol meaning that is a syntactic consequence of and is also a syntactic consequence of in logical system;
and expressed as truth-functional tautologies or theorems of propositional logic:
:
and
:
where and are propositions expressed in some formal system.