Dependence logic

Dependence logic is a logical formalism, created by Jouko Väänänen,Väänänen 2007 which adds dependence atoms to the language of first-order logic. A dependence atom is an expression of the form =\!\!(t_1 \ldots t_n), where t_1 \ldots t_n are terms, and corresponds to the statement that the value of t_n is functionally dependent on the values of t_1,\ldots, t_{n-1}.

Dependence logic is a logic of imperfect information, like branching quantifier logic or independence-friendly logic (IF logic): in other words, its game-theoretic semantics can be obtained from that of first-order logic by restricting the availability of information to the players, thus allowing for non-linearly ordered patterns of dependence and independence between variables. However, dependence logic differs from these logics in that it separates the notions of dependence and independence from the notion of quantification.

Syntax

The syntax of dependence logic is an extension of that of first-order logic. For a fixed signature σ = (Sfunc, Srel, ar), the set of all well-formed dependence logic formulas is defined according to the following rules:

=Terms=

Terms in dependence logic are defined precisely as in first-order logic.

=Atomic formulas=

There are three types of atomic formulas in dependence logic:

  1. A relational atom is an expression of the form Rt_1 \ldots t_n for any n-ary relation R in our signature and for any n-tuple of terms (t_1, \ldots, t_n);
  2. An equality atom is an expression of the form t_1 = t_2, for any two terms t_1 and t_2;
  3. A dependence atom is an expression of the form =\!\!(t_1 \ldots t_n), for any n \in \mathbb N and for any n-tuple of terms (t_1, \ldots, t_n).

Nothing else is an atomic formula of dependence logic.

Relational and equality atoms are also called first-order atoms.

=Complex formulas and sentences=

For a fixed signature σ, the set of all formulas \phi of dependence logic and their respective sets of free variables \mbox{Free}(\phi) are defined as follows:

  1. Any atomic formula \phi is a formula, and \mbox{Free}(\phi) is the set of all variables occurring in it;
  2. If \phi is a formula, so is \lnot \phi and \mbox{Free}(\lnot\phi) = \mbox{Free}(\phi);
  3. If \phi and \psi are formulas, so is \phi \vee \psi and \mbox{Free}(\phi \vee \psi) = \mbox{Free}(\phi) \cup \mbox{Free}(\psi);
  4. If \phi is a formula and x is a variable, \exists x \phi is also a formula and \mbox{Free}(\exists v \phi) = \mbox{Free}(\phi) \backslash \{v\}.

Nothing is a dependence logic formula unless it can be obtained through a finite number of applications of these four rules.

A formula \phi such that \mbox{Free}(\phi) = \emptyset is a sentence of dependence logic.

==Conjunction and universal quantification==

In the above presentation of the syntax of dependence logic, conjunction and universal quantification are not treated as primitive operators; rather, they are defined in terms of negation and, respectively, disjunction and existential quantification, by means of De Morgan's Laws.

Therefore, \phi \wedge \psi is taken as a shorthand for \lnot (\lnot \phi \vee \lnot \psi), and \forall x \phi is taken as a shorthand for \lnot(\exists x (\lnot \phi)).

Semantics

The team semantics for dependence logic is a variant of Wilfrid Hodges' compositional semantics for IF logic.Hodges 1997Väänänen 2007, §3.2 There exist equivalent game-theoretic semantics for dependence logic, both in terms of imperfect information games and in terms of perfect information games.

=Teams=

Let \mathcal A = (A, \sigma, I) be a first-order structure and let V = \{v_1, \ldots, v_n\} be a finite set of variables. Then a team over {{mathcal|A}} with domain {{mvar|V}} is a set of assignments over {{mathcal|A}} with domain {{mvar|V}}, that is, a set of functions {{mvar|μ}} from {{mvar|V}} to {{mvar|A}}.

It may be helpful to visualize such a team as a database relation with attributes v_1, \ldots, v_n and with only one data type, corresponding to the domain {{mvar|A}} of the structure: for example, if the team {{mvar|X}} consists of four assignments \mu_1, \ldots, \mu_4 with domain \{v_1, v_2, v_3\} then one may represent it as the relation

:\begin{array}{c|ccc}

& v_1

& v_2

& v_3

\\

\hline

\mu_1 &

\mu_1(v_1) & \mu_1(v_2) & \mu_1(v_3)

\\

\mu_2 &

\mu_2(v_1) & \mu_2(v_2) & \mu_2(v_3)

\\

\mu_3 &

\mu_3(v_1) & \mu_3(v_2) & \mu_3(v_3)

\\

\mu_4 &

\mu_4(v_1) & \mu_4(v_2) & \mu_4(v_3)

\end{array}

=Positive and negative satisfaction=

Team semantics can be defined in terms of two relations \mathcal T and \mathcal C between structures, teams and formulas.

Given a structure \mathcal A, a team X over it and a dependence logic formula \phi whose free variables are contained in the domain of X, if (\mathcal A, X, \phi) \in \mathcal T we say that X is a trump for \phi in \mathcal A, and we write that \mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi; and analogously, if (\mathcal A, X, \phi) \in \mathcal C we say that X is a cotrump for \phi in \mathcal A, and we write that \mathcal A \models_X^- \phi.

If \mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi one can also say that \phi is positively satisfied by X in \mathcal A, and if instead \mathcal A \models_X^- \phi one can say that \phi is negatively satisfied by X in \mathcal A.

The necessity of considering positive and negative satisfaction separately is a consequence of the fact that in dependence logic, as in the logic of branching quantifiers or in IF logic, the law of the excluded middle does not hold; alternatively, one may assume that all formulas are in negation normal form, using De Morgan's relations in order to define universal quantification and conjunction from existential quantification and disjunction respectively, and consider positive satisfaction alone.

Given a sentence \phi, we say that \phi is true in \mathcal A if and only if \mathcal A \models_{\{\emptyset\}}^+ \phi, and we say that \phi is false in \mathcal A if and only if \mathcal A \models_{\{\emptyset\}}^- \phi.

=Semantic rules=

As for the case of Alfred Tarski's satisfiability relation for first-order formulas, the positive and negative satisfiability relations of the team semantics for dependence logic are defined by structural induction over the formulas of the language. Since the negation operator interchanges positive and negative satisfiability, the two inductions corresponding to \models^+ and \models^- need to be performed simultaneously:

==Positive satisfiability==

  1. \mathcal A \models_X^+ R t_1 \ldots t_n if and only if
  2. R is a n-ary symbol in the signature of \mathcal A;
  3. All variables occurring in the terms t_1, \ldots, t_n are in the domain of X;
  4. For every assignment \mu \in X, the evaluation of the tuple (t_1, \ldots, t_n) according to \mu is in the interpretation of R in \mathcal A;
  5. \mathcal A \models_X^+ t_1 = t_2 if and only if
  6. All variables occurring in the terms t_1 and t_2 are in the domain of X;
  7. For every assignment \mu \in X, the evaluations of t_1 and t_2 according to \mathcal A are the same;
  8. \mathcal A \models_X^+ =\!\!(t_1 \ldots t_n) if and only if any two assignments \mu, \mu' \in X whose evaluations of the tuple (t_1, \ldots, t_{n-1}) coincide assign the same value to t_n;
  9. \mathcal A \models_X^+ \lnot \phi if and only if \mathcal A \models_X^- \phi;
  10. \mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi \vee \psi if and only if there exist teams Y and Z such that
  11. X = Y \cup Z'
  12. \mathcal A \models_Y^+ \phi;
  13. \mathcal A \models_Z^+ \psi;
  14. \mathcal A \models_X^+ \exists x \phi if and only if there exists a function F from X to the domain of \mathcal A such that \mathcal A \models_{X[F/x]}^+ \phi, where X[F/x] = \{ \mu[F(\mu)/x] : \mu \in X\}.

==Negative satisfiability==

  1. \mathcal A \models_X^- R t_1 \ldots t_n if and only if
  2. R is a n-ary symbol in the signature of \mathcal A;
  3. All variables occurring in the terms t_1, \ldots, t_n are in the domain of X;
  4. For every assignment \mu \in X, the evaluation of the tuple (t_1, \ldots, t_n) according to \mu is not in the interpretation of R in \mathcal A;
  5. \mathcal A \models_X^- t_1 = t_2 if and only if
  6. All variables occurring in the terms t_1 and t_2 are in the domain of X;
  7. For every assignment \mu \in X, the evaluations of t_1 and t_2 according to \mathcal A are different;
  8. \mathcal A \models_X^- =\!\!(t_1 \ldots t_n) if and only if X is the empty team;
  9. \mathcal A \models_X^- \lnot \phi if and only if \mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi;
  10. \mathcal A \models_X^- \phi \vee \psi if and only if \mathcal A \models_X^- \phi and \mathcal A \models_X^- \psi;
  11. \mathcal A \models_X^- \exists x \phi if and only if \mathcal A \models_{X[A/x]}^- \phi, where X[A/x] = \{ \mu[a/x] : a \in A\} and A is the domain of \mathcal A.

Dependence logic and other logics

=Dependence logic and first-order logic=

Dependence logic is a conservative extension of first-order logic:Väänänen 2007, §3.2 in other words, for every first-order sentence \phi and structure \mathcal A we have that \mathcal A \models_{\{\emptyset\}}^+ \phi if and only if \phi is true in \mathcal A according to the usual first-order semantics. Furthermore, for any first-order formula \phi, \mathcal A \models_{X}^+ \phi if and only if all assignments \mu \in X satisfy \phi in \mathcal A according to the usual first-order semantics.

However, dependence logic is strictly more expressive than first-order logic:Väänänen 2007, §4 for example, the sentence

:\exists z \forall x_1 \forall x_2 \exists y_1 \exists y_2 (=\!\!(x_1, y_1) \wedge =\!\!(x_2, y_2) \wedge (x_1 = x_2 \leftrightarrow y_1 = y_2) \wedge y_1 \not = z)

is true in a model \mathcal A if and only if the domain of this model is infinite, even though no first-order formula \phi has this property.

=Dependence logic and second-order logic=

Every dependence logic sentence is equivalent to some sentence in the existential fragment of second-order logic,Väänänen 2007, §6.1 that is, to some second-order sentence of the form

:\exists R_1 \ldots \exists R_n \psi(R_1, \ldots, R_n)

where \psi(R_1, \ldots, R_n) does not contain second-order quantifiers.

Conversely, every second-order sentence in the above form is equivalent to some dependence logic sentence.Väänänen 2007, §6.3

As for open formulas, dependence logic corresponds to the downwards monotone fragment of existential second-order logic, in the sense that a nonempty class of teams is definable by a dependence logic formula if and only if the corresponding class of relations is downwards monotone and definable by an existential second-order formula.Kontinen and Väänänen 2009

=Dependence logic and branching quantifiers=

Branching quantifiers are expressible in terms of dependence atoms: for example, the expression

: (Q_Hx_1,x_2,y_1,y_2)\phi(x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2)\equiv\begin{pmatrix}\forall x_1 \exists y_1\\ \forall x_2 \exists y_2\end{pmatrix}\phi(x_1,x_2,y_1,y_2)

is equivalent to the dependence logic sentence \forall x_1 \exists y_1 \forall x_2 \exists y_2 (=\!\!(x_1, y_1) \wedge =\!\!(x_2, y_2) \wedge \phi), in the sense that the former expression is true in a model if and only if the latter expression is true.

Conversely, any dependence logic sentence is equivalent to some sentence in the logic of branching quantifiers, since all existential second-order sentences are expressible in branching quantifier logic.Enderton 1970Walkoe 1970

=Dependence logic and IF logic=

Any dependence logic sentence is logically equivalent to some IF logic sentence, and vice versa.Väänänen 2007, §3.6

However, the issue is subtler when it comes to open formulas. Translations between IF logic and dependence logic formulas, and vice versa, exist as long as the domain of the team is fixed: in other words, for all sets of variables V = \{v_1 \ldots v_n\} and all IF logic formulas \phi with free variables in V there exists a dependence logic formula \phi^D such that

:\mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi \Leftrightarrow \mathcal A \models_X^+ \phi^D

for all structures \mathcal A and for all teams X with domain V, and conversely, for every dependence logic formula \psi with free variables in V there exists an IF logic formula \psi^I such that

:\mathcal A \models_X^+ \psi \Leftrightarrow \mathcal A \models_X^+ \psi^I

for all structures \mathcal A and for all teams X with domain V. These translations cannot be compositional.Kontinen and Väänänen 2009 bis

Properties

Dependence logic formulas are downwards closed: if \mathcal A \models_X \phi and Y \subseteq X then \mathcal A \models_Y \psi. Furthermore, the empty team (but not the team containing the empty assignment) satisfies all formulas of dependence logic, both positively and negatively.

The law of the excluded middle fails in dependence logic: for example, the formula \exists y (=\!\!(y) \wedge y = x) is neither positively nor negatively satisfied by the team X = \{(x:0), (x:1)\}. Furthermore, disjunction is not idempotent and does not distribute over conjunction.Väänänen 2007, §3

Both the compactness theorem and the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem are true for dependence logic. Craig's interpolation theorem also holds, but, due to the nature of negation in dependence logic, in a slightly modified formulation: if two dependence logic formulas \phi and \psi are contradictory, that is, it is never the case that both \phi and \psi hold in the same model, then there exists a first-order sentence \theta in the common language of the two sentences such that \phi implies \theta and \theta is contradictory with \psi.Väänänen 2007, §6.2

As for IF logic,Hintikka 2002 dependence logic can define its own truth operator:Väänänen 2007, §6.4 more precisely, there exists a formula \tau(x) such that for every sentence \phi of dependence logic and all models \mathcal M_\omega which satisfy Peano's axioms, if '\phi' is the Gödel number of \phi then

: \mathcal M_\omega \models^+_{\{\emptyset\}} \!\phi if and only if \mathcal M_\omega \models^+_{\{\emptyset\}} \tau('\phi').

This does not contradict Tarski's undefinability theorem, since the negation of dependence logic is not the usual contradictory one.

Complexity

As a consequence of Fagin's theorem, the properties of finite structures definable by a

dependence logic sentence correspond exactly to NP properties. Furthermore, Durand and Kontinen showed that restricting the number of universal quantifiers or the arity of dependence atoms in

sentences gives rise to hierarchy theorems with respect to expressive power.Durand and Kontinen

The inconsistency problem of dependence logic is semidecidable, and in fact equivalent to the inconsistency problem for first-order logic.

However, the decision problem for dependence logic is non-arithmetical, and is in fact complete with respect to the \Pi_2 class of the Lévy hierarchy.Väänänen 2007, §7

Variants and extensions

=Team logic=

Team logicVäänänen 2007, §8 extends dependence logic with a contradictory negation \sim\!\!\phi. Its expressive power is equivalent to that of full second-order logic.Kontinen and Nurmi 2009

=Modal dependence logic=

The dependence atom, or a suitable variant thereof, can be added to the language of modal logic, thus obtaining modal dependence logic.Sevenster 2009Väänänen 2008Lohmann and Vollmer 2010

=Intuitionistic dependence logic=

As it is, dependence logic lacks an implication. The intuitionistic implication \phi \rightarrow \psi, whose name derives from the similarity between its definition and that of the implication of intuitionistic logic, can be defined as follows:Abramsky and Väänänen 2009

: \mathcal A \models_X \phi \rightarrow \psi if and only if for all Y \subseteq X such that \mathcal A \models_Y \phi it holds that \mathcal A \models_Y \psi.

Intuitionistic dependence logic, that is, dependence logic supplemented with the intuitionistic implication, is equivalent to second-order logic.Yang 2010

=Independence logic=

Instead of dependence atoms, independence logic adds to the language of first-order logic independence atoms \vec{t_1}\bot_{\vec{t_3}} \vec{t_2} where \vec{t_1}, \vec{t_2} and \vec{t_3} are tuples of terms. The semantics of these atoms is defined as follows:

: \mathcal A \models_X \vec{t_1}\bot_{\vec{t_3}} \vec{t_2} if and only if for all s,s' \in X with \vec{t_3}\langle s\rangle=\vec{t_3}\langle s'\rangle there exists s\in X such that \vec{t_3}\langle s\rangle=\vec{t_3}\langle s\rangle, \vec{t_1}\langle s\rangle=\vec{t_1}\langle s\rangle and \vec{t_2}\langle s\rangle=\vec{t_2}\langle s'\rangle.

Independence logic corresponds to existential second-order logic, in the sense that a non-empty class of teams is definable by an independence logic formula if and only if the corresponding class of relations is definable by an existential second-order formula.Galliani 2012 Therefore, on the level of open formulas, independence logic is strictly stronger in expressive power than dependence logic. However, on the level of sentences these logics are equivalent.Grädel and Väänänen

=Inclusion/exclusion logic=

Inclusion/exclusion logic extends first-order logic with inclusion atoms \vec{t_1} \subseteq \vec{t_2} and exclusion atoms \vec{t_1} \mid \vec{t_2} where in both formulas \vec{t_1} and \vec{t_2} are term tuples of the same length. The semantics of these atoms is defined as follows:

  • \mathcal A \models_X \vec{t_1} \subseteq \vec{t_2} if and only if for all s\in X there exists s'\in X such that \vec{t_1}\langle s\rangle =\vec{t_2}\langle s'\rangle ;
  • \mathcal A \models_X \vec{t_1} \mid \vec{t_2} if and only if for all s,s'\in X it holds that \vec{t_1}\langle s\rangle \neq \vec{t_2}\langle s'\rangle.

Inclusion/exclusion logic has the same expressive power as independence logic, already on the level of open formulas.Galliani 2012 Inclusion logic and exclusion logic are obtained by adding only inclusion atoms or exclusion atoms to first-order logic, respectively. Inclusion logic sentences correspond in expressive power to greatest fixed-point logic sentences; hence inclusion logic captures (least) fixed-point logic on finite models, and PTIME over finite ordered models.Galliani and Hella 2013 Exclusion logic in turn corresponds to dependence logic in expressive power.Galliani 2012

=Generalized quantifiers=

Another way of extending dependence logic is to add some generalized quantifiers to the language of dependence logic. Very recently there has been some study of dependence logic with monotone generalized quantifiersEngström and dependence logic with a certain majority quantifier, the latter leading to a new descriptive complexity characterization of the counting hierarchy.Durand, Ebbing, Kontinen, Vollmer 2011

See also

Notes

{{reflist|3}}

References

{{refbegin}}

  • {{wikicite |ref=refAbrVaan09 |reference=Abramsky, Samson and Väänänen, Jouko (2009), 'From IF to BI'. Synthese 167(2): 207–230.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refDurEbb11 |reference= Durand, Arnaud; Ebbing Johannes; Kontinen, Juha and Vollmer Heribert (2011), '[http://drops.dagstuhl.de/opus/volltexte/2011/3346/pdf/28.pdf Dependence logic with a majority quantifier]'. FSTTCS 2011: 252-263.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refDurKon12 |reference= Durand, Arnaud and Kontinen, Juha, '[https://www.academia.edu/18703455/Hierarchies_in_Dependence_Logic Hierarchies in Dependence Logic]'. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 2012.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refEnderton70 |reference=Enderton, Herbert B. (1970), 'Finite {{sic|hide=y|partially|-}}ordered quantifiers'. Z. Math. Logik Grundlagen Math., 16: 393–397.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refEng12 |reference= Engström, Fredrik, '[https://arxiv.org/abs/1103.0396 Generalized quantifiers in dependence logic]'. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, to appear.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refGal12 |reference= Galliani, Pietro (2012), '[https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0168007211001217/pdf?md5=13f28c1160e72f36688687744f6dc76d&pid=1-s2.0-S0168007211001217-main.pdf&_valck=1 Inclusion and Exclusion in Team Semantics - On some logics of imperfect information]'. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163(1): 68-84.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refGalHella13 |reference= Galliani, Pietro and Hella, Lauri (2013), '[http://drops.dagstuhl.de/opus/volltexte/2013/4203/pdf/23.pdf Inclusion Logic and Fixed Point Logic]'. Proceedings of Computer Science Logic 2013 (CSL 2013), Leibniz International Proceedings in Informatics (LIPIcs) 23, 281-295.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refGrVaan12 |reference= Grädel, Erich and Väänänen, Jouko, '[http://www.math.helsinki.fi/logic/people/jouko.vaananen/Graedel_Vaananen_final.pdf Dependence and independence]'. Studia Logica, to appear.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refHintikka02 |reference=Hintikka, Jaakko (2002), '[http://www.cambridge.org/gb/knowledge/isbn/item1158300/?site_locale=en_GB The Principles of Mathematics Revisited]', {{isbn|978-0-521-62498-5}}.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refHodges97 |reference=Hodges, Wilfrid (1997), '[http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.37.5740&rep=rep1&type=ps Compositional semantics for a language of imperfect information]'. Logic Journal of the IGPL 5: 539–563.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refKontNurmi09 |reference= Kontinen, Juha and Nurmi, Ville (2009), 'Team Logic and Second-Order Logic'. In [https://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-3-642-02261-6 Logic, Language, Information and Computation], pp. 230–241.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refKontVaan09 |reference= Kontinen, Juha and Väänänen, Jouko (2009), 'On definability in dependence logic'. Journal of Logic, Language and Information 18(3): 317–332.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refKontVaan09b|reference= Kontinen, Juha and Väänänen, Jouko (2009), '[http://www.ml.kva.se/preprints/files/IML-0910f-22.pdf A Remark on Negation of Dependence Logic]'. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 52(1):55-65, 2011.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refLohmVoll10 |reference= Lohmann, Peter and Vollmer, Heribert (2010), 'Complexity Results for Modal Dependence Logic'. In Lecture Notes in Computer Science, pp. 411–425.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refSevenster09|reference= Sevenster, Merlijn (2009), '[https://ieeexplore.ieee.org/abstract/document/8133055/ Model-theoretic and Computational Properties of Modal Dependence Logic]'. Journal of Logic and Computation 19(6): 1157–1173.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refVaananen07 |reference=Väänänen, Jouko (2007), '[https://web.archive.org/web/20150822235254/http://www.cambridge.org/uk/catalogue/catalogue.asp?isbn=9780521876599 Dependence Logic -- A New Approach to Independence Friendly Logic]', {{isbn|978-0-521-87659-9}}.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refVaananen08 | reference= Väänänen, Jouko (2008), '[http://www.math.helsinki.fi/logic/people/jouko.vaananen/modaldependencelogic.pdf Modal dependence logic]'. New Perspectives in Logic and Interaction, pp. 237–254.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refWalkoe70 | reference= Walkoe, Wilbur J. (1970), [https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/journal-of-symbolic-logic/article/finite-partiallyordered-quantification/115E0CF95F881AF1B95A9D72DE54D6FF 'Finite {{sic|hide=y|partially|-}}ordered quantification]'. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 35: 535–575.}}
  • {{wikicite |ref=refYang10 | reference= Yang, Fan (2010), 'Expressing Second-order Sentences in Intuitionistic Dependence Logic'. Dependence and Independence in Logic proceedings, pp. 118–132.}}

{{refend}}