Dubins–Spanier theorems

{{Short description|Measure theory theorems}}

The Dubins–Spanier theorems are several theorems in the theory of fair cake-cutting. They were published by Lester Dubins and Edwin Spanier in 1961.{{Cite journal | doi = 10.2307/2311357| jstor = 2311357| title = How to Cut a Cake Fairly| journal = The American Mathematical Monthly| volume = 68| pages = 1–17| year = 1961| last1 = Dubins | first1 = Lester Eli| author2-link = Edwin Spanier| last2 = Spanier | first2 = Edwin Henry| issue = 1| author1-link = Lester Dubins}} Although the original motivation for these theorems is fair division, they are in fact general theorems in measure theory.

Setting

There is a set U, and a set \mathbb{U} which is a sigma-algebra of subsets of U.

There are n partners. Every partner i has a personal value measure V_i: \mathbb{U} \to \mathbb{R}. This function determines how much each subset of U is worth to that partner.

Let X a partition of U to k measurable sets: U = X_1 \sqcup \cdots \sqcup X_k. Define the matrix M_X as the following n\times k matrix:

:M_X[i,j] = V_i(X_j)

This matrix contains the valuations of all players to all pieces of the partition.

Let \mathbb{M} be the collection of all such matrices (for the same value measures, the same k, and different partitions):

:\mathbb{M} = \{M_X \mid X\text{ is a }k\text{-partition of } U\}

The Dubins–Spanier theorems deal with the topological properties of \mathbb{M}.

Statements

If all value measures V_i are countably-additive and nonatomic, then:

This was already proved by Dvoretzky, Wald, and Wolfowitz.{{Cite journal|doi=10.2140/pjm.1951.1.59|title=Relations among certain ranges of vector measures|journal=Pacific Journal of Mathematics|volume=1|pages=59–74|year=1951|last1=Dvoretzky|first1=A.|last2=Wald|first2=A.|last3=Wolfowitz|first3=J.|doi-access=free}}

Corollaries

= Consensus partition =

A cake partition X to k pieces is called a consensus partition with weights w_1, w_2, \ldots, w_k (also called exact division) if:

:\forall i \in \{1,\dots, n\}: \forall j \in \{1,\dots, k\}: V_i(X_j) = w_j

I.e, there is a consensus among all partners that the value of piece j is exactly w_j.

Suppose, from now on, that w_1, w_2, \ldots, w_k are weights whose sum is 1:

:\sum_{j=1}^k w_j =1

and the value measures are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1:

:\forall i \in \{1,\dots, n\}: V_i(U) = 1

The convexity part of the DS theorem implies that:{{rp|5}}

:::If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

:::then a consensus partition exists.

PROOF: For every j \in \{1,\dots, k\}, define a partition X^j as follows:

:X^j_j = U

:\forall r\neq j: X^j_r = \emptyset

In the partition X^j, all partners value the j-th piece as 1 and all other pieces as 0. Hence, in the matrix M_{X^j}, there are ones on the j-th column and zeros everywhere else.

By convexity, there is a partition X such that:

:M_X = \sum_{j=1}^k w_j\cdot M_{X^j}

In that matrix, the j-th column contains only the value w_j. This means that, in the partition X, all partners value the j-th piece as exactly w_j.

Note: this corollary confirms a previous assertion by Hugo Steinhaus. It also gives an affirmative answer to the problem of the Nile provided that there are only a finite number of flood heights.

= Super-proportional division =

A cake partition X to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called a super-proportional division with weights w_1, w_2, ..., w_n if:

:\forall i \in 1\dots n: V_i(X_i) > w_i

I.e, the piece allotted to partner i is strictly more valuable for him than what he deserves. The following statement is Dubins-Spanier Theorem on the existence of super-proportional division {{rp|6}}

{{math_theorem

|With these notations, let w_1, w_2, ..., w_n be weights whose sum is 1, assume that the point w:=(w_1, w_2, ..., w_n) is an interior point of the (n-1)-dimensional simplex with coordinates pairwise different, and assume that the value measures V_1, ..., V_n are normalized such that each partner values the entire cake as exactly 1 (i.e. they are non-atomic probability measures). If at least two of the measures V_i, V_j are not equal ( V_i\neq V_j ), then super-proportional divisions exist.}}

The hypothesis that the value measures V_1, ..., V_n are not identical is necessary. Otherwise, the sum \sum_{i=1}^n V_i(X_i) =\sum_{i=1}^n V_1(X_i) > \sum_{i=1}^n w_i =1 leads to a contradiction.

Namely, if all value measures are countably-additive and non-atomic, and if there are two partners i,j such that V_i\neq V_j,

then a super-proportional division exists.I.e, the necessary condition is also sufficient.

Sketch of Proof

Suppose w.l.o.g. that V_1 \neq V_2. Then there is some piece of the cake, Z\subseteq U, such that V_1(Z)>V_2(Z). Let \overline{Z} be the complement of Z; then V_2(\overline{Z})>V_1(\overline{Z}). This means that V_1(Z) + V_2(\overline{Z}) > 1. However, w_1+w_2\leq 1. Hence, either V_1(Z)>w_1 or V_2(\overline{Z})>w_2. Suppose w.l.o.g. that V_1(Z)>V_2(Z) and V_1(Z)>w_1 are true.

Define the following partitions:

  • X^1: the partition that gives Z to partner 1, \overline{Z} to partner 2, and nothing to all others.
  • X^i (for i\geq 2): the partition that gives the entire cake to partner i and nothing to all others.

Here, we are interested only in the diagonals of the matrices M_{X^j}, which represent the valuations of the partners to their own pieces:

  • In \textrm{diag}(M_{X^1}), entry 1 is V_1(Z), entry 2 is V_2(\overline{Z}), and the other entries are 0.
  • In \textrm{diag}(M_{X^i}) (for i\geq 2), entry i is 1 and the other entires are 0.

By convexity, for every set of weights z_1, z_2, ..., z_n there is a partition X such that:

:M_X = \sum_{j=1}^n {z_j\cdot M_{X^j}}.

It is possible to select the weights z_i such that, in the diagonal of M_X, the entries are in the same ratios as the weights w_i. Since we assumed that V_1(Z)>w_1, it is possible to prove that \forall i \in 1\dots n: V_i(X_i) > w_i, so X is a super-proportional division.

= Utilitarian-optimal division =

A cake partition X to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called utilitarian-optimal if it maximizes the sum of values. I.e, it maximizes:

:\sum_{i=1}^n{V_i(X_i)}

Utilitarian-optimal divisions do not always exist. For example, suppose U is the set of positive integers. There are two partners. Both value the entire set U as 1. Partner 1 assigns a positive value to every integer and partner 2 assigns zero value to every finite subset. From a utilitarian point of view, it is best to give partner 1 a large finite subset and give the remainder to partner 2. When the set given to partner 1 becomes larger and larger, the sum-of-values becomes closer and closer to 2, but it never approaches 2. So there is no utilitarian-optimal division.

The problem with the above example is that the value measure of partner 2 is finitely-additive but not countably-additive.

The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:{{rp|7}}

:::If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

:::then a utilitarian-optimal division exists.

In this special case, non-atomicity is not required: if all value measures are countably-additive, then a utilitarian-optimal partition exists.{{rp|7}}

= Leximin-optimal division =

A cake partition X to n pieces (one piece per partner) is called leximin-optimal with weights w_1, w_2, ..., w_n if it maximizes the lexicographically-ordered vector of relative values. I.e, it maximizes the following vector:

:{V_1(X_1) \over w_1}, {V_2(X_2) \over w_2}, \dots , {V_n(X_n) \over w_n}

where the partners are indexed such that:

:{V_1(X_1) \over w_1} \leq {V_2(X_2) \over w_2} \leq \dots \leq {V_n(X_n) \over w_n}

A leximin-optimal partition maximizes the value of the poorest partner (relative to his weight); subject to that, it maximizes the value of the next-poorest partner (relative to his weight); etc.

The compactness part of the DS theorem immediately implies that:{{rp|8}}

:::If all value measures are countably-additive and nonatomic,

:::then a leximin-optimal division exists.

Further developments

  • The leximin-optimality criterion, introduced by Dubins and Spanier, has been studied extensively later. In particular, in the problem of cake-cutting, it was studied by Marco Dall'Aglio.{{Cite journal|doi=10.1016/S0377-0427(99)00393-3|title=The Dubins–Spanier optimization problem in fair division theory|journal=Journal of Computational and Applied Mathematics|volume=130|pages=17–40|year=2001|last1=Dall'Aglio|first1=Marco|issue=1–2|bibcode=2001JCoAM.130...17D|doi-access=free}}

See also

References

{{reflist}}

{{DEFAULTSORT:Dubins-Spanier theorems}}

Category:Fair division

Category:Theorems in measure theory