Filters in topology#Convergent filter
{{very long|date=November 2022}}
{{Short description|Use of filters to describe and characterize all basic topological notions and results.}}
File:Filter vs ultrafilter.svg colored dark green. It is a {{em|filter}}, and even a {{em|principal filter}}. It is not an {{em|ultrafilter}}, as it can be extended to the larger proper filter by including also the light green elements. Because cannot be extended any further, it is an ultrafilter.]]
In topology, filters can be used to study topological spaces and define basic topological notions such as convergence, continuity, compactness, and more. Filters, which are special families of subsets of some given set, also provide a common framework for defining various types of limits of functions such as limits from the left/right, to infinity, to a point or a set, and many others. Special types of filters called {{em|ultrafilters}} have many useful technical properties and they may often be used in place of arbitrary filters.
Filters have generalizations called {{em|prefilters}} (also known as {{em|filter bases}}) and {{em|filter subbases}}, all of which appear naturally and repeatedly throughout topology. Examples include neighborhood filters/bases/subbases and uniformities. Every filter is a prefilter and both are filter subbases. Every prefilter and filter subbase is contained in a unique smallest filter, which they are said to {{em|generate}}. This establishes a relationship between filters and prefilters that may often be exploited to allow one to use whichever of these two notions is more technically convenient. There is a certain preorder on families of sets (subordination), denoted by that helps to determine exactly when and how one notion (filter, prefilter, etc.) can or cannot be used in place of another. This preorder's importance is amplified by the fact that it also defines the notion of filter convergence, where by definition, a filter (or prefilter) {{em|converges}} to a point if and only if where is that point's neighborhood filter. Consequently, subordination also plays an important role in many concepts that are related to convergence, such as cluster points and limits of functions. In addition, the relation which denotes and is expressed by saying that {{em|is subordinate to}} also establishes a relationship in which is to as a subsequence is to a sequence (that is, the relation which is called {{em|subordination}}, is for filters the analog of "is a subsequence of").
Filters were introduced by Henri Cartan in 1937{{sfn|Cartan|1937a|p=}} and subsequently used by Bourbaki in their book {{em|Topologie Générale}} as an alternative to the similar notion of a net developed in 1922 by E. H. Moore and H. L. Smith.
Filters can also be used to characterize the notions of sequence and net convergence. But unlikeSequences and nets in a space are maps from directed sets like the natural numbers, which in general maybe entirely unrelated to the set and so they, and consequently also their notions of convergence, are not intrinsic to sequence and net convergence, filter convergence is defined {{em|entirely}} in terms of subsets of the topological space and so it provides a notion of convergence that is completely intrinsic to the topological space; indeed, the category of topological spaces can be equivalently defined entirely in terms of filters. Every net induces a canonical filter and dually, every filter induces a canonical net, where this induced net (resp. induced filter) converges to a point if and only if the same is true of the original filter (resp. net). This characterization also holds for many other definitions such as cluster points. These relationships make it possible to switch between filters and nets, and they often also allow one to choose whichever of these two notions (filter or net) is more convenient for the problem at hand.
However, assuming that "subnet" is defined using either of its most popular definitions (which are those given by Willard and by Kelley), then in general, this relationship does {{em|not}} extend to subordinate filters and subnets because as detailed below, there exist subordinate filters whose filter/subordinate-filter relationship cannot be described in terms of the corresponding net/subnet relationship; this issue can however be resolved by using a less commonly encountered definition of "subnet", which is that of an AA-subnet.
Thus filters/prefilters and this single preorder provide a framework that seamlessly ties together fundamental topological concepts such as topological spaces (via neighborhood filters), neighborhood bases, convergence, various limits of functions, continuity, compactness, sequences (via sequential filters), the filter equivalent of "subsequence" (subordination), uniform spaces, and more; concepts that otherwise seem relatively disparate and whose relationships are less clear.
{{TOCLimit}}
Motivation
Archetypical example of a filter
{{See also|Filter (set theory)}}
The archetypical example of a filter is the Neighbourhood filter at a point in a topological space which is the family of sets consisting of all neighborhoods of
By definition, a neighborhood of some given point is any subset whose topological interior contains this point; that is, such that Importantly, neighborhoods are {{em|not}} required to be open sets; those are called {{em|open neighborhoods}}.
Listed below are those fundamental properties of neighborhood filters that ultimately became the definition of a "filter."
A {{em|filter on }} is a set of subsets of that satisfies all of the following conditions:
- {{em|Not empty}}: – just as since is always a neighborhood of (and of anything else that it contains);
- {{em|Does not contain the empty set}}: – just as no neighborhood of is empty;
- {{em|Closed under finite intersections}}: If – just as the intersection of any two neighborhoods of is again a neighborhood of ;
- {{em|Upward closed}}: If then – just as any subset of that includes a neighborhood of will necessarily {{em|be}} a neighborhood of (this follows from and the definition of "a neighborhood of ").
Generalizing sequence convergence by using sets − determining sequence convergence without the sequence
{{See also|Limit of a sequence|Net (mathematics)}}
A {{em|sequence in }} is by definition a map from the natural numbers into the space
The original notion of convergence in a topological space was that of a sequence converging to some given point in a space, such as a metric space.
With metrizable spaces (or more generally first-countable spaces or Fréchet–Urysohn spaces), sequences usually suffices to characterize, or "describe", most topological properties, such as the closures of subsets or continuity of functions.
But there are many spaces where sequences can {{em|not}} be used to describe even basic topological properties like closure or continuity.
This failure of sequences was the motivation for defining notions such as nets and filters, which {{em|never}} fail to characterize topological properties.
Nets directly generalize the notion of a sequence since nets are, by definition, maps from an arbitrary directed set into the space A sequence is just a net whose domain is with the natural ordering. Nets have their own notion of convergence, which is a direct generalization of sequence convergence.
Filters generalize sequence convergence in a different way by considering {{em|only}} the values of a sequence.
To see how this is done, consider a sequence which is by definition just a function whose value at is denoted by rather than by the usual parentheses notation that is commonly used for arbitrary functions.
Knowing only the image (sometimes called "the range") of the sequence is not enough to characterize its convergence; multiple sets are needed.
It turns out that the needed sets are the following,Technically, any infinite subfamily of this set of tails is enough to characterize this sequence's convergence. But in general, unless indicated otherwise, the set of {{em|all}} tails is taken unless there is some reason to do otherwise. which are called the {{em|tails}} of the sequence :
x_{\geq 1} =\; &\{&&x_1, &&x_2, &&x_3, &&x_4, &&\ldots&& \,\} \\[0.3ex]
x_{\geq 2} =\; &\{&&x_2, &&x_3, &&x_4, &&x_5, &&\ldots&& \,\} \\[0.3ex]
x_{\geq 3} =\; &\{&&x_3, &&x_4, &&x_5, &&x_6, &&\ldots&& \,\} \\[0.3ex]
& && && &&\;\,\vdots && && && \\[0.3ex]
x_{\geq n} =\; &\{&&x_n, \;\;\,&&x_{n+1}, \;&&x_{n+2}, \;&&x_{n+3},&&\ldots&& \,\} \\[0.3ex]
& && && &&\;\,\vdots && && && \\[0.3ex]
\end{alignat}
These sets completely determine this sequence's convergence (or non-convergence) because given any point, this sequence converges to it if and only if for every neighborhood (of this point), there is some integer such that contains all of the points This can be reworded as:
{{in5}}every neighborhood must contain some set of the form as a subset.
Or more briefly: every neighborhood must contain some tail as a subset.
It is this characterization that can be used with the above family of tails to determine convergence (or non-convergence) of the sequence
Specifically, with the family of {{em|sets}} in hand, the {{em|function}} is no longer needed to determine convergence of this sequence (no matter what topology is placed on ).
By generalizing this observation, the notion of "convergence" can be extended from sequences/functions to families of sets.
The above set of tails of a sequence is in general not a filter but it does "{{em|generate}}" a filter via taking its {{em|upward closure}} (which consists of all supersets of all tails). The same is true of other important families of sets such as any neighborhood basis at a given point, which in general is also not a filter but does generate a filter via its upward closure (in particular, it generates the neighborhood filter at that point). The properties that these families share led to the notion of a {{em|filter base}}, also called a {{em|prefilter}}, which by definition is any family having the minimal properties necessary and sufficient for it to generate a filter via taking its upward closure.
Nets versus filters − advantages and disadvantages
Filters and nets each have their own advantages and drawbacks and there's no reason to use one notion exclusively over the other.Indeed, net convergence is defined using neighborhood filters while (pre)filters are directed sets with respect to so it is difficult to keep these notions completely separate.
Depending on what is being proved, a proof may be made significantly easier by using one of these notions instead of the other.{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|p=44}} Both filters and nets can be used to completely characterize any given topology.
Nets are direct generalizations of sequences and can often be used similarly to sequences, so the learning curve for nets is typically much less steep than that for filters.
However, filters, and especially ultrafilters, have many more uses outside of topology, such as in set theory, mathematical logic, model theory (ultraproducts, for example), abstract algebra,{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=155-171}} combinatorics,{{cite journal|last=Fernández-Bretón|first=David J.|title=Using Ultrafilters to Prove Ramsey-type Theorems|journal=The American Mathematical Monthly|publisher=Informa UK Limited|volume=129|issue=2|date=2021-12-22|issn=0002-9890|doi=10.1080/00029890.2022.2004848|pages=116–131|arxiv=1711.01304|s2cid=231592954 }} dynamics, order theory, generalized convergence spaces, Cauchy spaces, and in the definition and use of hyperreal numbers.
Like sequences, nets are {{em|functions}} and so they have the {{em|advantages of functions}}.
For example, like sequences, nets can be "plugged into" other functions, where "plugging in" is just function composition.
Theorems related to functions and function composition may then be applied to nets.
One example is the universal property of inverse limits, which is defined in terms of composition of functions rather than sets and it is more readily applied to functions like nets than to sets like filters (a prominent example of an inverse limit is the Cartesian product).
Filters may be awkward to use in certain situations, such as when switching between a filter on a space and a filter on a dense subspace {{sfn|Howes|1995|pp=83-92}}
In contrast to nets, filters (and prefilters) are families of {{em|sets}} and so they have the {{em|advantages of sets}}.
For example, if is surjective then the {{em|image}} under of an arbitrary filter or prefilter is both easily defined and guaranteed to be a prefilter on 's domain, whereas it is less clear how to pullback (unambiguously/without choice) an arbitrary sequence (or net) so as to obtain a sequence or net in the domain (unless is also injective and consequently a bijection, which is a stringent requirement). Similarly, the intersection of any collection of filters is once again a filter whereas it is not clear what this could mean for sequences or nets.
Because filters are composed of subsets of the very topological space that is under consideration, topological set operations (such as closure or interior) may be applied to the sets that constitute the filter.
Taking the closure of all the sets in a filter is sometimes useful in functional analysis for instance.
Theorems and results about images or preimages of sets under a function may also be applied to the sets that constitute a filter; an example of such a result might be one of continuity's characterizations in terms of preimages of open/closed sets or in terms of the interior/closure operators.
Special types of filters called {{em|ultrafilters}} have many useful properties that can significantly help in proving results.
One downside of nets is their dependence on the directed sets that constitute their domains, which in general may be entirely unrelated to the space In fact, the class of nets in a given set is too large to even be a set (it is a proper class); this is because nets in can have domains of {{em|any}} cardinality.
In contrast, the collection of all filters (and of all prefilters) on is a set whose cardinality is no larger than that of
Similar to a topology on a filter on is "intrinsic to " in the sense that both structures consist {{em|entirely}} of subsets of and neither definition requires any set that cannot be constructed from (such as or other directed sets, which sequences and nets require).
Preliminaries, notation, and basic notions
{{Main|Filter (set theory)}}
In this article, upper case Roman letters like and denote sets (but not families unless indicated otherwise) and will denote the power set of A subset of a power set is called {{em|a family of sets}} (or simply, {{em|a family}}) where it is {{em|over }} if it is a subset of Families of sets will be denoted by upper case calligraphy letters such as , , and .
Whenever these assumptions are needed, then it should be assumed that is non-empty and that etc. are families of sets over
The terms "prefilter" and "filter base" are synonyms and will be used interchangeably.
Warning about competing definitions and notation
There are unfortunately several terms in the theory of filters that are defined differently by different authors.
These include some of the most important terms such as "filter."
While different definitions of the same term usually have significant overlap, due to the very technical nature of filters (and point–set topology), these differences in definitions nevertheless often have important consequences.
When reading mathematical literature, it is recommended that readers check how the terminology related to filters is defined by the author.
For this reason, this article will clearly state all definitions as they are used.
Unfortunately, not all notation related to filters is well established and some notation varies greatly across the literature (for example, the notation for the set of all prefilters on a set) so in such cases this article uses whatever notation is most self describing or easily remembered.
The theory of filters and prefilters is well developed and has a plethora of definitions and notations, many of which are now unceremoniously listed to prevent this article from becoming prolix and to allow for the easy look up of notation and definitions.
Their important properties are described later.
Sets operations
The {{em|Upward closed set}} or {{em|isotonization}} in {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27–29}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}} of a family of sets is
{{Quote frame|1=
}}
and similarly the {{em|downward closure}} of is
class="wikitable" style="width: 100%;"
|+ | |
Notation and Definition | Name |
---|---|
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Kernel}} of {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}} |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Dual of }} where is a set.{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Trace of }}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} or {{em|the restriction of }} where is a set; sometimes denoted by |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"|{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} | {{em|Elementwise}} ({{em|set}}) {{em|intersection}} ( will denote the usual intersection) |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"|{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} | {{em|Elementwise}} ({{em|set}}) {{em|union}} ( will denote the usual union) |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Elementwise}} ({{em|set}}) {{em|subtraction}} ( will denote the usual set subtraction) |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Power set}} of a set {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}} |
{{Quote box|align=center|1=For any two families declare that if and only if for every there exists some in which case it is said that is {{em|coarser than}} and that is {{em|finer than}} (or {{em|subordinate to}}) {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=58}}{{sfn|Schubert|1968|pp=48–71}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=3–4}} The notation may also be used in place of
If and then are said to be {{em|{{visible anchor|equivalent families|equivalent|text=equivalent}}}} (with respect to subordination).
Two families {{em|mesh}},{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} written if
}}
Throughout, is a map.
class="wikitable" style="width: 100%;"
|+ | |
Notation and Definition | Name |
---|---|
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"|{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–221}} | {{em|Image}} of or the {{em|preimage}} of under |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"|{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=215}} | {{em|Image}} of under |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Image}} (or range) of |
Topology notation
Denote the set of all topologies on a set
Suppose is any subset, and is any point.
class="wikitable" style="width: 100%;"
|+ | |
Notation and Definition | Name |
---|---|
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Set}} or {{em|prefilter}}The terms "Filter base" and "Filter" are used if and only if {{em|of open neighborhoods}} of |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Set}} or {{em|prefilter}} {{em|of open neighborhoods}} of |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Set}} or {{em|filter}} {{em|of neighborhoods}} of |
style="padding:0.5% 0 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Set}} or {{em|filter of neighborhoods}} of |
If then
{{anchor|Definition of nets|Definition of tails}}
Nets and their tails
A {{em|directed set}} is a set together with a preorder, which will be denoted by (unless explicitly indicated otherwise), that makes into an ({{em|upward}}) {{em|directed set}};{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|p=5}} this means that for all there exists some such that For any indices the notation is defined to mean while is defined to mean that holds but it is {{em|not}} true that (if is antisymmetric then this is equivalent to ).
A {{em|net in }}{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|p=5}} is a map from a non-empty directed set into
The notation will be used to denote a net with domain
class="wikitable" style="width: 100%;"
|+ | |
Notation and Definition | Name |
---|---|
style="padding:0.5% 2em 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Tail}} or {{em|section of starting at }} where is a directed set. |
style="padding:0.5% 2em 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|{{visible anchor|Tail of a net|text=Tail}}}} or {{em|section of starting at }} |
style="padding:0.5% 2em 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Set}} or {{em|{{visible anchor|prefilter of tails}}}}/{{em|sections}} of Also called the {{em|eventuality filter base}} generated by (the tails of) If is a sequence then is also called the {{em|{{visible anchor|sequential filter base|Sequential filter base}}}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|p=10}} or {{em|{{visible anchor|elementary prefilter}}}}.{{Citation|last1=Castillo|first1=Jesus M. F.|last2=Montalvo|first2=Francisco|title=A Counterexample in Semimetric Spaces|journal=Extracta Mathematicae|volume=5|issue=1|pages=38–40|date=January 1990|url=https://dialnet.unirioja.es/descarga/articulo/118277.pdf}} |
style="padding:0.5% 2em 0.5% 2em;"| | {{anchor|Filter of tails|Eventuality filter}}({{em|Eventuality}}) {{em|filter}} of/generated by (tails of) {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|p=10}} |
style="padding:0.5% 2em 0.5% 2em;"| | {{em|Tail}} or {{em|section of a net starting at }}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|p=10}} where is a directed set. |
Warning about using strict comparison
If is a net and then it is possible for the set which is called {{em|the tail of {{em|after}} }}, to be empty (for example, this happens if is an upper bound of the directed set ).
In this case, the family would contain the empty set, which would prevent it from being a prefilter (defined later).
This is the (important) reason for defining as rather than or even and it is for this reason that in general, when dealing with the prefilter of tails of a net, the strict inequality may not be used interchangeably with the inequality
=Filters and prefilters=
{{Families of sets}}
{{Main|Filter (set theory)}}
The following is a list of properties that a family of sets may possess and they form the defining properties of filters, prefilters, and filter subbases. Whenever it is necessary, it should be assumed that
{{Quote frame|1=The family of sets is:
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Proper|Proper filter}}}} or {{em|{{visible anchor|nondegenerate|Nondegenerate filter}}}} if Otherwise, if then it is called {{em|improper}}{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100–130}} or {{em|degenerate}}.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Directed downward}}}}{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|p=5}} if whenever then there exists some such that
- This property can be characterized in terms of directedness, which explains the word "directed": A binary relation on is called {{em|(upward) directed}} if for any two there is some satisfying Using in place of gives the definition of {{em|directed downward}} whereas using instead gives the definition of {{em|directed upward}}. Explicitly, is {{em|directed downward}} (resp. {{em|directed upward}}) if and only if for all there exists some "greater" such that (resp. such that ) − where the "greater" element is always on the right hand side, − which can be rewritten as (resp. as ).
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Closed under finite intersections}}}} (resp. {{em|unions}}) if the intersection (resp. union) of any two elements of is an element of
- If is closed under finite intersections then is necessarily directed downward. The converse is generally false.
- {{em|Upward closed set}} or {{em|Isotone}} in {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27–29}} if or equivalently, if whenever and some set satisfies Similarly, is {{em|downward closed}} if An upward (respectively, downward) closed set is also called an {{em|upper set}} or {{em|upset}} (resp. a {{em|lower set}} or {{em|down set}}).
- The family which is the upward closure of is the unique {{em|smallest}} (with respect to ) isotone family of sets over having as a subset.
}}
Many of the properties of defined above and below, such as "proper" and "directed downward," do not depend on so mentioning the set is optional when using such terms. Definitions involving being "upward closed in " such as that of "filter on " do depend on so the set should be mentioned if it is not clear from context.
{{Quote frame|1=A family is/is a(n):
- {{em|Ideal (set theory)}}{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100–130}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=82-91}} if is downward closed and closed under finite unions.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Dual ideal}}}} on {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–213}} if is upward closed in and also closed under finite intersections. Equivalently, is a dual ideal if for all {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
- Explanation of the word "dual": A family is a dual ideal (resp. an ideal) on if and only if the {{anchor|Dual of a family}}{{em|dual of }} which is the family is an ideal (resp. a dual ideal) on In other words, {{em|dual ideal}} means "{{em|dual of an ideal}}". The dual of the dual is the original family, meaning {{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100–130}}
- {{em|Filter (set theory)}} on {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–213}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} if is a proper dual ideal on That is, a filter on is a non−empty subset of that is closed under finite intersections and upward closed in Equivalently, it is a prefilter that is upward closed in In words, a filter on is a family of sets over that (1) is not empty (or equivalently, it contains ), (2) is closed under finite intersections, (3) is upward closed in and (4) does not have the empty set as an element.
- {{em|Warning}}: Some authors, particularly algebrists, use "filter" to mean a dual ideal; others, particularly topologists, use "filter" to mean a {{em|proper}}/{{em|non-degenerate}} dual ideal.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|p=100}} It is recommended that readers always check how "filter" is defined when reading mathematical literature. However, the definitions of "ultrafilter," "prefilter," and "filter subbase" always require non-degeneracy. This article uses Henri Cartan's original definition of "filter",{{sfn|Cartan|1937a|p=}}{{sfn|Cartan|1937b|p=}} which required non-degeneracy.
- The power set is the one and only dual ideal on that is not also a filter. Excluding from the definition of "filter" in topology has the same benefit as excluding from the definition of "prime number": it obviates the need to specify "non-degenerate" (the analog of "non-unital" or "non-") in many important results, thereby making their statements less awkward.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Prefilter}}}} or {{em|filter base}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65, 82-91}} if is proper and directed downward. Equivalently, is called a prefilter if its upward closure is a filter. It can also be defined as any family that is equivalent to {{em|some}} filter.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} A proper family is a prefilter if and only if {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} A family is a prefilter if and only if the same is true of its upward closure.
- If is a prefilter then its upward closure is the unique smallest (relative to ) filter on containing and it is called {{em|the filter generated by}} A filter is said to be {{em|generated by}} a prefilter if in which is called a {{em|filter base for }}
- Unlike a filter, a prefilter is {{em|not}} necessarily closed under finite intersections.
- {{em|{{pi}}-system}} if is closed under finite intersections. Every non-empty family is contained in a unique smallest {{pi}}-system called {{em|the {{pi}}-system generated by}} which is sometimes denoted by It is equal to the intersection of all {{pi}}-systems containing and also to the set of all possible finite intersections of sets from {{nowrap|:}}
- A {{pi}}-system is a prefilter if and only if it is proper. Every filter is a proper {{pi}}-system and every proper {{pi}}-system is a prefilter but the converses do not hold in general.
- A prefilter is equivalent to the {{pi}}-system generated by it and both of these families generate the same filter on
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Filter subbase}}}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}{{sfn|Arkhangel'skii|Ponomarev|1984|pp=7–8}} and {{em|centered}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} if and satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- has the {{em|finite intersection property}}, which means that the intersection of any finite family of (one or more) sets in is not empty; explicitly, this means that whenever then
- The {{pi}}-system generated by is proper; that is,
- The {{pi}}-system generated by is a prefilter.
- is a subset of {{em|some}} prefilter.
- is a subset of {{em|some}} filter.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=58}}
- Assume that is a filter subbase. Then there is a unique smallest (relative to ) filter containing called the {{em|{{visible anchor|filter generated by}} }}, and is said to {{em|be a filter subbase for}} this filter. This filter is equal to the intersection of all filters on that are supersets of The {{pi}}-system generated by denoted by will be a prefilter and a subset of Moreover, the filter generated by is equal to the upward closure of meaning {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} However, if {{em|and only if}} is a prefilter (although is always an upward closed filter {{em|sub}}base for ).
- A {{hsp}}-smallest (meaning smallest relative to {{hsp}}) {{em|pre}}filter containing a filter subbase will exist only under certain circumstances. It exists, for example, if the filter subbase happens to also be a prefilter. It also exists if the filter (or equivalently, the {{pi}}-system) generated by is principal, in which case is the unique smallest prefilter containing Otherwise, in general, a {{hsp}}-smallest {{em|pre}}filter containing might not exist. For this reason, some authors may refer to the {{pi}}-system generated by as {{em|{{visible anchor|the prefilter generated by|Prefilter generated by a filter subbase}} }} However, if a {{hsp}}-smallest prefilter does exist (say it is denoted by ) then contrary to usual expectations, it is {{em|not}} necessarily equal to "the prefilter generated by " (that is, is possible). And if the filter subbase happens to also be a prefilter but not a {{pi}}-system then unfortunately, "the prefilter generated by this prefilter" (meaning ) will not be (that is, is possible even when is a prefilter), which is why this article will prefer the accurate and unambiguous terminology of "the {{pi}}-system generated by ".
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Subfilter}}}} of a filter and that is a {{em|{{visible anchor|superfilter}}}} of {{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100–130}}{{sfn|Joshi|1983|p=244}} if is a filter and where for filters,
- Importantly, the expression "is a {{em|super}}filter of" is for filters the analog of "is a {{em|sub}}sequence of". So despite having the prefix "sub" in common, "is a {{em|sub}}filter of" is actually the {{em|reverse}} of "is a {{em|sub}}sequence of." However, can also be written which is described by saying " is subordinate to " With this terminology, "is {{em|sub}}ordinate to" becomes for filters (and also for prefilters) the analog of "is a {{em|sub}}sequence of,"{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=212}} which makes this one situation where using the term "subordinate" and symbol may be helpful.
}}
There are no prefilters on (nor are there any nets valued in ), which is why this article, like most authors, will automatically assume without comment that whenever this assumption is needed.
==Basic examples==
Named examples
- The singleton set is called the {{em|indiscrete}} or {{em|{{visible anchor|trivial filter}} on }}{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|pp=44–46}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}} It is the unique {{em|minimal}} filter on because it is a subset of every filter on ; however, it need not be a subset of every prefilter on
- The dual ideal is also called {{em|the degenerate filter on }}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}} (despite not actually being a filter). It is the only dual ideal on that is not a filter on
- If is a topological space and then the neighborhood filter at is a filter on By definition, a family is called a {{em|neighborhood basis}} (resp. a {{em|neighborhood subbase}}) at if and only if is a prefilter (resp. is a filter subbase) and the filter on that generates is equal to the neighborhood filter The subfamily of open neighborhoods is a filter base for Both prefilters also form a bases for topologies on with the topology generated being coarser than This example immediately generalizes from neighborhoods of points to neighborhoods of non-empty subsets
- is an {{em|{{visible anchor|elementary prefilter}}}}{{Citation|last1=Castillo|first1=Jesus M. F.|last2=Montalvo|first2=Francisco|title=A Counterexample in Semimetric Spaces|journal=Extracta Mathematicae|volume=5|issue=1|pages=38–40|date=January 1990|url=https://dialnet.unirioja.es/descarga/articulo/118277.pdf}} if for some sequence of points
- is an {{em|{{visible anchor|elementary filter}}}} or a {{em|{{visible anchor|sequential filter}}}} on {{sfn|Schaefer|Wolff|1999|pp=1–11}} if is a filter on generated by some elementary prefilter. The filter of tails generated by a sequence that is not eventually constant is necessarily {{em|not}} an ultrafilter.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=129–133}} Every principal filter on a countable set is sequential as is every cofinite filter on a countably infinite set.{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}} The intersection of finitely many sequential filters is again sequential.{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
- The set of all cofinite subsets of (meaning those sets whose complement in is finite) is proper if and only if is infinite (or equivalently, is infinite), in which case is a filter on known as the Fréchet filter on {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}{{sfn|Wilansky|2013|pp=44–46}} If is finite then is equal to the dual ideal which is not a filter. If is infinite then the family of complements of singleton sets is a filter subbase that generates the Fréchet filter on As with any family of sets over that contains the kernel of the Fréchet filter on is the empty set:
- The intersection of all elements in any non-empty family is itself a filter on called the {{em|infimum}} or {{em|greatest lower bound}} of which is why it may be denoted by Said differently, Because every filter on has as a subset, this intersection is never empty. By definition, the infimum is the finest/largest (relative to ) filter contained as a subset of each member of {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
- If are filters then their infimum in is the filter {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} If are prefilters then is a prefilter that is coarser than both (that is, ); indeed, it is one of the finest such prefilters, meaning that if is a prefilter such that then necessarily {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} More generally, if are non−empty families and if then and is a greatest element of {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
The {{em|supremum}} or {{em|least upper bound}} of denoted by is the smallest (relative to ) dual ideal on containing every element of as a subset; that is, it is the smallest (relative to ) dual ideal on containing as a subset.
This dual ideal is where is the {{pi}}-system generated by
As with any non-empty family of sets, is contained in {{em|some}} filter on if and only if it is a filter subbase, or equivalently, if and only if is a filter on in which case this family is the smallest (relative to ) filter on containing every element of as a subset and necessarily
The {{em|supremum}} or {{em|least upper bound}} of denoted by if it exists, is by definition the smallest (relative to ) filter on containing every element of as a subset.
If it exists then necessarily {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}} (as defined above) and will also be equal to the intersection of all filters on containing
This supremum of exists if and only if the dual ideal is a filter on
The least upper bound of a family of filters may fail to be a filter.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}} Indeed, if contains at least two distinct elements then there exist filters for which there does {{em|not}} exist a filter that contains both
If is not a filter subbase then the supremum of does not exist and the same is true of its supremum in but their supremum in the set of all dual ideals on will exist (it being the degenerate filter ).{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
- If are prefilters (resp. filters on ) then is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if it is non-degenerate (or said differently, if and only if mesh), in which case it is {{em|one of the}} coarsest prefilters (resp. {{em|the}} coarsest filter) on that is finer (with respect to ) than both this means that if is any prefilter (resp. any filter) such that then necessarily {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}} in which case it is denoted by {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
Other examples
- Let and let which makes a prefilter and a filter subbase that is not closed under finite intersections. Because is a prefilter, the smallest prefilter containing is The {{pi}}-system generated by is In particular, the smallest prefilter containing the filter subbase is {{em|not}} equal to the set of all finite intersections of sets in The filter on generated by is All three of the {{pi}}-system generates, and are examples of fixed, principal, ultra prefilters that are principal at the point is also an ultrafilter on
- Let be a topological space, and define where is necessarily finer than {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}} If is non-empty (resp. non-degenerate, a filter subbase, a prefilter, closed under finite unions) then the same is true of If is a filter on then is a prefilter but not necessarily a filter on although is a filter on equivalent to
- The set of all dense open subsets of a (non-empty) topological space is a proper {{pi}}-system and so also a prefilter. If the space is a Baire space, then the set of all countable intersections of dense open subsets is a {{pi}}-system and a prefilter that is finer than If (with ) then the set of all such that has finite Lebesgue measure is a proper {{pi}}-system and a free prefilter that is also a proper subset of The prefilters and are equivalent and so generate the same filter on
Since is a Baire space, every countable intersection of sets in is dense in (and also comeagre and non-meager) so the set of all countable intersections of elements of is a prefilter and {{pi}}-system; it is also finer than, and not equivalent to,
==Ultrafilters==
{{Main|Ultrafilter (set theory)|Ultrafilter}}
There are many other characterizations of "ultrafilter" and "ultra prefilter," which are listed in the article on ultrafilters. Important properties of ultrafilters are also described in that article.
{{Quote frame|1=A non-empty family of sets is/is an:
- {{em|Ultra}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=219–221}} if and any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
- For every set there exists some set such that (or equivalently, such that ).
- For every set there exists some set such that
- This characterization of " is ultra" does not depend on the set so mentioning the set is optional when using the term "ultra."
- For {{em|every}} set (not necessarily even a subset of ) there exists some set such that
- {{em|Ultra prefilter}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=219–221}} if it is a prefilter that is also ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra. A prefilter is ultra if and only if it satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is {{em|maximal}} in with respect to which means that
-
- Although this statement is identical to that given below for ultrafilters, here is merely assumed to be a prefilter; it need not be a filter.
- is ultra (and thus an ultrafilter).
- is equivalent to some ultrafilter.
- A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter. A filter subbase is ultra if and only if it is a maximal filter subbase with respect to (as above).{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100-130}}
- {{em|Ultrafilter on }}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=219–221}} if it is a filter on that is ultra. Equivalently, an ultrafilter on is a filter that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is generated by an ultra prefilter.
- For any {{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=100–130}}
- This condition can be restated as: is partitioned by and its dual
- For any if then (a filter with this property is called a {{em|prime filter}}).
- This property extends to any finite union of two or more sets.
- is a {{em|maximal}} filter on ; meaning that if is a filter on such that then necessarily (this equality may be replaced by ).
- If is upward closed then So this characterization of ultrafilters as maximal filters can be restated as:
- Because subordination is for filters the analog of "is a subnet/subsequence of" (specifically, "subnet" should mean "AA-subnet," which is defined below), this characterization of an ultrafilter as being a "maximally subordinate filter" suggests that an ultrafilter can be interpreted as being analogous to some sort of "maximally deep net" (which could, for instance, mean that "when viewed only from " in some sense, it is indistinguishable from its subnets, as is the case with any net valued in a singleton set for example),For instance, one sense in which a net could be interpreted as being "maximally deep" is if all important properties related to (such as convergence for example) of any subnet is completely determined by in all topologies on In this case and its subnet become effectively indistinguishable (at least topologically) if one's information about them is limited to only that which can be described in solely in terms of and directly related sets (such as its subsets). which is an idea that is actually made rigorous by ultranets. The ultrafilter lemma is then the statement that every filter ("net") has some subordinate filter ("subnet") that is "maximally subordinate" ("maximally deep").
}}
The ultrafilter lemma
The following important theorem is due to Alfred Tarski (1930).{{sfn|Jech|2006|pp=73-89}}
{{Math theorem|name=The ultrafilter lemma/principle/theorem{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}|note=Tarski|math_statement=Every filter on a set is a subset of some ultrafilter on
}}
A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
Assuming the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel (ZF), the ultrafilter lemma follows from the Axiom of choice (in particular from Zorn's lemma) but is strictly weaker than it. The ultrafilter lemma implies the Axiom of choice for finite sets. If {{em|only}} dealing with Hausdorff spaces, then most basic results (as encountered in introductory courses) in Topology (such as Tychonoff's theorem for compact Hausdorff spaces and the Alexander subbase theorem) and in functional analysis (such as the Hahn–Banach theorem) can be proven using only the ultrafilter lemma; the full strength of the axiom of choice might not be needed.
==Kernels==
The kernel is useful in classifying properties of prefilters and other families of sets.
{{Quote frame|1=The {{em|kernel}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27–29}} of a family of sets is the intersection of all sets that are elements of
}}
If then and this set is also equal to the kernel of the {{pi}}-system that is generated by
In particular, if is a filter subbase then the kernels of all of the following sets are equal:
:(1) (2) the {{pi}}-system generated by and (3) the filter generated by
If is a map then
Equivalent families have equal kernels.
Two principal families are equivalent if and only if their kernels are equal.
===Classifying families by their kernels===
{{Quote frame|1=A family of sets is:
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Free}}}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}} if or equivalently, if this can be restated as
- A filter is free if and only if is infinite and includes the Fréchet filter on as a subset.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Fixed}}}} if in which case, is said to be {{em|fixed by}} any point
- Any fixed family is necessarily a filter subbase.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Principal}}}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}} if
- A proper principal family of sets is necessarily a prefilter.
- {{em|{{visible anchor|Discrete}}}} or {{em|Principal at}} {{sfn|Wilansky|2013|pp=44–46}} if
- The {{em|principal filter at }} is the filter A filter is principal at if and only if
- {{em|Countably deep}} if whenever is a countable subset then {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
}}
If is a principal filter on then and
and is also the smallest prefilter that generates
Family of examples: For any non-empty the family is free but it is a filter subbase if and only if no finite union of the form covers in which case the filter that it generates will also be free. In particular, is a filter subbase if is countable (for example, the primes), a meager set in a set of finite measure, or a bounded subset of If is a singleton set then is a subbase for the Fréchet filter on
===Characterizing fixed ultra prefilters===
If a family of sets is fixed (that is, ) then is ultra if and only if some element of is a singleton set, in which case will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter is ultra if and only if is a singleton set.
Every filter on that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on other than these.{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=33–35}}
The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point.
{{math theorem|name=Proposition|math_statement=If is an ultrafilter on then the following are equivalent:
- is fixed, or equivalently, not free, meaning
- is principal, meaning
- Some element of is a finite set.
- Some element of is a singleton set.
- is principal at some point of which means for some
- does {{em|not}} contain the Fréchet filter on
- is sequential.{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
}}
{{anchor|Comparison of families|Comparison of families of sets|Subordination}}
=Finer/coarser, subordination, and meshing=
The preorder that is defined below is of fundamental importance for the use of prefilters (and filters) in topology. For instance, this preorder is used to define the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence",{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=212}} where "" can be interpreted as " is a subsequence of " (so "subordinate to" is the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence of"). It is also used to define prefilter convergence in a topological space.
The definition of meshes with which is closely related to the preorder is used in topology to define cluster points.
Two families of sets {{em|{{visible anchor|mesh}}}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} and are {{em|compatible}}, indicated by writing if If do not mesh then they are {{em|dissociated}}. If then are said to {{em|mesh}} if mesh, or equivalently, if the {{em|{{visible anchor|trace|Trace on a set}}}} of which is the family
does not contain the empty set, where the trace is also called the {{em|{{visible anchor|restriction|Restriction to a set}}}} of
{{Quote frame|1=Declare that stated as is {{em|coarser than}} and is {{em|finer than}} (or {{em|subordinate to}}) {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}{{sfn|Schubert|1968|pp=48–71}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=3–4}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}} if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- Definition: Every {{em|includes}} some Explicitly, this means that for every there is some such that (thus holds).
- Said more briefly in plain English, if every set in is {{em|larger}} than some set in Here, a "larger set" means a superset.
-
- In words, states exactly that is larger than some set in The equivalence of (a) and (b) follows immediately.
- which is equivalent to ;
- ;
- which is equivalent to ;
and if in addition is upward closed, which means that then this list can be extended to include:
- {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27–29}}
- So in this case, this definition of " is {{em|finer}} than " would be identical to the topological definition of "finer" had been topologies on
If an upward closed family is finer than (that is, ) but then is said to be {{em|strictly finer}} than and is {{em|strictly coarser}} than
Two families are {{em|comparable}} if one of them is finer than the other.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
}}
Example: If is a subsequence of then is subordinate to in symbols: and also
Stated in plain English, the prefilter of tails of a subsequence is always subordinate to that of the original sequence.
To see this, let be arbitrary (or equivalently, let be arbitrary) and it remains to show that this set contains some
For the set to contain it is sufficient to have
Since are strictly increasing integers, there exists such that and so holds, as desired.
Consequently,
The left hand side will be a {{em|strict/proper}} subset of the right hand side if (for instance) every point of is unique (that is, when is injective) and is the even-indexed subsequence because under these conditions, every tail (for every ) of the subsequence will belong to the right hand side filter but not to the left hand side filter.
For another example, if is any family then always holds and furthermore,
A non-empty family that is coarser than a filter subbase must itself be a filter subbase.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
Every filter subbase is coarser than both the {{pi}}-system that it generates and the filter that it generates.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
If are families such that the family is ultra, and then is necessarily ultra. It follows that any family that is equivalent to an ultra family will necessarily {{em|be}} ultra. In particular, if is a prefilter then either both and the filter it generates are ultra or neither one is ultra.
The relation is reflexive and transitive, which makes it into a preorder on {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65, 82-91, 102-120}}
The relation is antisymmetric but if has more than one point then it is {{em|not}} symmetric.
==Equivalent families of sets==
The preorder induces its canonical equivalence relation on where for all is {{em|equivalent}} to if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27–29}}
- The upward closures of are equal.
Two upward closed (in ) subsets of are equivalent if and only if they are equal.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
If then necessarily and is equivalent to
Every equivalence class other than contains a unique representative (that is, element of the equivalence class) that is upward closed in {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
Properties preserved between equivalent families
Let be arbitrary and let be any family of sets. If are equivalent (which implies that ) then for each of the statements/properties listed below, either it is true of {{em|both}} or else it is false of {{em|both}} :{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65, 82-91, 102-120}}
- Not empty
- Proper (that is, is not an element)
- Moreover, any two degenerate families are necessarily equivalent.
- Filter subbase
- Prefilter
- In which case generate the same filter on (that is, their upward closures in are equal).
- Free
- Principal
- Ultra
- Is equal to the trivial filter
- In words, this means that the only subset of that is equivalent to the trivial filter {{em|is}} the trivial filter. In general, this conclusion of equality does not extend to non−trivial filters (one exception is when both families are filters).
- Meshes with
- Is finer than
- Is coarser than
- Is equivalent to
Missing from the above list is the word "filter" because this property is {{em|not}} preserved by equivalence.
However, if are filters on then they are equivalent if and only if they are equal; this characterization does {{em|not}} extend to prefilters.
Equivalence of prefilters and filter subbases
If is a prefilter on then the following families are always equivalent to each other:
- ;
- the {{pi}}-system generated by ;
- the filter on generated by ;
and moreover, these three families all generate the same filter on (that is, the upward closures in of these families are equal).
In particular, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates.
By transitivity, two prefilters are equivalent if and only if they generate the same filter.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
Every prefilter is equivalent to exactly one filter on which is the filter that it generates (that is, the prefilter's upward closure).
Said differently, every equivalence class of prefilters contains exactly one representative that is a filter.
In this way, filters can be considered as just being distinguished elements of these equivalence classes of prefilters.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=53-65}}
A filter subbase that is {{em|not}} also a prefilter can{{em|not}} be equivalent to the prefilter (or filter) that it generates.
In contrast, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates.
This is why prefilters can, by and large, be used interchangeably with the filters that they generate while filter subbases cannot.
Set theoretic properties and constructions relevant to topology
{{See also|Filter (set theory)}}
=Trace and meshing=
If is a prefilter (resp. filter) on then the trace of which is the family is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if mesh (that is, {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}), in which case the trace of is said to be {{em|induced by }}.
The trace is always finer than the original family; that is,
If is ultra and if mesh then the trace is ultra.
If is an ultrafilter on then the trace of is a filter on if and only if
For example, suppose that is a filter on is such that Then mesh and generates a filter on that is strictly finer than {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
When prefilters mesh
Given non-empty families the family
satisfies and
If is proper (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase) then this is also true of both
In order to make any meaningful deductions about from needs to be proper (that is, which is the motivation for the definition of "mesh".
In this case, is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase) if and only if this is true of both
Said differently, if are prefilters then they mesh if and only if is a prefilter.
Generalizing gives a well known characterization of "mesh" entirely in terms of subordination (that is, ):
{{in5}}Two prefilters (resp. filter subbases) mesh if and only if there exists a prefilter (resp. filter subbase) such that and
If the least upper bound of two filters exists in then this least upper bound is equal to {{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=31–32}}
=Images and preimages under functions=
{{See also|List of set identities and relations|Algebra of sets}}
Throughout, will be maps between non-empty sets.
Images of prefilters
Let Many of the properties that may have are preserved under images of maps; notable exceptions include being upward closed, being closed under finite intersections, and being a filter, which are not necessarily preserved.
Explicitly, if one of the following properties is true of then it will necessarily also be true of (although possibly not on the codomain unless is surjective):{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–221}}{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=37–39}}{{sfn|Arkhangel'skii|Ponomarev|1984|pp=20–22}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}{{sfn|Jech|2006|pp=73-89}}
ultra, ultrafilter, filter, prefilter, filter subbase, dual ideal, upward closed, proper/non-degenerate, ideal, closed under finite unions, downward closed, directed upward.
Moreover, if is a prefilter then so are both {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
The image under a map of an ultra set is again ultra and if is an ultra prefilter then so is
If is a filter then is a filter on the range but it is a filter on the codomain if and only if is surjective.{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=37–39}}
Otherwise it is just a prefilter on and its upward closure must be taken in to obtain a filter.
The upward closure of is
where if is upward closed in (that is, a filter) then this simplifies to:
If then taking to be the inclusion map shows that any prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on is also a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
Preimages of prefilters
Let
Under the assumption that is surjective:
{{in5}} is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, {{pi}}-system, closed under finite unions, proper) if and only if this is true of
However, if is an ultrafilter on then even if is surjective (which would make a prefilter), it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter to be neither ultra nor a filter on {{hsp}}{{sfn|Arkhangel'skii|Ponomarev|1984|pp=20–22}}
If is not surjective then denote the trace of by where in this case particular case the trace satisfies:
and consequently also:
This last equality and the fact that the trace is a family of sets over means that to draw conclusions about the trace can be used in place of and the {{em|surjection}} can be used in place of
For example:{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–221}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
{{in5}} is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, {{pi}}-system, proper) if and only if this is true of
In this way, the case where is not (necessarily) surjective can be reduced down to the case of a surjective function (which is a case that was described at the start of this subsection).
Even if is an ultrafilter on if is not surjective then it is nevertheless possible that which would make degenerate as well. The next characterization shows that degeneracy is the only obstacle. If is a prefilter then the following are equivalent:{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–221}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
- is a prefilter;
- is a prefilter;
- ;
- meshes with
and moreover, if is a prefilter then so is {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–221}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
If and if denotes the inclusion map then the trace of is equal to {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}} This observation allows the results in this subsection to be applied to investigating the trace on a set.
==Subordination is preserved by images and preimages==
The relation is preserved under both images and preimages of families of sets.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
This means that for {{em|any}} families {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
Moreover, the following relations always hold for {{em|any}} family of sets :{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
where equality will hold if is surjective.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
Furthermore,
If then{{sfn|Dolecki|Mynard|2016|pp=27-54}}
and {{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}} where equality will hold if is injective.{{sfn|Császár|1978|pp=102-120}}
=Products of prefilters=
Suppose is a family of one or more non-empty sets, whose product will be denoted by and for every index let
denote the canonical projection.
Let be non−empty families, also indexed by such that for each
The {{em|product}} of the families {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}} is defined identically to how the basic open subsets of the product topology are defined (had all of these been topologies). That is, both the notations
denote the family of all cylinder subsets such that for all but finitely many and where for any one of these finitely many exceptions (that is, for any such that necessarily ).
When every is a filter subbase then the family is a filter subbase for the filter on generated by {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
If is a filter subbase then the filter on that it generates is called the {{em|filter generated by }}.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
If every is a prefilter on then will be a prefilter on and moreover, this prefilter is equal to the coarsest prefilter such that
for every {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
However, may fail to be a filter on even if every is a filter on {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=57–68}}
Convergence, limits, and cluster points
Throughout, is a topological space.
Prefilters vs. filters
With respect to maps and subsets, the property of being a prefilter is in general more well behaved and better preserved than the property of being a filter. For instance, the image of a prefilter under some map is again a prefilter; but the image of a filter under a non-surjective map is {{em|never}} a filter on the codomain, although it will be a prefilter. The situation is the same with preimages under non-injective maps (even if the map is surjective). If is a proper subset then any filter on will not be a filter on although it will be a prefilter.
One advantage that filters have is that they are distinguished representatives of their equivalence class (relative to ), meaning that any equivalence class of prefilters contains a unique filter. This property may be useful when dealing with equivalence classes of prefilters (for instance, they are useful in the construction of completions of uniform spaces via Cauchy filters). The many properties that characterize ultrafilters are also often useful. They are used to, for example, construct the Stone–Čech compactification. The use of ultrafilters generally requires that the ultrafilter lemma be assumed. But in the many fields where the axiom of choice (or the Hahn–Banach theorem) is assumed, the ultrafilter lemma necessarily holds and does not require an addition assumption.
A note on intuition
Suppose that is a non-principal filter on an infinite set has one "upward" property (that of being closed upward) and one "downward" property (that of being directed downward).
Starting with any there always exists some that is a {{em|proper}} subset of ; this may be continued ad infinitum to get a sequence of sets in with each being a {{em|proper}} subset of The same is {{em|not}} true going "upward", for if then there is no set in that contains as a proper subset.
Thus when it comes to limiting behavior (which is a topic central to the field of topology), going "upward" leads to a dead end, while going "downward" is typically fruitful. So to gain understanding and intuition about how filters (and prefilter) relate to concepts in topology, the "downward" property is usually the one to concentrate on. This is also why so many topological properties can be described by using only prefilters, rather than requiring filters (which only differ from prefilters in that they are also upward closed).
The "upward" property of filters is less important for topological intuition but it is sometimes useful to have for technical reasons. For example, with respect to every filter subbase is contained in a unique smallest filter but there may not exist a unique smallest prefilter containing it.
=Limits and convergence=
{{in5}}A family is said to {{em|{{visible anchor|Convergent filter|Convergent prefilter|Convergent family|text=converge}} in }} to a point of {{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} if Explicitly, means that every neighborhood contains some as a subset (that is, ); thus the following then holds: In words, a family converges to a point or subset if and only if it is {{em|finer}} than the neighborhood filter at
A family converging to a point may be indicated by writing {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}} and saying that is a {{em|{{visible anchor|Limit of a filter|Limit of a prefilter|Limit of a family|Limit|Limit point|text=limit}}}} of if this limit is a point (and not a subset), then is also called a {{em|{{visible anchor|Limit point of a filter|Limit point of a prefilter|Limit point of a family|text=limit point}}}}.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68-83}}
As usual, is defined to mean that and is the {{em|only}} limit point of that is, if also {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}} (If the notation "" did not also require that the limit point be unique then the equals sign {{=}} would no longer be guaranteed to be transitive).
The set of all limit points of is denoted by {{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
In the above definitions, it suffices to check that is finer than some (or equivalently, finer than every) neighborhood base in of the point (for example, such as or when ).
Examples
If is Euclidean space and denotes the Euclidean norm (which is the distance from the origin, defined as usual), then all of the following families converge to the origin:
- the prefilter of all open balls centered at the origin, where
- the prefilter of all closed balls centered at the origin, where This prefilter is equivalent to the one above.
- the prefilter where is a union of spheres centered at the origin having progressively smaller radii. This family consists of the sets as ranges over the positive integers.
- any of the families above but with the radius ranging over (or over any other positive decreasing sequence) instead of over all positive reals.
- * Drawing or imagining any one of these sequences of sets when has dimension suggests that intuitively, these sets "should" converge to the origin (and indeed they do). This is the intuition that the above definition of a "convergent prefilter" make rigorous.
Although was assumed to be the Euclidean norm, the example above remains valid for any other norm on
The one and only limit point in of the free prefilter is since every open ball around the origin contains some open interval of this form.
The fixed prefilter does not converges in to any {{em|point}} and so although does converge to the {{em|set}} since
However, not every fixed prefilter converges to its kernel. For instance, the fixed prefilter also has kernel but does not converges (in ) to it.
The free prefilter of intervals does not converge (in ) to any point.
The same is also true of the prefilter because it is equivalent to and equivalent families have the same limits.
In fact, if is any prefilter in any topological space then for every
More generally, because the only neighborhood of is itself (that is, ), every non-empty family (including every filter subbase) converges to
For any point its neighborhood filter always converges to More generally, any neighborhood basis at converges to
A point is always a limit point of the principle ultra prefilter and of the ultrafilter that it generates.
The empty family does not converge to any point.
Basic properties
If converges to a point then the same is true of any family finer than
This has many important consequences.
One consequence is that the limit points of a family are the same as the limit points of its upward closure:
In particular, the limit points of a prefilter are the same as the limit points of the filter that it generates.
Another consequence is that if a family converges to a point then the same is true of the family's trace/restriction to any given subset of
If is a prefilter and then converges to a point of if and only if this is true of the trace {{sfn|Dixmier|1984|pp=13–18}}
If a filter subbase converges to a point then so do the filter and the {{pi}}-system that it generates, although the converse is not guaranteed. For example, the filter subbase does not converge to in although the filter that it generates—which is equal to the principal filter generated by —does.
Given the following are equivalent for a prefilter
- converges to
- converges to
- There exists a family equivalent to that converges to
Because subordination is transitive, if and moreover, for every both and the maximal/ultrafilter converge to Thus every topological space induces a canonical convergence defined by
At the other extreme, the neighborhood filter is the smallest (that is, coarsest) filter on that converges to that is, any filter converging to must contain as a subset. Said differently, the family of filters that converge to consists exactly of those filter on that contain as a subset.
Consequently, the finer the topology on then the {{em|fewer}} prefilters exist that have any limit points in
=Cluster points=
A family is said to {{em|cluster at}} a point of if it meshes with the neighborhood filter of that is, if Explicitly, this means that and every neighborhood of
In particular, a point is a {{em|{{visible anchor|Cluster point of a filter|Cluster point of a prefilter|Cluster point of a family|Cluster point|text=cluster point}}}} or an {{em|{{visible anchor|Accumulation point of a filter|Accumulation point of a prefilter|Accumulation point of a family|Accumulation point|text=accumulation point}}}} of a family {{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} if meshes with the neighborhood filter at The set of all cluster points of is denoted by where the subscript may be dropped if not needed.
In the above definitions, it suffices to check that meshes with some (or equivalently, meshes with every) neighborhood base in of
When is a prefilter then the definition of " mesh" can be characterized entirely in terms of the subordination preorder
Two equivalent families of sets have the exact same limit points and also the same cluster points. No matter the topology, for every both and the principal ultrafilter cluster at
If clusters to a point then the same is true of any family coarser than Consequently, the cluster points of a family are the same as the cluster points of its upward closure:
In particular, the cluster points of a prefilter are the same as the cluster points of the filter that it generates.
Given the following are equivalent for a prefilter :
- clusters at
- The family generated by clusters at
- There exists a family equivalent to that clusters at
- {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=69}}
- for every neighborhood of
- If is a filter on then for every neighborhood
- There exists a prefilter subordinate to (that is, ) that converges to
- This is the filter equivalent of " is a cluster point of a sequence if and only if there exists a subsequence converging to
- In particular, if is a cluster point of a prefilter then is a prefilter subordinate to that converges to
The set of all cluster points of a prefilter satisfies
Consequently, the set of all cluster points of {{em|any}} prefilter is a closed subset of {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} This also justifies the notation for the set of cluster points.{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
In particular, if is non-empty (so that is a prefilter) then since both sides are equal to
=Properties and relationships=
Just like sequences and nets, it is possible for a prefilter on a topological space of infinite cardinality to not have {{em|any}} cluster points or limit points.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}
If is a limit point of then is necessarily a limit point of any family {{em|finer}} than (that is, if then ).{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}
In contrast, if is a cluster point of then is necessarily a cluster point of any family {{em|coarser}} than (that is, if mesh and then mesh).
Equivalent families and subordination
Any two equivalent families can be used {{em|interchangeably}} in the definitions of "limit of" and "cluster at" because their equivalency guarantees that if and only if and also that if and only if
In essence, the preorder is incapable of distinguishing between equivalent families.
Given two prefilters, whether or not they mesh can be characterized entirely in terms of subordination.
Thus the two most fundamental concepts related to (pre)filters to Topology (that is, limit and cluster points) can both be defined {{em|entirely}} in terms of the subordination relation. This is why the preorder is of such great importance in applying (pre)filters to Topology.
Limit and cluster point relationships and sufficient conditions
Every limit point of a non-degenerate family is also a cluster point; in symbols:
This is because if is a limit point of then mesh,{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–213}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}} which makes a cluster point of {{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}} But in general, a cluster point need not be a limit point. For instance, every point in any given non-empty subset is a cluster point of the principle prefilter (no matter what topology is on ) but if is Hausdorff and has more than one point then this prefilter has no limit points; the same is true of the filter that this prefilter generates.
However, every cluster point of an {{em|ultra}} prefilter is a limit point. Consequently, the limit points of an {{em|ultra}} prefilter are the same as its cluster points: that is to say, a given point is a cluster point of an ultra prefilter if and only if converges to that point.{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=219–221}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=70}}
Although a cluster point of a filter need not be a limit point, there will always exist a finer filter that does converge to it; in particular, if clusters at then is a filter subbase whose generated filter converges to
If is a filter subbase such that then In particular, any limit point of a filter subbase subordinate to is necessarily also a cluster point of
If is a cluster point of a prefilter then is a prefilter subordinate to that converges to
If and if is a prefilter on then every cluster point of belongs to and any point in is a limit point of a filter on {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}
Primitive sets
A subset is called {{em|{{visible anchor|Primitive set|text=primitive}}}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}} if it is the set of limit points of some ultrafilter (or equivalently, some ultra prefilter). That is, if there exists an ultrafilter such that is equal to which recall denotes the set of limit points of Since limit points are the same as cluster points for ultra prefilters, a subset is primitive if and only if it is equal to the set of cluster points of some ultra prefilter
For example, every closed singleton subset is primitive.{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}} The image of a primitive subset of under a continuous map is contained in a primitive subset of {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
Assume that are two primitive subset of
If is an open subset of that intersects then for any ultrafilter such that {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
In addition, if are distinct then there exists some and some ultrafilters such that and {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
Other results
{{See also|Limit superior and limit inferior#Definition for filter bases}}
If is a complete lattice then:{{citation needed|date=November 2020}}
- The limit inferior of is the infimum of the set of all cluster points of
- The limit superior of is the supremum of the set of all cluster points of
- is a convergent prefilter if and only if its limit inferior and limit superior agree; in this case, the value on which they agree is the limit of the prefilter.
{{anchor|Limits of functions|Limit points of functions}}
=Limits of functions defined as limits of prefilters=
{{anchor|Limit of a function|Limit point of a function}}
{{anchor|Limit of a function with respect to a filter|Limit point of a function with respect to a filter}}
{{anchor|Cluster point of a function|Cluster points of functions}}
{{See also|Limit of a function|One-sided limit}}
Suppose is a map from a set into a topological space and If is a limit point (respectively, a cluster point) of then is called a {{em|limit point}} or {{em|limit}} (respectively, a {{em|cluster point}}) {{em|of with respect to }}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}
Explicitly, is a limit of with respect to if and only if which can be written as (by definition of this notation) and stated as {{em|tend to along }}{{sfn|Dixmier|1984|pp=14–17}} If the limit is unique then the arrow may be replaced with an equals sign {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}} The neighborhood filter can be replaced with any family equivalent to it and the same is true of
The definition of a convergent net is a special case of the above definition of a limit of a function.
Specifically, if is a net then
where the left hand side states that is a Convergent net while the right hand side states that is a limit {{em|of the function}} with respect to (as just defined above).
The table below shows how various types of limits encountered in analysis and topology can be defined in terms of the convergence of images (under ) of particular prefilters on the domain
This shows that prefilters provide a general framework into which many of the various definitions of limits fit.{{sfn|Dixmier|1984|pp=13–18}}
The limits in the left-most column are defined in their usual way with their obvious definitions.
Throughout, let be a map between topological spaces,
If is Hausdorff then all arrows {{nowrap|""}} in the table may be replaced with equal signs {{nowrap|""}} and {{nowrap|1=""}} may be replaced with {{nowrap|1="".}}{{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}}
class="wikitable" style="text-align:center;"
|+ | |||
Type of limit | {{nowarp|if and only if}} | Definition in terms of prefilters{{sfn|Dixmier|1984|pp=13–18}} | Assumptions |
---|---|---|---|
style=''|
|⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | is a sequence in | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| | for a double-ended sequence | |||
| |⇔ |style='text-align:left;'| |style="padding-left:2em; padding-right:2em;"| a seminormed space; {{nowrap|1=for example, a Banach space}} |
By defining different prefilters, many other notions of limits can be defined; for example,
Divergence to infinity
Divergence of a real-valued function to infinity can be defined/characterized by using the prefilters
where along if and only if and similarly, along if and only if The family can be replaced by any family equivalent to it, such as for instance (in real analysis, this would correspond to replacing the strict inequality {{nowrap|""}} in the definition with {{nowrap|""),}} and the same is true of and
So for example, if then if and only if holds. Similarly, if and only if or equivalently, if and only if
More generally, if is valued in (or some other seminormed vector space) and if then if and only if holds, where
Filters and nets{{anchor|Nets and filters}}
{{See also|Filter (set theory)#Filters and nets}}
This section will describe the relationships between prefilters and nets in great detail because of how important these details are applying filters to topology − particularly in switching from utilizing nets to utilizing filters and vice verse.
=Nets to prefilters=
In the definitions below, the first statement is the standard definition of a limit point of a net (respectively, a cluster point of a net) and it is gradually reworded until the corresponding filter concept is reached.
{{Quote frame|1=A net is said to {{anchor|Convergent net}}{{em|converge in}} to a point written and is called a {{em|limit}} or {{em|limit point}} of {{sfn|Kelley|1975|pp=65–72}} if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- Definition: For every there exists some such that if
- For every there exists some such that the tail of starting at is contained in (that is, such that ).
- For every there exists some such that
- that is, the prefilter converges to
As usual, is defined to mean that and is the {{em|only}} limit point of that is, if also {{sfn|Kelley|1975|pp=65–72}}
}}
{{Quote frame|1=A point is called a {{anchor|Cluster point of a net}}{{em|cluster}} or {{em|accumulation point}} of a net if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- Definition: For every and every there exists some such that
- For every and every the tail of starting at intersects (that is, ).
- For every and every
- mesh (by definition of "mesh").
- is a cluster point of
}}
If is a map and is a net in then {{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=155-171}}
=Prefilters to nets=
A {{em|pointed set}} is a pair consisting of a non-empty set and an element
For any family let
Define a canonical preorder on pointed sets by declaring
There is a canonical map defined by
If then the tail of the assignment starting at is
Although is not, in general, a partially ordered set, it is a directed set if (and only if) is a prefilter.
So the most immediate choice for the definition of "the net in induced by a prefilter " is the assignment from into
{{Quote frame|1=If is a prefilter on then the {{em|net associated with }} is the map
\operatorname{Net}_{\mathcal{B}} :\;&& (\operatorname{PointedSets}(\mathcal{B}), \leq) &&\,\to \;& X \\
&& (B, b) &&\,\mapsto\;& b \\
\end{alignat}
that is,
}}
If is a prefilter on is a net in and the prefilter associated with is ; that is:The set equality holds more generally: if the family of sets then the family of tails of the map (defined by ) is equal to
This would not necessarily be true had been defined on a proper subset of
If is a net in then it is {{em|not}} in general true that is equal to because, for example, the domain of may be of a completely different cardinality than that of (since unlike the domain of the domain of an arbitrary net in could have {{em|any}} cardinality).
{{Math theorem|name=Proposition|math_statement=If is a prefilter on and then
- is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of
}}
{{Math proof|drop=hidden|proof=
Recall that and that if is a net in then (1) and (2) is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of
By using it follows that
It also follows that is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of
}}
Partially ordered net
The domain of the canonical net is in general not partially ordered. However, in 1955 Bruns and Schmidt discoveredBruns G., Schmidt J.,Zur Aquivalenz von Moore-Smith-Folgen und Filtern, Math. Nachr. 13 (1955), 169-186. a construction (detailed here: Filter (set theory)#Partially ordered net) that allows for the canonical net to have a domain that is both partially ordered and directed; this was independently rediscovered by Albert Wilansky in 1970.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=155-171}}
Because the tails of this partially ordered net are identical to the tails of (since both are equal to the prefilter ), there is typically nothing lost by assuming that the domain of the net associated with a prefilter is both directed {{em|and}} partially ordered.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=155-171}} If can further be assumed that the partially ordered domain is also a dense order.
=Subordinate filters and subnets=
{{anchor|Subnets}}
The notion of " is subordinate to " (written ) is for filters and prefilters what " is a subsequence of " is for sequences.{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=212}}
For example, if denotes the set of tails of and if denotes the set of tails of the subsequence (where ) then (which by definition means ) is true but is in general false.
If is a net in a topological space and if is the neighborhood filter at a point then
If is an surjective open map, and is a prefilter on that converges to then there exist a prefilter on such that and is equivalent to (that is, ).{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=220–221}}
==Subordination analogs of results involving subsequences==
{{See also|Sequential space|Fréchet–Urysohn space}}
The following results are the prefilter analogs of statements involving subsequences.{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–221}} The condition "" which is also written is the analog of " is a subsequence of " So "finer than" and "subordinate to" is the prefilter analog of "subsequence of." Some people prefer saying "subordinate to" instead of "finer than" because it is more reminiscent of "subsequence of."
{{Math theorem|name=Proposition{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–221}}{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}|math_statement=
Let be a prefilter on and let
- Suppose is a prefilter such that
- If then By definition, if and only if Since and transitivity implies
- This is the analog of "if a sequence converges to then so does every subsequence."
- If is a cluster point of then is a cluster point of
- This is the analog of "if is a cluster point of some subsequence, then is a cluster point of the original sequence."
- If then By definition, if and only if Since and transitivity implies
- if and only if for any finer prefilter there exists some even more fine prefilter such that {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=68–74}}
- This is the analog of "a sequence converges to if and only if every subsequence has a sub-subsequence that converges to "
- is a cluster point of if and only if there exists some finer prefilter such that
- This is the analog of the following {{em|false}} statement: " is a cluster point of a sequence if and only if it has a subsequence that converges to " (that is, if and only if is a subsequential limit).
- The analog for sequences is false since there is a Hausdorff topology on and a sequence in this space (both defined hereThe topology on is defined as follows: Every subset of is open in this topology and the neighborhoods of are all those subsets containing for which there exists some positive integer such that for every integer contains all but at most finitely many points of For example, the set is a neighborhood of Any diagonal enumeration of furnishes a sequence that clusters at but possess not convergent subsequence. An explicit example is the inverse of the bijective Hopcroft and Ullman pairing function which is defined by {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|p=60}}) that clusters at but that also does not have any subsequence that converges to {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–216}}
}}
==Non-equivalence of subnets and subordinate filters==
{{anchor|Subnets versus subordinate filters}}
{{See also|Net (mathematics)|Subnet (mathematics)|Filter (set theory)#Subnets versus subordinate filters}}
Subnets in the sense of Willard and subnets in the sense of Kelley are the most commonly used definitions of "subnet."{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
The first definition of a subnet ("Kelley-subnet") was introduced by John L. Kelley in 1955.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
Stephen Willard introduced in 1970 his own variant ("Willard-subnet") of Kelley's definition of subnet.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
AA-subnets were introduced independently by Smiley (1957), Aarnes and Andenaes (1972), and Murdeshwar (1983); AA-subnets were studied in great detail by Aarnes and Andenaes but they are not often used.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
A subset of a preordered space is {{em|{{visible anchor|frequent}}}} or {{em|cofinal}} in if for every there exists some such that If contains a tail of then is said to be {{em|{{visible anchor|eventual|eventually}}}} in ; explicitly, this means that there exists some such that (that is, for all satisfying ). A subset is eventual if and only if its complement is not frequent (which is termed {{em|{{visible anchor|infrequent}}}}).{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
A map between two preordered sets is {{em|Order-preserving function}} if whenever satisfy then
{{Quote frame|1=Definitions: Let be nets. Then{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
- is a {{em|{{visible anchor|Willard-subnet|Willard-subnet}}}} of or a {{em|subnet in the sense of Willard}} if there exists an order-preserving map such that is cofinal in
- is a {{em|{{visible anchor|Kelley-subnet|Kelley-subnet}}}} of or a {{em|subnet in the sense of Kelley}} if there exists a map such that and whenever is eventual in then is eventual in
- is an {{em|{{visible anchor|AA-subnet|AA-subnet}}}} of or a {{em|subnet in the sense of Aarnes and Andenaes}} if any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
- If is eventual in is eventual in
- For any subset mesh, then so do
- For any subset
}}
Kelley did not require the map to be order preserving while the definition of an AA-subnet does away entirely with any map between the two nets' domains and instead focuses entirely on − the nets' common codomain.
Every Willard-subnet is a Kelley-subnet and both are AA-subnets.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
In particular, if is a Willard-subnet or a Kelley-subnet of then
:Example: If and is a constant sequence and if and then is an AA-subnet of but it is neither a Willard-subnet nor a Kelley-subnet of
AA-subnets have a defining characterization that immediately shows that they are fully interchangeable with sub(ordinate)filters.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}{{cite web|last=Clark|first=Pete L.|title=Convergence| website=math.uga.edu/|url=http://math.uga.edu/~pete/convergence.pdf|date=18 October 2016|access-date=18 August 2020}}
Explicitly, what is meant is that the following statement is true for AA-subnets:
{{in5}}If are prefilters then if and only if is an AA-subnet of
If "AA-subnet" is replaced by "Willard-subnet" or "Kelley-subnet" then the above statement becomes {{em|false}}. In particular, as this counter-example demonstrates, the problem is that the following statement is in general false:
{{in5}}{{em|False}} statement: If are prefilters such that is a Kelley-subnet of
Since every Willard-subnet is a Kelley-subnet, this statement thus remains false if the word "Kelley-subnet" is replaced with "Willard-subnet".
If "subnet" is defined to mean Willard-subnet or Kelley-subnet then nets and filters are not completely interchangeable because there exists a filter–sub(ordinate)filter relationships that cannot be expressed in terms of a net–subnet relationship between the two induced nets. In particular, the problem is that Kelley-subnets and Willard-subnets are {{em|not}} fully interchangeable with subordinate filters. If the notion of "subnet" is not used or if "subnet" is defined to mean AA-subnet, then this ceases to be a problem and so it becomes correct to say that nets and filters are interchangeable. Despite the fact that AA-subnets do not have the problem that Willard and Kelley subnets have, they are not widely used or known about.{{sfn|Schechter|1996|pp=157–168}}
Topologies and prefilters
Throughout, is a topological space.
=Examples of relationships between filters and topologies=
Bases and prefilters
Let be a family of sets that covers and define for every The definition of a base for some topology can be immediately reworded as: is a base for some topology on if and only if is a filter base for every
If is a topology on and then the definitions of is a basis (resp. subbase) for can be reworded as:
{{in5}} is a base (resp. subbase) for if and only if for every is a filter base (resp. filter subbase) that generates the neighborhood filter of at
Neighborhood filters
The archetypical example of a filter is the set of all neighborhoods of a point in a topological space.
Any neighborhood basis of a point in (or of a subset of) a topological space is a prefilter. In fact, the definition of a neighborhood base can be equivalently restated as: "a neighborhood base is any prefilter that is equivalent the neighborhood filter."
Neighborhood bases at points are examples of prefilters that are fixed but may or may not be principal.
If has its usual topology and if then any neighborhood filter base of is fixed by (in fact, it is even true that ) but is {{em|not}} principal since
In contrast, a topological space has the discrete topology if and only if the neighborhood filter of every point is a principal filter generated by exactly one point.
This shows that a non-principal filter on an infinite set is not necessarily free.
The neighborhood filter of every point in topological space is fixed since its kernel contains (and possibly other points if, for instance, is not a T1 space). This is also true of any neighborhood basis at
For any point in a T1 space (for example, a Hausdorff space), the kernel of the neighborhood filter of is equal to the singleton set
However, it is possible for a neighborhood filter at a point to be principal but {{em|not}} discrete (that is, not principal at a {{em|single}} point).
A neighborhood basis of a point in a topological space is principal if and only if the kernel of is an open set. If in addition the space is T1 then so that this basis is principal if and only if is an open set.
Generating topologies from filters and prefilters
Suppose is not empty (and ). If is a filter on then is a topology on but the converse is in general false. This shows that in a sense, filters are {{em|almost}} topologies. Topologies of the form where is an {{em|ultra}}filter on are an even more specialized subclass of such topologies; they have the property that {{em|every}} proper subset is {{em|either}} open or closed, but (unlike the discrete topology) never both. These spaces are, in particular, examples of door spaces.
If is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, {{pi}}-system, proper) on then the same is true of both and the set of all possible unions of one or more elements of If is closed under finite intersections then the set is a topology on with both being bases for it. If the {{pi}}-system covers then both are also bases for If is a topology on then is a prefilter (or equivalently, a {{pi}}-system) if and only if it has the finite intersection property (that is, it is a filter subbase), in which case a subset will be a basis for if and only if is equivalent to in which case will be a prefilter.
=Topological properties and prefilters=
Neighborhoods and topologies
The neighborhood filter of a nonempty subset in a topological space is equal to the intersection of all neighborhood filters of all points in {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=129}}
A subset is open in if and only if whenever is a filter on and then
Suppose are topologies on
Then is finer than (that is, ) if and only if whenever is a filter on if then {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}} Consequently, if and only if for every filter and every if and only if {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}}
However, it is possible that while also for every filter converges to {{em|some}} point of if and only if converges to {{em|some}} point of {{sfn|Wilansky|2008|pp=32-35}}
Closure
If is a prefilter on a subset then every cluster point of belongs to {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=70}}
If is a non-empty subset, then the following are equivalent:
- is a limit point of a prefilter on Explicitly: there exists a prefilter such that {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–221}}
- is a limit point of a filter on {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=70}}
- There exists a prefilter such that
- The prefilter meshes with the neighborhood filter Said differently, is a cluster point of the prefilter
- The prefilter meshes with some (or equivalently, with every) filter base for (that is, with every neighborhood basis at ).
The following are equivalent:
- is a limit points of
- There exists a prefilter such that {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–221}}
Closed sets
If is not empty then the following are equivalent:
- is a closed subset of
- If is a prefilter on such that then
- If is a prefilter on such that is an accumulation points of then {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=211–221}}
- If is such that the neighborhood filter meshes with then
Hausdorffness
The following are equivalent:
- is a Hausdorff space.
- Every prefilter on converges to at most one point in {{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
- The above statement but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter, ultra prefilter, ultrafilter.{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
Compactness
As discussed in this article, the Ultrafilter Lemma is closely related to many important theorems involving compactness.
The following are equivalent:
- is a compact space.
- Every ultrafilter on converges to at least one point in {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=83}}
- That this condition implies compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma. That compactness implies this condition can be proven without the ultrafilter lemma (or even the axiom of choice).
- The above statement but with the word "ultrafilter" replaced by "ultra prefilter".{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
- For every filter there exists a filter such that and converges to some point of
- The above statement but with each instance of the word "filter" replaced by: prefilter.
- Every filter on has at least one cluster point in {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|p=83}}
- That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.
- The above statement but with the word "filter" replaced by "prefilter".{{sfn|Narici|Beckenstein|2011|pp=2–7}}
- Alexander subbase theorem: There exists a subbase such that every cover of by sets in has a finite subcover.
- That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.
If is the set of all complements of compact subsets of a given topological space then is a filter on if and only if is {{em|not}} compact.
{{Math theorem|name=Theorem{{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=83–84}}|math_statement=
If is a filter on a compact space and is the set of cluster points of then every neighborhood of belongs to
Thus a filter on a compact Hausdorff space converges if and only if it has a single cluster point.
}}
Continuity
Let be a map between topological spaces
Given the following are equivalent:
- is continuous at
- Definition: For every neighborhood of there exists some neighborhood of such that
- {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–216}}
- If is a filter on such that then
- The above statement but with the word "filter" replaced by "prefilter".
The following are equivalent:
- is continuous.
- If is a prefilter on such that then {{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=215–216}}
- If is a limit point of a prefilter then is a limit point of
- Any one of the above two statements but with the word "prefilter" replaced by "filter".
If is a prefilter on is a cluster point of is continuous, then is a cluster point in of the prefilter {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
A subset of a topological space is dense in if and only if for every the trace of the neighborhood filter along does not contain the empty set (in which case it will be a filter on ).
Suppose is a continuous map into a Hausdorff regular space and that is a dense subset of a topological space Then has a continuous extension if and only if for every the prefilter converges to some point in Furthermore, this continuous extension will be unique whenever it exists.{{sfn|Dugundji|1966|pp=216}}
Products
Suppose is a non-empty family of non-empty topological spaces and that is a family of prefilters where each is a prefilter on
Then the product of these prefilters (defined above) is a prefilter on the product space which as usual, is endowed with the product topology.
If then if and only if
Suppose are topological spaces, is a prefilter on having as a cluster point, and is a prefilter on having as a cluster point.
Then is a cluster point of in the product space {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
However, if then there exist sequences such that both of these sequences have a cluster point in but the sequence does {{em|not}} have a cluster point in {{sfn|Bourbaki|1989|pp=132–133}}
Example application: The ultrafilter lemma along with the axioms of ZF imply Tychonoff's theorem for compact Hausdorff spaces:
{{collapse top|title=Proof|left=true}}
Let be compact Hausdorff space topological spaces.
Assume that the ultrafilter lemma holds (because of the Hausdorff assumption, this proof does {{em|not}} need the full strength of the axiom of choice; the ultrafilter lemma suffices).
Let be given the product topology (which makes a Hausdorff space) and for every let denote this product's projections.
If then is compact and the proof is complete so assume
Despite the fact that because the axiom of choice is not assumed, the projection maps are not guaranteed to be surjective.
Let be an ultrafilter on and for every let denote the ultrafilter on generated by the ultra prefilter
Because is compact and Hausdorff, the ultrafilter converges to a unique limit point (because of 's uniqueness, this definition does not require the axiom of choice).
Let where satisfies for every
The characterization of convergence in the product topology that was given above implies that
Thus every ultrafilter on converges to some point of which implies that is compact (recall that this implication's proof only required the ultrafilter lemma).
{{collapse bottom}}
Examples of applications of prefilters
=Uniformities and Cauchy prefilters=
{{Main|Uniform space|Complete uniform space|Complete metric space}}
{{See also|Topological group|Complete topological vector space}}
A uniform space is a set equipped with a filter on that has certain properties. A {{em|base}} or {{em|fundamental system of entourages}} is a prefilter on whose upward closure is a uniform space.
A prefilter on a uniform space with uniformity is called a {{em|Cauchy prefilter}} if for every entourage there exists some that is {{em|-small}}, which means that
A {{em|minimal Cauchy filter}} is a minimal element (with respect to or equivalently, to ) of the set of all Cauchy filters on
Examples of minimal Cauchy filters include the neighborhood filter of any point
Every convergent filter on a uniform space is Cauchy. Moreover, every cluster point of a Cauchy filter is a limit point.
A uniform space is called {{em|complete}} (resp. {{em|sequentially complete}}) if every Cauchy prefilter (resp. every elementary Cauchy prefilter) on converges to at least one point of (replacing all instance of the word "prefilter" with "filter" results in equivalent statement).
Every compact uniform space is complete because any Cauchy filter has a cluster point (by compactness), which is necessarily also a limit point (since the filter is Cauchy).
Uniform spaces were the result of attempts to generalize notions such as "uniform continuity" and "uniform convergence" that are present in metric spaces. Every topological vector space, and more generally, every topological group can be made into a uniform space in a canonical way. Every uniformity also generates a canonical induced topology. Filters and prefilters play an important role in the theory of uniform spaces. For example, the completion of a Hausdorff uniform space (even if it is not metrizable) is typically constructed by using minimal Cauchy filters.
Nets are less ideal for this construction because their domains are extremely varied (for example, the class of all Cauchy nets is not a set); sequences cannot be used in the general case because the topology might not be metrizable, first-countable, or even sequential.
The set of all {{em|minimal Cauchy filters}} on a Hausdorff topological vector space (TVS) can made into a vector space and topologized in such a way that it becomes a completion of (with the assignment becoming a linear topological embedding that identifies as a dense vector subspace of this completion).
More generally, a Cauchy space is a pair consisting of a set together a family of (proper) filters, whose members are declared to be "{{em|Cauchy filters}}", having all of the following properties:
- For each the discrete ultrafilter at is an element of
- If is a subset of a proper filter then
- If and if each member of intersects each member of then
The set of all Cauchy filters on a uniform space forms a Cauchy space. Every Cauchy space is also a convergence space.
A map between two Cauchy spaces is called {{em|Cauchy continuous}} if the image of every Cauchy filter in is a Cauchy filter in
Unlike the category of topological spaces, the category of Cauchy spaces and Cauchy continuous maps is Cartesian closed, and contains the category of proximity spaces.
=Topologizing the set of prefilters=
{{See also|Stone space}}
Starting with nothing more than a set it is possible to topologize the set
of all filter bases on with the {{em|Stone topology}}, which is named after Marshall Harvey Stone.
To reduce confusion, this article will adhere to the following notational conventions:
- Lower case letters for elements
- Upper case letters for subsets
- Upper case calligraphy letters for subsets (or equivalently, for elements such as prefilters).
- Upper case double-struck letters for subsets
For every let
where As a side note, had the definitions of "filter" and "prefilter" not required propriety then the degenerate dual ideal would have been a prefilter on so that in particular, with These sets will be the basic open subsets of the Stone topology.
If then
From this inclusion, it is possible to deduce all of the subset inclusions displayed below with the exception of This is because the inclusion is the only one in the sequence below whose proof uses the defining assumption that
For all
where in particular, the equality shows that the family is a -system that forms a basis for a topology on called the {{em|Stone topology}}. It is henceforth assumed that carries this topology and that any subset of carries the induced subspace topology.
In contrast to most other general constructions of topologies (for example, the product, quotient, subspace topologies, etc.), this topology on was defined with{{em|out}} using anything other than the set there were {{em|no}} preexisting structures or assumptions on so this topology is completely independent of everything other than (and its subsets).
The following criteria can be used for checking for points of closure and neighborhoods.
If then:
- {{em|Closure in }}: belongs to the closure of if and only if
- {{em|Neighborhoods in }}: is a neighborhood of if and only if there exists some such that (that is, such that for all ).
It will be henceforth assumed that because otherwise and the topology is which is uninteresting.
Subspace of ultrafilters
The set of ultrafilters on (with the subspace topology) is a Stone space, meaning that it is compact, Hausdorff, and totally disconnected.
If has the discrete topology then the map defined by sending to the principal ultrafilter at is a topological embedding whose image is a dense subset of (see the article Stone–Čech compactification for more details).
Relationships between topologies on and the Stone topology on
Every induces a canonical map defined by which sends to the neighborhood filter of
If then if and only if
Thus every topology can be identified with the canonical map which allows to be canonically identified as a subset of (as a side note, it is now possible to place on and thus also on the topology of pointwise convergence on so that it now makes sense to talk about things such as sequences of topologies on converging pointwise).
For every the surjection is always continuous, closed, and open, but it is injective if and only if (that is, a Kolmogorov space).
In particular, for every topology the map is a topological embedding (said differently, every Kolmogorov space is a topological subspace of the space of prefilters).
In addition, if is a map such that (which is true of for instance), then for every the set is a neighborhood (in the subspace topology) of
See also
- {{annotated link|Characterizations of the category of topological spaces}}
- {{annotated link|Convergence space}}
- {{annotated link|Filtration (mathematics)}}
- {{annotated link|Filtration (probability theory)}}
- {{annotated link|Filtration (abstract algebra)}}
- {{annotated link|Fréchet filter}}
- {{annotated link|Generic filter}}
- {{annotated link|Ideal (set theory)}}
- {{annotated link|Stone–Čech compactification#Construction using ultrafilters}}
- {{annotated link|The fundamental theorem of ultraproducts}}
Notes
{{reflist|group=note}}
Proofs
{{reflist|group=proof}}
Citations
{{reflist}}
References
- {{Adams Franzosa Introduction to Topology Pure and Applied}}
- {{Arkhangel'skii Ponomarev Fundamentals of General Topology Problems and Exercises|edition=2}}
- {{Berberian Lectures in Functional Analysis and Operator Theory}}
- {{Bourbaki General Topology Part I Chapters 1-4}}
- {{Bourbaki General Topology Part II Chapters 5-10}}
- {{Bourbaki Topological Vector Spaces Part 1 Chapters 1–5}}
- {{cite book|last1=Burris|first1=Stanley|author-link1=Stanley Burris|last2=Sankappanavar|first2=Hanamantagouda P.|year=2012|title=A Course in Universal Algebra|publisher=Springer-Verlag|isbn=978-0-9880552-0-9|url=http://www.thoralf.uwaterloo.ca/htdocs/ualg.html|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220401154440/https://www.math.uwaterloo.ca/~snburris/htdocs/UALG/univ-algebra2012.pdf|archive-date=1 April 2022}}
- {{cite journal|last=Cartan|first=Henri|author-link=Henri Cartan|title=Théorie des filtres|title-link=|journal=Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des sciences|volume=205|year=1937a|pages=595–598|url=http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k3157c/f594.image}}
- {{cite journal|last=Cartan|first=Henri|author-link=Henri Cartan|title=Filtres et ultrafiltres|title-link=|journal=Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des séances de l'Académie des sciences|volume=205|year=1937b|pages=777–779|url=http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k3157c/f776.image}}
- {{Comfort Negrepontis The Theory of Ultrafilters 1974}}
- {{Császár General Topology}}
- {{Dixmier General Topology}}
- {{Dolecki Mynard Convergence Foundations Of Topology}}
- {{Dugundji Topology}}
- {{Dunford Schwartz Linear Operators Part 1 General Theory}}
- {{Edwards Functional Analysis Theory and Applications}}
- {{Howes Modern Analysis and Topology 1995}}
- {{Jarchow Locally Convex Spaces}}
- {{cite book|last=Jech|first=Thomas|author-link=Thomas Jech|title=Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded|publisher=Springer Science & Business Media|publication-place=Berlin New York|year=2006|isbn=978-3-540-44085-7|oclc=50422939}}
- {{Joshi Introduction to General Topology}}
- {{Kelley General Topology}}
- {{Köthe Topological Vector Spaces I}}
- {{cite web|last=MacIver R.|first=David|title=Filters in Analysis and Topology|date=1 July 2004|url=http://www.efnet-math.org/~david/mathematics/filters.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20071009170540/http://www.efnet-math.org/~david/mathematics/filters.pdf |archive-date=2007-10-09 }} (Provides an introductory review of filters in topology and in metric spaces.)
- {{Narici Beckenstein Topological Vector Spaces|edition=2}}
- {{Robertson Topological Vector Spaces}}
- {{Schaefer Wolff Topological Vector Spaces|edition=2}}
- {{Schechter Handbook of Analysis and Its Foundations}}
- {{Schubert Topology}}
- {{Trèves François Topological vector spaces, distributions and kernels}}
- {{Wilansky Modern Methods in Topological Vector Spaces|edition=1}}
- {{Wilansky Topology for Analysis 2008}}
- {{Willard General Topology}}
{{Topology}}