McKelvey–Schofield chaos theorem
{{Short description|Result in social choice theory}}{{Electoral systems sidebar|expanded=Social and collective choice}}
The McKelvey–Schofield chaos theorem is a result in social choice theory. It states that if preferences are defined over a multidimensional policy space, then choosing policies using majority rule is unstable. There will in most cases be no Condorcet winner and any policy can be enacted through a sequence of votes, regardless of the original policy. This means that adding more policies and changing the order of votes ("agenda manipulation") can be used to arbitrarily pick the winner.
Versions of the theorem have been proved for different types of preferences, with different classes of exceptions. A version of the theorem was first proved by Richard McKelvey in 1976, for preferences based on Euclidean distances in . Another version of the theorem was proved by Norman Schofield in 1978, for differentiable preferences.
The theorem can be thought of as showing that Arrow's impossibility theorem holds when preferences are restricted to be concave in . The median voter theorem shows that when preferences are restricted to be single-peaked on the real line, Arrow's theorem does not hold, and the median voter's ideal point is a Condorcet winner. The chaos theorem shows that this good news does not continue in multiple dimensions.
Definitions
The theorem considers a finite number of voters, {{mvar|n}}, who vote for policies which are represented as points in Euclidean space of dimension {{mvar|m}}. Each vote is between two policies using majority rule. Each voter, {{mvar|i}}, has a utility function, {{mvar|Ui}}, which measures how much they value different policies.{{clarify|date=August 2024|reason=Ties could happen if utilities are equal or there are an even number of voters}}
Euclidean preferences
Richard McKelvey considered the case when preferences are "Euclidean metrics".{{cite journal |last1=McKelvey |first1=Richard D. |title=Intransitivities in Multidimensional Voting Models and Some Implications for Agenda Control |journal=Journal of Economic Theory |date=June 1976 |volume=12 |issue=3 |pages=472–482|doi=10.1016/0022-0531(76)90040-5 }} That means every voter's utility function has the form
U_i(x)=\Phi_i \cdot d(x,x_i)
for all policies {{mvar|x}} and some {{mvar|xi}}, where {{mvar|d}} is the Euclidean distance and is a monotone decreasing function.
Under these conditions, there could be a collection of policies which don't have a Condorcet winner using majority rule. This means that, given a number of policies {{mvar|Xa}}, {{mvar|Xb}}, {{mvar|Xc}}, there could be a series of pairwise elections where:
- {{mvar|Xa}} wins over {{mvar|Xb}}
- {{mvar|Xb}} wins over {{mvar|Xc}}
- {{mvar|Xc}} wins over {{mvar|Xa}}
McKelvey proved that elections can be even more "chaotic" than that: If there is no equilibrium outcome{{clarify|date=August 2024|reason=Definition?}} then any two policies, e.g. {{mvar|A}} and {{mvar|B}}, have a sequence of policies, , where each one pairwise wins over the other in a series of elections, meaning:
- {{mvar|A}} wins over {{mvar|X1}}
- {{mvar|X1}} wins over {{mvar|X2}}
- ...
- {{mvar|Xs}} wins over {{mvar|B}}
This is true regardless of whether {{mvar|A}} would beat {{mvar|B}} or vice versa.
= Example =
File:McKelvey theorem example.svg
The simplest illustrating example is in two dimensions, with three voters. Each voter will then have a maximum preferred policy, and any other policy will have a corresponding circular indifference curve centered at the preferred policy. If a policy was proposed, then any policy in the intersection of two voters indifference curves would beat it. Any point in the plane will almost always have a set of points that are preferred by 2 out of 3 voters.
Generalisations
Norman Schofield extended the theorem to more general classes of utility functions, requiring only that they are differentiable. He also established conditions for the existence of a directed continuous path of policies, where each policy further along the path would win against one earlier.{{cite journal |last1=Schofield |first1=N.|title=Instability of Simple Dynamic Games |journal=The Review of Economic Studies |date=1 October 1978 |volume=45 |issue=3 |pages=575–594 |doi=10.2307/2297259|jstor=2297259 }}{{Cite book |last1=Cox |first1=Gary W. |author-link=Gary W. Cox |title=Positive Changes in Political Science |last2=Shepsle |first2=Kenneth A. |author-link2=Kenneth Shepsle |pages=20–23 |chapter=Majority Cycling and Agenda Manipulation: Richard McKelvey's Contributions and Legacy |date=2007 |publisher=University of Michigan Press |isbn=978-0-472-06986-6 |editor-last=Aldrich |editor-first=John Herbert |series=Analytical perspectives on politics |location=Ann Arbor, Michigan |editor-last2=Alt |editor-first2=James E. |editor-last3=Lupia |editor-first3=Arthur}} Some of Schofield's proofs were later found to be incorrect by Jeffrey S. Banks, who corrected his proofs.{{Cite journal |last=Banks |first=Jeffrey S. |date=1995-01-01 |title=Singularity theory and core existence in the spatial model |journal=Journal of Mathematical Economics |volume=24 |issue=6 |pages=523–536 |doi=10.1016/0304-4068(94)00704-E |issn=0304-4068|doi-access=free }}{{Cite book |last=Saari |first=Donald G. |author-link=Donald G. Saari |url=https://www.worldcat.org/title/227031682 |title=Disposing dictators, demystifying voting paradoxes: social choice analysis |date=2008 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-51605-1 |location=Cambridge, New York |chapter=Deliver Us from the Plurality Vote |oclc=227031682}}
References
{{reflist}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:McKelvey-Schofield chaos theorem}}
{{Econ-theory-stub}}