Personal identity

{{Short description|Philosophical idea of a person having a unique existence}}

{{About|the topic in philosophy|a person's self-identity or sense of self|Self-concept|and|Identity (social science)|other uses|Personal identity (disambiguation)|and|Identity (disambiguation)}}

{{Self sidebar|Carmen Giles=Carmen Vann}}

Personal identity is the unique numerical identity of a person over time.[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/identity-personal/ Personal Identity] (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/identity/ Identity] (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) Discussions regarding personal identity typically aim to determine the necessary and sufficient conditions under which a person at one time and a person at another time can be said to be the {{em|same}} person, persisting through time.

In philosophy, the problem of personal identity{{cite web|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/person-i/|title=Personal Identity - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy|website=www.iep.utm.edu|access-date=22 October 2017|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170903032724/http://www.iep.utm.edu/person-i/|archive-date=3 September 2017}} is concerned with how one is able to identify a single person over a time interval, dealing with such questions as, "What makes it true that a person at one time is the same thing as a person at another time?" or "What kinds of things are we persons?"

In contemporary metaphysics, the matter of personal identity is referred to as the diachronic problem of personal identity.{{efn|{{langx|el|Διαχρονικός|Diachronikos}}}}An Essay Concerning Human Understanding; Volumes 1–3. By John Locke The synchronic problem concerns the question of what features and traits characterize a person at a given time. Analytic philosophy and continental philosophy both inquire about the nature of identity. Continental philosophy deals with conceptually maintaining identity when confronted by different philosophic propositions, postulates, and presuppositions about the world and its nature.Self and Subjectivity; "Identity, Sex, and the Metaphysics of Substance". Edited by Kim Atkins. p257.Cultural Theory: An Anthology. Edited by Imre Szeman, Timothy Kaposy. p481. "Identity, Sex, and the Metaphysics of Substance"

Continuity of substance

=Bodily substance=

{{further|Materialism}}{{see also|Physicalism|Further facts}}

One way to explain how persons persist over time is to say that identity consists in physical or bodily continuity.{{Citation |last=Olson |first=Eric T. |title=Personal Identity |date=2023 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2023/entries/identity-personal/ |access-date=2024-03-27 |edition=Fall 2023 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri}}Olson, Eric T. 1997. The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology. New York: Oxford University Press. However, there are problems with this view. As the Ship of Theseus thought experiment illustrates, even for inanimate objects there are difficulties in determining whether one physical body at one time is the same thing as a physical body at another time. With humans, over time our bodies age and grow, losing and gaining matter, and over sufficient years will not consist of most of the matter they once consisted of. It is thus problematic to ground the persistence of personal identity over time in the continuous existence of our bodies. Nevertheless, this approach has its supporters, who define humans as biological organisms. They assert the proposition that a psychological relation is not necessary for personal continuity.{{efn|See also: Disjunctive syllogism, Affirming a disjunct, Proof by assertion.}} This personal identity ontology assumes the relational theoryOlson, Eric T. 2007. What Are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. New York: Oxford University Press. of life-sustaining processes instead of bodily continuity.

The teletransportation problem proposed by Derek Parfit is designed to bring out intuitions about corporeal continuity. The thought experiment discusses cases in which a person is teleported from Earth to Mars. Ultimately, the inability to specify where on a spectrum the transmitted person stops being identical to the initial person on Earth appears to show that having a numerically identical physical body is not the criterion for personal identity.Durante, Chris. 2013. "[http://philosophynow.org/issues/97/A_Philosophical_Identity_Crisis A Philosophical Identity Crisis]." Philosophy Now 97. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130806075708/http://philosophynow.org/issues/97/A_Philosophical_Identity_Crisis|date=2013-08-06}}.

Christian List has argued against physicalist conceptions of consciousness and personal identity on the basis of how first-personal facts relate to third-personal facts. He argues that first-personal facts cannot supervene on third-personal facts, and that this refutes not only physicalism, but also most forms of dualism with purely third-personal metaphysics.{{cite web |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/LISTFA |title=The first-personal argument against physicalism |last=List |first=Christian |date=2023 |website= |publisher= |access-date=20 May 2025 |quote=}} List also argues that there exists a "quadrilemma" for theories of consciousness. He claims that at most three of the following metaphysical claims can be true: 'first-person realism', 'non-solipsism', 'non-fragmentation', and 'one world' – and thus at least one of these four must be false.{{cite web |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/LISAQF |title=A quadrilemma for theories of consciousness |last=List |first=Christian |date=2023 |website= |publisher=The Philosophical Quarterly |access-date=20 May 2025 |quote=}} List has proposed a model he calls the "many-worlds theory of consciousness" in order to reconcile the subjective nature of consciousness without lapsing into solipsism.{{cite web |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/LISTMT-2 |title=The many-worlds theory of consciousness |last=List |first=Christian |date=2023 |website= |publisher=The Philosophical Quarterly |access-date=20 May 2025 |quote=}}

=Mental substance=

{{Further|Mind-body dualism|Monism|Mind–body problem}}

{{See also|Idealism|Pluralism (philosophy)}}

In another concept of mind, the set of cognitive faculties{{efn|Those faculties that enable consciousness, perception, thinking, judgement, and memory.|name=|group=}} are considered to consist of an immaterial substance, separate from and independent of the body.Going, Jonathan. 1835. The Christian Library, Vols. 3-4. p. 786+. cf. [https://books.google.com/books?id=aOkWAQAAIAAJ&pg=PA803 p. 803]: "Now all would believe in the separate existence of the soul if they had experience of its existing apart from the body. But the facts referred to proves that it does exist apart from one body with which it once was united, and though it is in union with another, yet as it is not adherent to the same, it is shown to have an existence separate from, and independent of that body." If a person is then identified with their mind, rather than their body—if a person is considered to {{em|be}} their mind—and their mind is such a non-physical substance, then personal identity over time may be grounded in the persistence of this non-physical substance, despite the continuous change in the substance of the body it is associated with.

The mind-body problem{{cite book |author=Descartes, R. |year=2008 |title=Meditations on First Philosophy |edition= Michael Moriarity translation of 1641 |publisher= Oxford University Press |url=https://archive.org/details/meditationsonfir0000desc|url-access=registration |isbn=9780191604942 }}{{cite book |editor1=RC Olby |editor2=GN Cantor |editor3=JR Christie |editor4=MJS Hodges |title=Companion to the History of Modern Science |publisher=Taylor and Francis |year=1996 |pages=702–11 |isbn=0415145783 |chapter=The mind-body problem |chapter-url=http://human-nature.com/rmyoung/papers/pap102h.html |author=Robert M. Young |edition=Paperback reprint of Routledge 1990 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070614061431/http://human-nature.com/rmyoung/papers/pap102h.html |archive-date=2007-06-14 }}{{cite encyclopedia |author=Robinson, Howard |title=Dualism |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta |url = http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/dualism/ |date=Nov 3, 2011}}{{cite book |title= Forming the Mind: Essays on the Internal Senses and the Mind/Body Problem from Avicenna to the Medical Enlightenment |publisher= Springer Science+Business Media |year= 2010 |edition=Paperback reprint of 2007 |isbn= 978-9048175307 |chapter=Introduction |page=3 |author=Henrik Lagerlund |editor= Henrik Lagerlund |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=IV-dcQAACAAJ}} concerns the explanation of the relationship, if any, that exists between minds, or mental processes, and bodily states or processes. One of the aims of philosophers who work in this area is to explain how a non-material mind can influence a material body and vice versa.

This is controversial and problematic, and adopting it as a solution raises questions. Perceptual experiences depend on stimuli which arrive at various sensory organs from the external world and these stimuli cause changes in mental states; ultimately causing sensation.{{efn|This may be pleasant, unpleasant, or neutral.}} A desire for food, for example, will tend to cause a person to move their body in a manner and in a direction to obtain food. The question, then, is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to arise out of an organ (the human brain) possessing electrochemical properties. A related problem is to explain how propositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs and desires) can cause neurons of the brain to fire and muscles to contract in the correct manner. These comprise some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from at least the time of René Descartes.

Some philosophers have used a form of indexicality as a way of defining the self. The philosopher Benj Hellie coined the phrase "the vertiginous question" to describe the question of why, of all the subjects of experience out there, this one—the one corresponding to the human being referred to as Benj Hellie—is the one whose experiences are live. (The reader is supposed to substitute their own case for Hellie's.){{cite journal |last1=Hellie |first1=Benj |last2= |first2= |date=2013 |title=Against Egalitarianism |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/HELCFC |journal=Analysis |volume=73 |issue= |publisher= |pages=304–320 |doi=10.1093/analys/ans101 |access-date=}} Other philosophers have described similar phenomena. Tim S. Roberts refers to the question of why a particular organism out of all the organisms that happen to exist happens to be you as the "Even Harder Problem of Consciousness".{{cite journal|last=Roberts|first=Tim S.|title=The Even Harder Problem of Consciousness by Roberts. Tim S.|journal=NeuroQuantology|date=September 2007|volume=5|issue=2|pages=214–221|doi=10.14704/nq.2007.5.2.129 |url=https://www.researchgate.net/publication/228618472}} Herbert Spiegelberg has referred to it as the "I-am-me experience", and it has been called the "Ich-Erlebnis" by German psychologists.{{citation |last=Watanabe |first=Tsuneo |contribution=From Spiegelberg's "I-am-me" experience to the solipsistic experience |title=IHSRC 2009 (The 28th International Human Science Research Conference) |place=Molde, Norway |date=1 June 2009 |url=https://www.researchgate.net/publication/388593480_From_Spiegelberg's_I-am-me_experience_to_the_solipsistic_experience |access-date=2 February 2025 }}{{citation |last=Watanabe |first=Tsuneo |contribution=Enigma of the private self and studies of the "I-am-me experience": Towards a phenomenological approach to the development of the subjective self |title=ISTP (International Society for Theoretical Psychology) 2017 Conference (Tokyo, Japan) |url=https://www.researchgate.net/publication/386086401_Enigma_of_the_private_self_and_studies_of_the_I-am-me_experience_Towards_a_phenomenological_approach_to_the_development_of_the_subjective_self }} Japanese philosopher Hitoshi Nagai defines the self as the "one who directly experiences the consciousness of oneself".* Why Isn’t Consciousness Real? (1) Philosophia Osaka No. 6, 2011:41-61 [http://hnagai.web.fc2.com/why_isnt_consciousness_real_day1.pdf PDF]

Continuity of consciousness

=Locke's conception=

File:Locke Essay 1690.jpg in four books (1690) by John Locke (1632–1704)]]

John Locke considered personal identity (or the self) to be founded on consciousness (viz. memory), and not on the substance of either the soul or the body.Locke, John. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Vols 1–3. Chapter 27 of Book II of his Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1689), entitled "On Identity and Diversity", has been said to be one of the first modern conceptualizations of consciousness as the repeated self-identification of oneself. Through this identification, moral responsibility could be attributed to the subject and punishment and guilt could be justified, as critics such as Nietzsche would point out.

According to Locke, personal identity (the self) "depends on consciousness, not on substance" nor on the soul. We are the same person to the extent that we are conscious of the past and future thoughts and actions in the same way as we are conscious of present thoughts and actions. If consciousness is this "thought" which "goes along with the substance…which makes the same person," then personal identity is only founded on the repeated act of consciousness: "This may show us wherein personal identity consists: not in the identity of substance, but…in the identity of consciousness." For example, one may claim to be a reincarnation of Plato, therefore having the same soul substance. One would be the same person as Plato only if one had the same consciousness of Plato's thoughts and actions that he himself did. Therefore, self-identity is not based on the soul. One soul may have various personalities.

Neither is self-identity founded on the body substance, argues Locke, as the body may change while the person remains the same. Even the identity of animals is not founded on their body: "animal identity is preserved in identity of life, and not of substance," as the body of the animal grows and changes during its life. On the other hand, identity of humans is based on their consciousness.{{efn|Take for example a prince's mind which enters the body of a cobbler: to all exterior eyes, the cobbler would remain a cobbler. But to the prince himself, the cobbler would be himself, as he would be conscious of the prince's thoughts and acts, and not those of the cobbler. A prince's consciousness in a cobbler's body: thus the cobbler is, in fact, a prince.}}

This border case leads to this problematic thought that since personal identity is based on consciousness, and only oneself can be aware of one's consciousness, exterior human judges may never know if they are really judging—and punishing—the same person, or simply the same body. In other words, Locke argues that one may be judged only for the acts of the body, as this is what is apparent to all but God. We are only responsible for the acts of which we are conscious. This forms the basis of the insanity defense—one cannot be held accountable for acts of which one was unconscious—and therefore leads to philosophical questions:

{{blockquote|personal identity consists [not in the identity of substance] but in the identity of consciousness, wherein if Socrates and the present mayor of Queenborough agree, they are the same person: if the same Socrates waking and sleeping do not partake of the same consciousness, Socrates waking and sleeping is not the same person. And to punish Socrates waking for what sleeping Socrates thought, and waking Socrates was never conscious of, would be no more right, than to punish one twin for what his brother-twin did, whereof he knew nothing, because their outsides were so like, that they could not be distinguished; for such twins have been seen.{{Cite web|url=https://www.gutenberg.org/files/10615/10615-h/10615-h.htm#link2HCH0030|title = An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding, Volume I., by John Locke}}}}

Or again:

{{blockquote|PERSON, as I take it, is the name for this self. Wherever a man finds what he calls himself, there, I think, another may say is the same person. It is a forensic term, appropriating actions and their merit; and so belong only to intelligent agents, capable of a law, and happiness, and misery. This personality extends itself beyond present existence to what is past, only by consciousness,—whereby it becomes concerned and accountable; owns and imputes to itself past actions, just upon the same ground and for the same reason as it does the present. All which is founded in a concern for happiness, the unavoidable concomitant of consciousness; that which is conscious of pleasure and pain, desiring that that self that is conscious should be happy. And therefore whatever past actions it cannot reconcile or APPROPRIATE to that present self by consciousness, it can be no more concerned in it than if they had never been done: and to receive pleasure or pain, i.e. reward or punishment, on the account of any such action, is all one as to be made happy or miserable in its first being, without any demerit at all. For, supposing a MAN punished now for what he had done in another life, whereof he could be made to have no consciousness at all, what difference is there between that punishment and being CREATED miserable? And therefore, conformable to this, the apostle tells us, that, at the great day, when every one shall 'receive according to his doings, the secrets of all hearts shall be laid open.' The sentence shall be justified by the consciousness all person shall have, that THEY THEMSELVES, in what bodies soever they appear, or what substances soever that consciousness adheres to, are the SAME that committed those actions, and deserve that punishment for them.}}

Henceforth, Locke's conception of personal identity founds it not on the substance or the body, but in the "same continued consciousness", which is also distinct from the soul since the soul may have no consciousness of itself (as in reincarnation). He creates a third term between the soul and the body. For Locke, the body may change, while consciousness remains the same.Encyclopædia Britannica. Volume 18. Edited by Hugh Chisholm.[https://books.google.com/books?id=IycqAAAAYAAJ&pg=PA225 p225]+253.{{cite journal | pmc = 3115296 | pmid=21694978 | doi=10.4103/0973-1229.77443 | volume=9 | issue=1 | title=John locke on personal identity | journal=Mens Sana Monogr | pages=268–75 | last1 = Nimbalkar | first1 = N| year=2011 | doi-access=free }} Therefore, personal identity, for Locke, is not in the body but in consciousness.

=Philosophical intuition=

Bernard Williams presents a thought experiment appealing to the intuitions about what it is to be the same person in the future.Williams, Bernard. 1970. "The Self and the Future." Philosophical Review 79(2):161–80. The thought experiment consists of two approaches to the same experiment.

For the first approach Williams suggests that suppose that there is some process by which subjecting two persons to it can result in the two persons have "exchanged" bodies. The process has put into the body of person B the memories, behavioral dispositions, and psychological characteristics of the person who prior to undergoing the process belonged to person A; and conversely with person B. To show this one is to suppose that before undergoing the process person A and B are asked to which resulting person, A-Body-Person or B-Body-Person, they wish to receive a punishment and which a reward. Upon undergoing the process and receiving either the punishment or reward, it appears to that A-Body-Person expresses the memories of choosing who gets which treatment as if that person was person B; conversely with B-Body-Person.

This sort of approach to the thought experiment appears to show that since the person who expresses the psychological characteristics of person A to be person A, then intuition is that psychological continuity is the criterion for personal identity.

The second approach is to suppose that someone is told that one will have memories erased and then one will be tortured. Does one need to be afraid of being tortured? The intuition is that people will be afraid of being tortured, since it will still be one despite not having one's memories. Next, Williams asked one to consider several similar scenarios.{{efn|The synoptical collage of an event or series of actions and events are:

  • One has memories erased, and are given new "fake" memories (counterfeit), and then one is to be tortured;
  • have one's memories erased, are given copies of another's memories, and then are to be tortured;
  • have one's memories erased, are given another's genuine memories, and then one is to be tortured;
  • have one's memories erased, are given another's genuine memories, that person is given one's memories, and then one is to be tortured.}}

Intuition is that in all the scenarios one is to be afraid of being tortured, that it is still one's self despite having one's memories erased and receiving new memories. The last scenario is identical to the first.{{efn|With the supposed superfluous information included in the last scenario.}}

In the first approach, intuition is to show that one's psychological continuity is the criterion for personal identity, but in second approach, intuition is that it is one's bodily continuity that is the criterion for personal identity. To resolve this conflict Williams feels one's intuition in the second approach is stronger and if he was given the choice of distributing a punishment and a reward he would want his body-person to receive the reward and the other body-person to receive the punishment, even if that other body-person has his memories.

=Psychological continuity=

In psychology, personal continuity, also called personal persistence or self-continuity, is the uninterrupted connection concerning a particular person of their private life and personality. Personal continuity is the union affecting the facets arising from personality in order to avoid discontinuities from one moment of time to another time.{{efn|For more, see: consciousness.}}Frost, Martin. March 2009. "[http://www.martinfrost.ws/htmlfiles/mar2009/identity-self-image.html Identity and self-image]." martinfrost.ws. {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130827233126/http://www.martinfrost.ws/htmlfiles/mar2009/identity-self-image.html|date=2013-08-27}}

Personal continuity is an important part of identity; this is the process of ensuring that the qualities of the mind, such as self-awareness, sentience, sapience, and the ability to perceive the relationship between oneself and one's environment, are consistent from one moment to the next. Personal continuity is the property of a continuous and connected period of time{{cite book | author-link=David Hume | last=Hume | first=David | date=1739 | chapter=Of contiguity and distance in space and time | chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0079 | title=A Treatise of Human Nature | at=Book 2, part 3, § 7, pp. 427, 432}}Locke, John. "On Identity and Diversity." Ch. 27 in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 1-3. pp. 46, 69. and is intimately related to do with a person's body or physical being in a single four-dimensional continuum.Giddens, Anthony. 1990. "Modernity, Time, Space." In The Consequences of Modernity. Associationism, a theory of how ideas combine in the mind, allows events or views to be associated with each other in the mind, thus leading to a form of learning. Associations can result from contiguity, similarity, or contrast. Through contiguity, one associates ideas or events that usually happen to occur at the same time. Some of these events form an autobiographical memory in which each is a personal representation of the general or specific events and personal facts.

Ego integrity is the psychological concept of the ego's accumulated assurance of its capacity for order and meaning. Ego identity is the accrued confidence that the inner sameness and continuity prepared in the past are matched by the sameness and continuity of one's meaning for others, as evidenced in the promise of a career. Body and ego control organ expressionsPervin, Lawrence A., and Cary L. Cooper, eds. Personality: Critical Concepts.Thinking Bodies. Edited by Juliet Flower MacCannell, Laura Zakarin{{cite book | last=Maudsley | first=Henry | author-link=Henry Maudsley | year=1884 | orig-year=1883 | title=Body and will: Metaphysical, physiological, and pathological aspects | publication-place=New York | publisher=D. Appleton and Company | url=https://archive.org/details/bodywillbeingess00mauduoft?view=theater}}{{cite book | last=Steiner | first=Rudolf | author-link=Rudolf Steiner | year=1968 | orig-year=1909 | title=The four temperaments | edition=2nd | translator-last=Dawson | translator-first=Frances E. | publisher=Anthroposophic Press | lccn=68023910 | url=https://archive.org/details/Steiner4Temperaments?view=theater}}The Book of the Law, or Liber AL vel Legis. By Aleister Crowley, Aiwass and of the other attributes of the dynamics of a physical system to face the emotions of ego deathDartington, Tim. Managing Vulnerability: The Underlying Dynamics of Systems of Care.Ashford, José B., Craig Winston LeCroy, and Kathy L. Lortie. Human Behavior in the Social Environment: A Multidimensional Perspective. in circumstances which can summon, sometimes, anti-theonymistic self-abandonment.de Caussade, Jean-Pierre. Abandonment to Divine Providence.James, William. 1890. The Principles of Psychology, Vol. 1.Cohen, Donna, and Carl Eisdorfer. [https://books.google.com/books?id=2YzkWTEtNq8C The Loss of Self].Mahar, A. J. The Legacy of Abandonment in Borderline Personality Disorder.Narayan, R. K. The Guide.

=Identity continuum=

{{See also|#The no-self theory|Self-discovery}}

It has been argued from the nature of sensations and ideas that there is no such thing as a permanent identity.{{cite book|last1=MacFarquhar|first1=Colin|last2=Gleig|first2=George|title=Encyclopædia britannica: or, A dictionary of arts, sciences, and miscellaneous literature|publisher=A. Bell and C. Macfarquhar|url=https://archive.org/details/encbritannica11macf|page=[https://archive.org/details/encbritannica11macf/page/587 587]|access-date=15 January 2017|language=en|year=1797}} Daniel Shapiro asserts that one of four major views on identity does not recognize a "permanent identity" and instead thinks of "thoughts without a thinker"—"a consciousness shell with drifting emotions and thoughts but no essence". According to him this view is based on the Buddhist concept of anatta, "a continuously evolving flow of awareness."{{cite book|last1=Shapiro|first1=Daniel|title=Negotiating the Nonnegotiable: How to Resolve Your Most Emotionally Charged Conflicts|publisher=Penguin|isbn=9781101626962|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nmdYCgAAQBAJ&pg=PT83|access-date=15 January 2017|language=en|date=2016-04-19|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180504232258/https://books.google.de/books?id=nmdYCgAAQBAJ&pg=PT83|archive-date=4 May 2018}} Malcolm David Eckel states that "the self changes at every moment and has no permanent identity"{{cite book|last1=Eckel|first1=Malcolm David|title=Buddhism: Origins, Beliefs, Practices, Holy Texts, Sacred Places|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=9780195219074|language=en|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/buddhismoriginsb0000ecke|year=2002}}—it is a "constant process of changing or becoming;" a "fluid ever-changing self."{{cite book|last1=Schneider|first1=Kirk J.|last2=Pierson|first2=J. Fraser|last3=Bugental|first3=James F. T.|title=The Handbook of Humanistic Psychology: Theory, Research, and Practice|publisher=SAGE Publications|isbn=9781483322827|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vUcXBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA116|access-date=15 January 2017|language=en|date=2014-02-14|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170116190737/https://books.google.de/books?id=vUcXBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA116|archive-date=16 January 2017}}

Bundle theory of the self

File:A Treatise of Human Nature by David Hume.jpg

David Hume undertook looking at the mind–body problem. Hume also investigated a person's character, the relationship between human and animal nature, and the nature of agency. Hume pointed out that we tend to think that we are the same person we were five years ago. Though we've changed in many respects, the same person appears present now as was present then. We might start thinking about which features can be changed without changing the underlying self. Hume denied a distinction between the various features of a person and the mysterious self that supposedly bears those features. When we begin introspecting:

[We] always stumble on some particular perception or other.… I may venture to affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions which succeed each other with an inconceivable rapidity and are in perpetual flux and movement.{{cite book | last=Hume | first=David | date=1739 | chapter=Of personal identity | chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0043 | title=A Treatise of Human Nature | at=Book 1, part 4, § 6}}

It is plain, that in the course of our thinking, and in the constant revolution of our ideas, our imagination runs easily from one idea to any other that resembles it, and that this quality alone is to the fancy a sufficient bond and association. It is likewise evident that as the senses, in changing their objects, are necessitated to change them regularly, and take them as they lie contiguous to each other, the imagination must by long custom acquire the same method of thinking, and run along the parts of space and time in conceiving its objects.{{cite book | last=Hume | first=David | date=1739 | chapter=Of the connexion or association of ideas | chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0009 | title=A Treatise of Human Nature | at=Book 1, part 1, § 4}}

Note in particular that, in Hume's view, these perceptions do not belong to anything. Hume, similar to the Buddha,Ross, Nancy Wilson. Buddhism: Way of Life & Thought. [https://books.google.com/books?id=eqdbDZaW1QAC&pg=PA29 p. 29]. compares the soul to a commonwealth, which retains its identity not by virtue of some enduring core substance, but by being composed of many different, related, and yet constantly changing elements.{{cite book | last=Hume | first=David | date=1739 | chapter=Of personal identity | chapter-url=https://gutenberg.org/cache/epub/4705/pg4705-images.html#link2H_4_0043 | title=A Treatise of Human Nature | at=Book 1, part 4, § 6 | quote=In this respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of its parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the same person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his impressions and ideas, without losing his identity.}} The question of personal identity then becomes a matter of characterizing the loose cohesion{{efn|See also: structural cohesion}} of one's personal experience.{{efn|In the Appendix to the Treatise, Hume stated that he was dissatisfied with his account of the self, yet he never returned to the issue.}}

In short, what matters for Hume is not that 'identity' exists, but the fact that the relations of causation, contiguity, and resemblances obtain among the perceptions. Critics of Hume state that in order for the various states and processes of the mind to seem unified, there must be something which perceives their unity, the existence of which would be no less mysterious than a personal identity. Hume solves this by considering substance as engendered by the togetherness of its properties.

No-self theory

{{See also|Nihilism|Post-left anarchy#Self-theory}}

{{Distinguish|Anattā}}

The "no-self theory" holds that the self cannot be reduced to a bundle because the concept of a self is incompatible with the idea of a bundle. Propositionally, the idea of a bundle implies the notion of bodily or psychological relations that do not in fact exist. James Giles, a principal exponent of this view, argues that the no-self or eliminativist theory and the bundle or reductionist theory agree about the non-existence of a substantive self. The reductionist theory, according to Giles, mistakenly resurrects the idea{{efn|And, presumably, resurrection.}} of the self[https://philosophy.as.uky.edu/sites/default/files/The%20No-Self%20Theory%20-%20Hume,%20Buddhism,%20and%20Personal%20Identity%20-%20James%20Giles.pdf The No-Self Theory] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140808051956/https://philosophy.as.uky.edu/sites/default/files/The%20No-Self%20Theory%20-%20Hume,%20Buddhism,%20and%20Personal%20Identity%20-%20James%20Giles.pdf |date=2014-08-08 }}: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity. James Giles in terms of various accounts about psychological relations.{{efn|See also: Psychological entropy.}} The no-self theory, on the other hand, "lets the self lie where it has fallen".

James Giles, No Self to be Found: The Search for Personal Identity, University Press of America, 1997, p. 10

This is because the no-self theory rejects all theories of the self, even the bundle theory. On Giles' reading, Hume is actually a no-self theorist and it is a mistake to attribute to him a reductionist view like the bundle theory. Hume's assertion that personal identity is a fiction supports this reading, according to Giles.

The Buddhist view of personal identity is also a no-self theory rather than a reductionist theory, because the Buddha rejects attempts to reconstructions in terms of consciousness, feelings, or the body in notions of an eternal/permanent, unchanging Self,

Giles, James. 1993. "The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity." Philosophy East and West 42. since our thoughts, personalities and bodies are never the same from moment to moment, as specifically explained in Śūnyatā.{{cite book|last1=Wrasman|first1=Andy|title=Contradict: They Can't All Be True|publisher=WestBowPress|isbn=9781490829814|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dYkNAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA27|access-date=15 January 2017|language=en|date=2014-01-13|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170116191138/https://books.google.de/books?id=dYkNAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA27|archive-date=16 January 2017}}

According to this line of criticism, the sense of self is an evolutionary artifact,{{efn|See also: Phenotypic traits, Society (Social artifact), Culture (Cultural artifact), evolutionary psychology (criticism of evolutionary psychology).}} which saves time in the circumstances it evolved for. But sense of self breaks down when considering some events such as memory loss,{{efn|See also: Alzheimer's disease}} dissociative identity disorder, brain damage, brainwashing, and various thought experiments.[http://www.philosophersnet.com/games/identity.htm "Staying alive game - Examples of thought experiments on personal identity"] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20071011024327/http://www.philosophersnet.com/games/identity.htm |date=2007-10-11 }} When presented with imperfections in the intuitive sense of self and the consequences to this concept which rely on the strict concept of self, a tendency to mend the concept occurs, possibly because of cognitive dissonance.{{efn|Though, this does not address the loose cohesion of self and other similar epistemological views.}}

Open individualism is a term coined by Daniel Kolak that refers to the view in the philosophy of self that there exists only one numerically identical subject, who is everyone at all times, in the past, present and future.{{Cite book|last=Kolak|first=Daniel|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-_JD9NIWBVgC|title=I Am You: The Metaphysical Foundations for Global Ethics|date=2007-11-03|publisher=Springer Science & Business Media|isbn=978-1-4020-3014-7|language=en}}{{Rp|page=617}} It is a theoretical solution to the question of personal identity, being contrasted with "Empty individualism", the view that personal identities correspond to a fixed pattern that instantaneously disappears with the passage of time, and "Closed individualism", the common view that personal identities are particular to subjects and yet survive over time.{{Rp|page=xxii}}

Experimental philosophy

{{disputed section|date=April 2024}}

Since the 21st century, philosophers have also been using the methods of psychological science to better understand philosophical intuitions.{{cite journal |last1=Knobe |first1=Joshua |title=Philosophers are doing something different now: Quantitative data |journal=Cognition |date=2015 |volume=135 |pages=36–38 |doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2014.11.011 |pmid=25440237 |s2cid=33859882 |url=https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2014.11.011}} This empirical approach to philosophy is known as Experimental philosophy or "xPhi" for short. Studies in xPhi have found various psychological factors predict variance even in philosophers views about personal identity.{{cite journal |last1=Byrd |first1=Nick |title=Great Minds do not Think Alike: Philosophers' Views Predicted by Reflection, Education, Personality, and Other Demographic Differences |journal=Review of Philosophy and Psychology |date=2022 |volume=14 |issue=2 |pages=647–684 |doi=10.1007/s13164-022-00628-y |s2cid=247911367 |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-022-00628-y}}

=Moral self theory=

Findings from xPhi suggest that moral intuitions may have a major influence on our intuitions about personal identity. For example, some experimental philosophers have found that when a person undergoes a dramatic change (e.g., traumatic brain injury), people are less likely to think that the person is the "same" after their dramatic change if the person became morally worse (as opposed to morally better).{{cite journal |last1=Tobia |first1=Kevin |title=Personal identity and the Phineas Gage effect |journal=Analysis |date=2015 |volume=75 |issue=3 |pages=396–405 |doi=10.1093/analys/anv041 |url=https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/anv041}} Data like this support the "moral self hypothesis", that "moral traits are essential" to personal identity,{{cite journal |last1=Strohminger |first1=Nina |last2=Nichols |first2=Shaun |title=The Essential Moral Self |journal=Cognition |date=2014 |volume=131 |issue=1 |pages=159–171 |doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2013.12.005 |pmid=24503450 |s2cid=28462268 |url=https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2013.12.005|url-access=subscription }} with some going as far as saying that, "When someone undergoes dramatic mental change, their numerical identity—whether they're the same person as they were before—can seem to become disrupted".

=Numerical and qualitative=

While the direction of change (e.g., moral improvement vs. moral deterioration) has been found to cause substantial shifts in peoples' judgments about personal identity, multiple studies find that none of these shifts constitute thinking that someone is numerically non-identical to the person they were before the change—such that the person before the change is one person and the person after the change is an entirely separate second person: when people were asked how many people are described in cases of dramatic moral change, the vast majority of answers were "one" (rather than two or more).{{cite journal |last1=Schwenkler |first1=John |last2=Byrd |first2=Nick |last3=Lambert |first3=Enoch |last4=Taylor |first4=Matthew |title=One: but not the same |journal=Philosophical Studies |date=2021 |volume=179 |issue=6 |pages=1939–1951 |doi=10.1007/s11098-021-01739-5 |s2cid=244191298 |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-021-01739-5|url-access=subscription }} This aligns with more recent evidence that these shifts in intuitions about personal identity are about qualitative identity (i.e., how similar one is to a prior version of themselves) rather than numerical identity (i.e., whether there are two or more people described by cases in which a person undergoes a dramatic change).{{cite journal |last1=Finlay |first1=Melissa |last2=Starmans |first2=Christina |title=Not the same same: Distinguishing between similarity and identity in judgments of change |journal=Cognition |date=2022 |volume=2018 |page=104953 |doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104953 |pmid=34784500 |s2cid=244100585 |url=https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cognition.2021.104953|url-access=subscription }}

Relation to solipsism

Philosophers such as Caspar Hare have argued that the existence of personal identity and existing as oneself and not as someone else implies a form of solipsism. Caspar Hare's theories of the metaphysics of self include the theories of egocentric presentism, a form of solipsism introduces by Hare that argues that the experiences of other individuals are not present in the way that one's current perspective is.{{cite journal|last=Hare|first=Caspar|title=Self-Bias, Time-Bias, and the Metaphysics of Self and Time|journal=The Journal of Philosophy|date=July 2007|volume=104|issue=7|pages=350–373|doi=10.5840/jphil2007104717|url=http://web.mit.edu/~casparh/www/Papers/CJHareSelfBias2.pdf}}{{cite book|last=Hare|first=Caspar|title=On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects|year=2009|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=9780691135311|url=http://press.princeton.edu/titles/8921.html}} and perspectival realism, in which things within perceptual awareness have a defining intrinsic property that exists absolutely and not relative to anything.{{cite journal |last=Hare |first=Caspar |date=September 2010 |title=Realism About Tense and Perspective |url=http://web.mit.edu/~casparh/www/Papers/CJHarePerspectivalRealism.pdf |journal=Philosophy Compass |volume=5 |issue=9 |pages=760–769 |doi=10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00325.x |hdl-access=free |hdl=1721.1/115229}} Several other philosophers have written reviews of Caspar Hare's theories.{{cite journal|last=McDaniel|first=Kris|title=On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects by Hare, Caspar - Review|journal=Ethics|date=January 2012|volume=122|issue=2|pages=403–410|url=http://krmcdani.mysite.syr.edu/whymcxmattersmost.pdf|doi=10.1086/663578}}{{cite journal|last=Markosian|first=Ned|title=Are You Special? A Review of Caspar Hare's On Myself, and Other, Less Important Subjects|journal=The Philosophical Review|url=http://myweb.facstaff.wwu.edu/nmarkos/Papers/Hare.Review.pdf|access-date=2015-03-13|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150226073041/http://myweb.facstaff.wwu.edu/nmarkos/Papers/Hare.Review.pdf|archive-date=2015-02-26|url-status=dead}}

Vincent Conitzer has argued that there exists a connection between the self and the metaphysics of time. He argues that arguments in favor of the A-theory of time are more effective as arguments for the combined position of both A-theory being true and the "I" being metaphysically privileged from other perspectives.{{cite arXiv|last=Conitzer|first=Vincent|author-link=|date=30 Aug 2020|title=The Personalized A-Theory of Time and Perspective|eprint=2008.13207v1|class=physics.hist-ph}}

See also

  • {{annotated link|Philosophy of self}}
  • {{annotated link|Right to personal identity}}

= Identity<!-- (about identity of things generally, not only of persons)--> =

  • {{annotated link|Abstract and concrete}}
  • {{annotated link|Identity and change}}
  • {{annotated link|Nominal identity}}
  • {{annotated link|Personal life}}

= Continuity =

  • {{annotated link|Dōgen}}
  • {{annotated link|Hebbian theory}}
  • {{annotated link|Information-theoretic death}}
  • {{annotated link|Meme}}
  • {{annotated link|Mindstream}}
  • {{annotated link|Noumenon}}
  • {{annotated link|Neuroplasticity}} (Spike-timing-dependent plasticity)
  • {{annotated link|Perdurantism}}
  • {{annotated link|Pratītyasamutpāda}} otherwise known as dependent origination
  • {{annotated link|Process philosophy}}
  • {{annotated link|Synchronicity}}

=Other=

Notes

{{Notelist}}

References

{{Reflist|2}}

Further reading

=Books=

{{refbegin|colwidth=30em}}

  • {{citation | first=Joseph | last=Butler | date=1736 | chapter=Of personal identity | chapter-url=http://www.ummoss.org/self/butler.html | title=The Analogy of Religion}} Reprinted in {{harvtxt|Perry|2008}}.
  • Vere Claiborne Chappell, The Cambridge Companion to Locke. Cambridge University Press, 1994. 343 pages. {{ISBN|0-521-38772-8}}
  • Shaun Gallagher, Jonathan Shear, Models of the Self. Imprint Academic, 1999. 524 pages. {{ISBN|0-907845-09-6}}
  • Brian Garrett, Personal Identity and Self-Consciousness. Routledge, 1998. 137 pages. {{ISBN|0-415-16573-3}}
  • James Giles, No Self to be Found: the Search for Personal Identity. University Press of America, 1997.
  • J. Kim & E. Sosa, A Companion to Metaphysics. Blackwell, 1995, Page 380, "persons and personal identity".
  • G Kopf, Beyond Personal Identity: Dogen, Nishida, and a Phenomenology of No-Self. Routledge, 2001. {{ISBN|0-7007-1217-8}}
  • {{cite book | last=Locke | first=John | author-link=John Locke | date=1690 | chapter=Of identity and diversity | chapter-url=https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/10615/pg10615.html#id01173 | title=An essay concerning humane understanding | edition=2nd | volume=1 | publication-place=London}}
  • E. Jonathan Lowe, An Introduction to Philosophy of the Mind. Cambridge University Press, 2000.
  • E. Jonathan Lowe, The Possibility of Metaphysics: Substance, Identity, and Time. Oxford University Press, 2001. 288 pages. {{ISBN|0-19-924499-5}}
  • E. Jonathan Lowe, A Survey of Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, 2002, chapters 2,3, 4.
  • Thomas Nagel, The View from Nowhere.
  • Harold W. Noonan, Personal Identity. Routledge, 2003. 296 pages. {{ISBN|0-415-27315-3}}
  • Eric Todd Olson, The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology. Oxford University Press, 1997. 189 pages. {{ISBN|0-19-513423-0}}
  • H. B. Paksoy, [http://vlib.iue.it/carrie/texts/carrie_books/paksoy-7/ Identities: How Governed, Who Pays?] {{ISBN|0-9621379-0-1}}
  • Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons, part 3.
  • {{cite book | editor-last=Perry | editor-first=John | year=2008 | orig-year=1975 | title=Personal identity | publication-place=Berkeley | publisher=University of California Press | series=Topics in Philosophy | isbn=978-0-520-25642-2 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PIE32PrcDzUC}}
  • {{cite book | last=Perry | first=John | year=2002 | title=Identity, Personal Identity, and the Self | publication-place=Indianapolis | publisher=Hackett | isbn=978-0-87220-520-8 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=54nvGHWVfqYC}}
  • {{cite book | last=Perry | first=John | year=1978 | title=A Dialogue on Personal Identity and Immortality | publication-place=Indianapolis | publisher=Hackett | series=Hackett Philosophical Dialogues | isbn=978-0-915144-53-2}}
  • Thomas Reid, "Of identity. Of Mr. Locke's account of our personal identity". In Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. Reprinted in John Perry (ed.), Personal Identity, (2008)
  • Andrea Sauchelli, Personal Identity and Applied Ethics. London, Routledge, 2018. {{ISBN|978-1138185692}}
  • A. E. Pitson, Hume's Philosophy of the Self. Routledge, 2002. 224 pages. {{ISBN|0-415-24801-9}}
  • Mark Siderits, Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy. Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2003. 231 pages. {{ISBN|0-7546-3473-6}}
  • Marc Slors, The Diachronic Mind. Springer, 2001. 234 pages. {{ISBN|0-7923-6978-5}}

{{refend}}

= Articles =

{{refbegin|colwidth=30em}}

  • N Agar, Functionalism and Personal Identity. Nous, 2003.
  • E J Borowski, Diachronic Identity as Relative Identity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 1975.
  • SD Bozinovski, Self-Neglect Among the Elderly: Maintaining Continuity of Self. DIANE Publishing, 1998. 434 pages. {{ISBN|0-7881-7456-8}}
  • Andrew Brennan, Personal identity and personal survival. Analysis, 42, 44–50. 1982.
  • M. Chandler, C. Lalonde, B. W. Sokol, D. (Editor) (eds.) Personal Persistence, Identity Development, and Suicide. Blackwell Publishing, 2003. {{ISBN|1-4051-1879-2}}
  • WE Conn, Erikson's "identity": an essay on the psychological foundations of religious ethics.
  • J Copner,The Faith of a Realist. Williams and Norgate, 1890. 351 pages.
  • {{cite journal | last1 = Fields | first1 = Lloyd | year = 1987 | title = Parfit on personal identity and desert | journal = Philosophical Quarterly | volume = 37 | issue = 149| pages = 432–441 | doi=10.2307/2219573| jstor = 2219573 }}
  • {{cite journal | pmid = 14197795 | volume=55 | issue=3 | date=August 1964 | journal=Br J Psychol | pages=269–76 | last1 = Foulds | first1 = GA | title=Personal Continuity and Psycho-Pathological Disruption | doi=10.1111/j.2044-8295.1964.tb00910.x}}
  • {{cite journal | last1 = Garrett | first1 = Brian | year = 1990 | title = Personal identity and extrinsicness | journal = Mind | volume = 97 | pages = 105–109 }}
  • W Greve, K Rothermund, D Wentura, The Adaptive Self: Personal Continuity and Intentional Self-development. 2005.
  • J Habermas, The paradigm shift in Mead. In M. Aboulafia (Ed.), Philosophy, social theory, and the thought of George Herbert Mead 1991. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
  • GF Hellden, Personal Context and Continuity of Human Thought: Recurrent Themes in a Longitudinal Study of Students' Conceptions.
  • J Jacobson, Islam in Transition: Religion and Identity Among British Pakistani Youth. Routledge, 1998. 177 pages. {{ISBN|0-415-17085-0}}
  • M Kapstein, (Review) Collins, Parfit, and the Problem of Personal Identity in Two Philosophical Traditions. Philosophy East and West, 1986.
  • Christine M. Korsgaard, Personal Identity and the Unity of Agency: A Kantian Response to Parfit. Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 18, No. 2 (Spring, 1989), pp. 101–132.
  • JC LaVoie, Ego identity formation in middle adolescence. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 1976.
  • Michael Metzeltin, Wege zur Europäischen Identität. Individuelle, nationalstaatliche und supranationale Identitätskonstrukte, Berlin, Frank & Timme, 2010. 285 pages. {{ISBN|978-3-86596-297-3}}
  • D Mohr, Development of attributes of personal identity. Developmental Psychology, 1978.
  • {{cite journal | last1 = Parfit | first1 = Derek | year = 1971 | title = Personal identity | journal = Philosophical Review | volume = 80 | issue = 1| pages = 3–27 | doi=10.2307/2184309| jstor = 2184309 }}
  • R W Perrett, C Barton, Personal Identity, Reductionism and the Necessity of Origins. Erkenntnis, 1999.
  • Paul Ricœur, Soi-même comme un autre, 1990. Paris:Seuil. (en: Oneself as another)
  • {{cite journal | last1 = Robinson | first1 = John | year = 1988 | title = Personal identity and survival | journal = Journal of Philosophy | volume = 85 | issue = 6| pages = 319–328 | doi=10.2307/2026722| jstor = 2026722 }}
  • B Romero, Self-maintenance therapy in Alzheimer's disease. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 2001.
  • BM Ross, Remembering the Personal Past: Descriptions of Autobiographical Memory. Oxford University Press, 1991. {{ISBN|0-19-506894-7}}
  • S Seligman, RS Shanok, Subjectivity, Complexity and the Social World. Psychoanalytic Dialogues, 1995.
  • JM Shorter, More About Bodily Continuity and Personal Identity. Analysis, 1962.
  • J Sully, Illusions: A Psychological Study. Appleton, 1881. 372 pages.
  • DG Thompson, The Religious Sentiments of the Human Mind. 1888.
  • Michel Weber, "[https://www.academia.edu/1849715/_Process_and_Individuality_2008_ Process and Individuality]" in Maria Pachalska and Michel Weber (eds.), Neuropsychology and Philosophy of Mind in Process. Essays in Honor of Jason W. Brown, Frankfurt / Lancaster, Ontos Verlag, 2008, pp. 401–415.
  • Bernard Williams, Bodily Continuity and Personal Identity. Analysis, 1960.
  • Bernard Williams, The Self and the Future, in Philosophical Review 79, 1970.

{{refend}}

=Online articles=

{{refbegin|colwidth=30em}}

  • Daniel Dennett, [http://www.lehigh.edu/~mhb0/Dennett-WhereAmI.pdf Where am I?]
  • [http://www.polyarchy.org/paradigm/english/magic.html#roots Roots, Identity, Nationality] A brief critical analysis of the concept of identity
  • [http://phineasquimby.com/personal_identity.html Phineas Parkhurst Quimby on Personal Identity]
  • Max More, [http://www.maxmore.com/disscont.htm The Diachronic Self] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20040610182354/http://www.maxmore.com/disscont.htm |date=2004-06-10 }} : Identity, Continuity, Transformation.
  • Vakhtangi Makhniahvilim [http://www.ctr4process.org/publications/SeminarPapers/27-1Makhniashvili.pdf Parfit and Whitehead on personal identity].
  • [https://doi.org/10.1023%2FA%3A1005455206904 Personal Identity, Reductionism and the Necessity of Origins]. Erkenntnis. Volume 51, Numbers 2-3 / November 1999.
  • V. Chappell, [http://philosophy.fas.nyu.edu/docs/IO/1650/chappell.pdf Locke on Consciousness]. philosophy.fas.nyu.edu.
  • James Giles, [http://ccbs.ntu.edu.tw/FULLTEXT/JR-PHIL/james1.htm The No-Self Theory: Hume, Buddhism, and Personal Identity], Philosophy East and West, 1993.
  • [http://www.science.uva.nl/~seop/entries/consciousness-unity/ The Unity of Consciousness]. science.uva.nl.
  • D. Cole, [https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF00413555 Artificial intelligence and personal identity]. Synthese, 1991.
  • [http://www.benbest.com/science/anatmind/anatmd4.html Nervous system development -- network origins]. benbest.com.
  • [http://www.changesurfer.com/Hlth/BD/Brain.html 'Brain Death and Technological Change:  Personal Identity, Neural Prostheses and Uploading']
  • [http://www.ibiblio.org/jstrout/identity/ Forum on Personal Identity]
  • [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke/supplement.html The Immateriality of the Soul and Personal Identity]
  • [http://service.phil-fak.uni-duesseldorf.de/ezpublish/index.php/article/articleview/157/1/19/ 'Personal Identity and the Methodology of Imaginary Cases']
  • [http://www.uky.edu/~cperring/PIsyl.html Personal Identity Syllabus – 'The Metaphysics of Persons']
  • [http://www4.ncsu.edu/~carroll/META-SYL-S00.htm PHI 330 Homepage – Metaphysics]
  • [http://www.courses.rochester.edu/uzquiano/PHL242/index02.html PHL 242-442 – Metaphysics]
  • [http://www.philosophers.co.uk/games/identity.htm 'Staying Alive   The Personal Identity Game]
  • [http://www.lucs.lu.se/spinning/categories/moral/Tannsjo/ Tannsjo, Torbjorn – 'Morality and Personal Identity']
  • [http://www.fordham.edu/philosophy/graduate/syllabi/phga6402_topics_metaphysics.htm Topics in Metaphysics – Personal Identity]
  • [http://www.bu.edu/wcp/MainPPer.htm 20th WCP:  Persons and Personal Identity]
  • William H. Swatos, Jr. (Editor), [http://hirr.hartsem.edu/ency/identity.htm Identity]. Encyclopedia of Religion and Society.
  • [https://doi.org/10.1007%2FBF01577250 Ego identity formation in middle adolescence]. springerlink.com.
  • ''[http://individual.utoronto.ca/weisberg/phl105/docs/lecture_notes/Personal_Identity.pdf Personal Identity & Immortality]'. individual.utoronto.ca.
  • [https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC3115296/ John Locke on Personal Identity].
  • [http://www.siue.edu/~wlarkin/research/persons.html Persons, Animals, And Bodies].

{{refend}}