Physics (Aristotle)
{{Short description|Treatise by Aristotle}}
{{about|the book titled "Physics"||Physics (disambiguation)}}
{{for|a comparison with modern mathematical physics|Aristotelian physics}}
{{italic title}}
File:Aristotle Physica page 1.png appended to the title. The translation of ex is equivocal in English; it could mean "of" or "from", not helpful in this case. The image is not the original publication of Bekker's recension from which the standard Bekker numbers are derived. Indeed, Bekker numbers do not appear at all, though the recension is Bekker's, and the book and chapter numbers derived from the age of manuscripts (not known when) are used. For Bekker's arrangement, see the 1831 edition published by the Academia Regia Borussica in Berlin.{{NoteTag|An explanation of Bekker numbering along with an image of Page 184, the start of Physics, is to be found in {{cite web |title = How to Cite Aristotle |url = http://minerva.union.edu/wareht/aristotle/how_to_cite_aristotle.pdf |publisher = Union College |location = Schenectady, NY |access-date = 24 November 2017 }}}}]]
The Physics (Greek: Φυσικὴ ἀκρόασις Phusike akroasis; Latin: Physica, or Naturales Auscultationes, possibly meaning "Lectures on nature") is a named text, written in ancient Greek, collated from a collection of surviving manuscripts known as the Corpus Aristotelicum, attributed to the 4th-century BC philosopher Aristotle.
The meaning of physics in Aristotle
It is a collection of treatises or lessons that deals with the most general (philosophical) principles of natural or moving things, both living and non-living, rather than physical theories (in the modern sense) or investigations of the particular contents of the universe. The chief purpose of the work is to discover the principles and causes of (and not merely to describe) change, or movement, or motion (κίνησις kinesis), especially that of natural wholes (mostly living things, but also inanimate wholes like the cosmos). In the conventional Andronicean ordering of Aristotle's works, it stands at the head of, as well as being foundational to, the long series of physical, cosmological and biological treatises, whose ancient Greek title, τὰ φυσικά, means "the [writings] on nature" or "natural philosophy".
Description of the content
The Physics is composed of eight books, which are further divided into chapters. This system is of ancient origin, now obscure. In modern languages, books are referenced with Roman numerals, standing for ancient Greek capital letters (the Greeks represented numbers with letters, e.g. A for 1). Chapters are identified by Arabic numerals, but the use of the English word "chapter" is strictly conventional. Ancient "chapters" (capita) are generally very short, often less than a page. Additionally, the Bekker numbers give the page and column (a or b) used in the Prussian Academy of Sciences' edition of Aristotle's works, instigated and managed by Bekker himself. These are evident in the 1831 2-volume edition. Bekker's line numbers may be given. These are often given, but unless the edition is the Academy's, they do match any line counts.
=Book I (Α; 184a–192b)=
Book I introduces Aristotle's approach to nature, which is to be based on principles, causes, and elements. Before offering his particular views, he engages previous theories, such as those offered by Melissus and Parmenides. Aristotle's own view comes out in Ch. 7 where he identifies three principles: substances, opposites, and privation.
Chapters 3 and 4 are among the most difficult in all of Aristotle's works and involve subtle refutations of the thought of Parmenides, Melissus and Anaxagoras.
In chapter 5, he continues his review of his predecessors, particularly how many first principles there are. Chapter 6 narrows down the number of principles to two or three. He presents his own account of the subject in chapter 7, where he first introduces the word matter (Greek: hyle) to designate fundamental essence (ousia). He defines matter in chapter 9: "For my definition of matter is just this—the primary substratum of each thing, from which it comes to be without qualification, and which persists in the result."
Matter in Aristotle's thought is, however, defined in terms of sensible reality; for example, a horse eats grass: the horse changes the grass into itself; the grass as such does not persist in the horse, but some aspect of it{{spaced ndash}}its matter{{spaced ndash}}does. Matter is not specifically described, but consists of whatever is apart from quality or quantity and that of which something may be predicated. Matter in this understanding does not exist independently (i.e. as a substance), but exists interdependently (i.e. as a "principle") with form and only insofar as it underlies change.A good explanation: David L. Schindler, "The Problem of Mechanism" in Beyond Mechanism, ed. David L. Schindler (University Press of America, 1986), 1-12 at 3-4. Matter and form are analogical terms.
=Book II (Β; 192b–200b)=
Book II identifies "nature" (physis) as "a source or cause of being moved and of being at rest in that to which it belongs primarily" (1.192b21). Thus, those entities are natural which are capable of starting to move, e.g. growing, acquiring qualities, displacing themselves, and finally being born and dying. Aristotle contrasts natural things with the artificial: artificial things can move also, but they move according to what they are made of, not according to what they are. For example, if a wooden bed were buried and somehow sprouted as a tree, it would be according to what it is made of, not what it is. Aristotle contrasts two senses of nature: nature as matter and nature as form or definition.
By "nature", Aristotle means the natures of particular things and would perhaps be better translated "a nature." In Book II, however, his appeal to "nature" as a source of activities is more typically to the genera of natural kinds (the secondary substance). But, contra Plato, Aristotle attempts to resolve a philosophical quandary that was well understood in the fourth century.{{cite book |title=Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought |last=Hankinson |first=R. J. |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-19-924656-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iwfy-n5IWL8C |page=125}} The Eudoxian planetary model sufficed for the wandering stars, but no deduction of terrestrial substance would be forthcoming based solely on the mechanical principles of necessity, (ascribed by Aristotle to material causation in chapter 9). In the Enlightenment, centuries before modern science made good on atomist intuitions, a nominal allegiance to mechanistic materialism gained popularity despite harboring Newton's action at distance, and comprising the native habitat of teleological arguments: Machines or artifacts composed of parts lacking any intrinsic relationship to each other with their order imposed from without. Thus, the source of an apparent thing's activities is not the whole itself, but its parts. While Aristotle asserts that the matter (and parts) are a necessary cause of things{{spaced ndash}}the material cause{{spaced ndash}}he says that nature is primarily the essence or formal cause (1.193b6), that is, the information, the whole species itself.
{{blockquote
| The necessary in nature, then, is plainly what we call by the name of matter, and the changes in it. Both causes must be stated by the physicist, but especially the end; for that is the cause of the matter, not vice versa; and the end is 'that for the sake of which', and the beginning starts from the definition or essence…{{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.2.ii.html#646 |publisher=The Internet Classics Archive |title=Physics |author=Aristotle |editor=trans. by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye |at=II 9}}
|Aristotle |Physics II 9
}}
In chapter 3, Aristotle presents his theory of the four causes (material, efficient, formal, and finalFor an especially clear discussion, see chapter 6 of Mortimer Adler, Aristotle for Everybody: Difficult Thought Made Easy (1978).). Material cause explains what something is made of (for example, the wood of a house), formal cause explains the form which a thing follows to become that thing (the plans of an architect to build a house), efficient cause is the actual source of the change (the physical building of the house), and final cause is the intended purpose of the change (the final product of the house and its purpose as a shelter and home).
Of particular importance is the final cause or purpose (telos). It is a common mistake to conceive of the four causes as additive or alternative forces pushing or pulling; in reality, all four are needed to explain (7.198a22-25). What we typically mean by cause in the modern scientific idiom is only a narrow part of what Aristotle means by efficient cause.There is an excellent explanation here: Michael J. Dodds, "Science, Causality And Divine Action: Classical Principles For Contemporary Challenges," CTNS Bulletin 21.1 (Winter 2001), sect. 2-3.
He contrasts purpose with the way in which "nature" does not work, chance (or luck), discussed in chapters 4, 5, and 6. (Chance working in the actions of humans is tuche and in unreasoning agents automaton.) Something happens by chance when all the lines of causality converge without that convergence being purposefully chosen, and produce a result similar to the teleologically caused one.
In chapters 7 through 9, Aristotle returns to the discussion of nature. With the enrichment of the preceding four chapters, he concludes that nature acts for an end, and he discusses the way that necessity is present in natural things. For Aristotle, the motion of natural things is determined from within them, while in the modern empirical sciences, motion is determined from without (more properly speaking: there is nothing to have an inside).
=Book III (Γ; 200b–208a)=
In order to understand "nature" as defined in the previous book, one must understand the terms of the definition. To understand motion, book III begins with the definition of change based on Aristotle's notions of potentiality and actuality.For an overview of the topic with some interpretations of Aristotle's vocabulary, see {{cite encyclopedia | last=Sachs | first=Joe | url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/a/aris-mot.htm | title=Motion and its Place in Nature | encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy | access-date=1 December 2017}} Change, he says, is the actualization of a thing's ability insofar as it is able.{{harvnb|Brague|1990}}
The rest of the book (chapters 4-8) discusses the infinite (apeiron, the unlimited). He distinguishes between the infinite by addition and the infinite by division, and between the actually infinite and potentially infinite. He argues against the actually infinite in any form, including infinite bodies, substances, and voids. Aristotle here says the only type of infinity that exists is the potentially infinite. Aristotle characterizes this as that which serves as "the matter for the completion of a magnitude and is potentially (but not actually) the completed whole" (207a22-23). The infinite, lacking any form, is thereby unknowable. Aristotle writes, "it is not what has nothing outside it that is infinite, but what always has something outside it" (6.206b33-207a1-2).
=Book IV (Δ; 208a–223b)=
Book IV discusses the preconditions of motion: place (topos, chapters 1-5), void (kenon, chapters 6-9), and time (khronos, chapters 10-14). The book starts by distinguishing the various ways a thing can "be in" another. He likens place to an immobile container or vessel: "the innermost motionless boundary of what contains" is the primary place of a body (4.212a20). Unlike space, which is a volume co-existent with a body, place is a boundary or surface.
He teaches that, contrary to the Atomists and others, a void is not only unnecessary, but leads to contradictions, e.g., making locomotion impossible.
Time is a constant attribute of movements and, Aristotle thinks, does not exist on its own but is relative to the motions of things. Tony Roark describes Aristotle's view of time as follows:
Aristotle defines time as "a number of motion with respect to the before and after" (Phys. 219b1–2), by which he intends to denote motion's susceptibility to division into undetached parts of arbitrary length, a property that it possesses both by virtue of its intrinsic nature and also by virtue of the capacities and activities of percipient souls. Motion is intrinsically indeterminate, but perceptually determinable, with respect to its length. Acts of perception function as determiners; the result is determinate units of kinetic length, which is precisely what a temporal unit is.{{harvnb|Roark|2011|p=1}}
=Books V and VI (Ε: 224a–231a; Ζ: 231a–241b)=
Books V and VI deal with how motion occurs. Book V classifies four species of movement, depending on where the opposites are located. Movement categories include quantity (e.g. a change in dimensions, from great to small), quality (as for colors: from pale to dark), place (local movements generally go from up downwards and vice versa), or, more controversially, substance. In fact, substances do not have opposites, so it is inappropriate to say that something properly becomes, from not-man, man: generation and corruption are not kinesis in the full sense.
Book VI discusses how a changing thing can reach the opposite state, if it has to pass through infinite intermediate stages. It investigates by rational and logical arguments the notions of continuity and division, establishing that change—and, consequently, time and place—are not divisible into indivisible parts; they are not mathematically discrete but continuous, that is, infinitely divisible (in other words, that you cannot build up a continuum out of discrete or indivisible points or moments). Among other things, this implies that there can be no definite (indivisible) moment when a motion begins. This discussion, together with that of speed and the different behavior of the four different species of motion, eventually helps Aristotle answer the famous paradoxes of Zeno, which purport to show the absurdity of motion's existence.
=Book VII (Η; 241a25–250b7)=
Book VII briefly deals with the relationship of the moved to his mover, which Aristotle describes in substantial divergence with Plato's theory of the soul as capable of setting itself in motion (Laws book X, Phaedrus, Phaedo). Everything which moves is moved by another. He then tries to correlate the species of motion and their speeds, with the local change (locomotion, phorà) as the most fundamental to which the others can be reduced.
Book VII.1-3 also exist in an alternative version, not included in the Bekker edition.
=Book VIII (Θ; 250a14–267b26)=
Book VIII (which occupies almost a fourth of the entire Physics, and probably constituted originally an independent course of lessons) discusses two main topics, though with a wide deployment of arguments: the time limits of the universe, and the existence of a Prime Mover — eternal, indivisible, without parts and without magnitude. Isn't the universe eternal, has it had a beginning, will it ever end? Aristotle's response, as a Greek, could hardly be affirmative, never having been told of a creatio ex nihilo, but he also has philosophical reasons for denying that motion had not always existed, on the grounds of the theory presented in the earlier books of the Physics. Eternity of motion is also confirmed by the existence of a substance which is different from all the others in lacking matter; being pure form, it is also in an eternal actuality, not being imperfect in any respect; hence needing not to move. This is demonstrated by describing the celestial bodies thus: the first things to be moved must undergo an infinite, single and continuous movement, that is, circular. This is not caused by any contact but (integrating the view contained in the Metaphysics, bk. XII) by love and aspiration.
Significance to philosophy and science in the modern world
The works of Aristotle are typically influential to the development of Western science and philosophy.{{cite book | quote=Aristotle's Physics is the hidden, and therefore never adequately studied, foundational book of Western philosophy. | first=Martin | last=Heidegger | chapter=On the Essence and Concept of φὐσις in Aristotle's Physics Β, 1 | title=Pathmarks | url=https://archive.org/details/pathmarks00heid_123 | url-access=limited | editor-first=William | editor-last=McNeill | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1998 | pages=[https://archive.org/details/pathmarks00heid_123/page/n198 183]–230, 185}} (Emphasis in original). The citations below are not given as any sort of final modern judgement on the interpretation and significance of Aristotle, but are only the notable views of some moderns.
= Heidegger =
Martin Heidegger writes:
{{blockquote
| The Physics is a lecture in which he seeks to determine beings that arise on their own, τὰ φύσει ὄντα, with regard to their being. Aristotelian "physics" is different from what we mean today by this word, not only to the extent that it belongs to antiquity whereas the modern physical sciences belong to modernity, rather above all it is different by virtue of the fact that Aristotle's "physics" is philosophy, whereas modern physics is a positive science that presupposes a philosophy.... This book determines the warp and woof of the whole of Western thinking, even at that place where it, as modern thinking, appears to think at odds with ancient thinking. But opposition is invariably {{sic|comprised |hide=y|of}} a decisive, and often even perilous, dependence. Without Aristotle's Physics there would have been no Galileo.{{cite book | first=Martin | last=Heidegger | author-link=Martin Heidegger | title=The Principle of Reason | translator-first=Reginald | translator-last=Lilly | location=Bloomington | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1991 | series=Studies in Continental Thought | pages=62–63 | isbn=0253210666 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=rWDUmlA6M98C&pg=PA63}}
}}
= Russell =
Bertrand Russell says of Physics and On the Heavens (which he believed was a continuation of Physics) that they were:
{{blockquote
| ...extremely influential, and dominated science until the time of Galileo ... The historian of philosophy, accordingly, must study them, in spite of the fact that hardly a sentence in either can be accepted in the light of modern science.{{cite book |title=The History of Western Philosophy |first=Bertrand |last=Russell |year=1946 |page=226 | location=London | publisher=George Allen & Unwin Ltd. |url=https://archive.org/stream/westernphilosoph035502mbp#page/n233}}
}}
= Rovelli =
Italian theoretical physicist Carlo Rovelli considers Aristotle's physics as a correct and non-intuitive special case of Newtonian physics for the motion of matter in fluid after it has reached terminal velocity (steady state). His theory disregards the initial phase of acceleration, which is too short to be observed by the naked eye. Galileo's inclined plane experiment bypasses the issue, as it slows down acceleration enough to allow observing the initial phase of acceleration by the naked eye.
The five elements explain forms of observed motions. Ether explains circular motion in the sky, earth and water explains downward motion, and fire and air explains upward motion. To explain downward motion, instead of postulating one element, he proposed two, because wood moves up in water but down in air, while earth moves down in both water and air. The complex interaction between the 4 elements could explain most of the rising and falling motions of objects with different densities.
The velocity of falling objects is equal to , where is the weight of the object, is the density of the surrounding fluid (such as air, fire, or water), is a constant, and is a constant depending on the shape of the object. This is correct for the terminal velocity of falling objects in fluid in a constant gravitational field, in the case where most of the fluid resistance is drag force, . In this case, the terminal velocity is {{Cite journal |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |date=2015 |title=Aristotle's Physics: A Physicist's Look |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S2053447714000116/type/journal_article |journal=Journal of the American Philosophical Association |language=en |volume=1 |issue=1 |pages=23–40 |doi=10.1017/apa.2014.11 |issn=2053-4477|arxiv=1312.4057 }}
See also
Notes
{{NoteFoot}}
References
{{reflist|colwidth=30em}}
Bibliography
= Recensions of ''Physics'' in the ancient Greek =
A recension is a selection of a specific text for publication. The manuscripts on a given work attributed to Aristotle offer textual variants. One recension makes a selection of one continuous text, but typically gives notes stating the alternative sections of text. Determining which text is to be presented as "original" is a detailed scholarly investigation. The recension is often known by its scholarly editor's name.
{{div col |colwidth=30em}}
- Aristotle, Physics. Greek text with translation by P. H. Wicksteed, F. M. Cornford. Loeb Classical Library 228, 255. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1934–57.
- Aristotle, Physica. Ed. W. D. Ross. Oxford University Press, 1951. ISBN 9780198145141.
- {{cite book | editor=W.D. Ross | author=Aristotle | title=Aristotle's Physics. A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary| location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1936 |doi=10.1017/S0009840X00076721| s2cid=162514411 }}
- {{cite book | author=Aristotelis | title=Volumen Secundum Continens Ethica, Naturalem Auscultationem, de Caelo, de Generatione et Metaphysica, cum Indice Nominum et Rerum | series=Opera Omnia | year=1879 | language=grc, la | location=Parisiis | publisher=Editore Ambrosio Firmin Didot | url=https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=njp.32101073249078;view=1up;seq=9}}
- {{cite book| series=Aristotelis Opera; Accedunt Indices Syllburgiani | author1=Aristotle | author2=Fredericus Syllburgius | author2-link=Friedrich Sylburg | volume=Tomus II | language=grc | location=Oxonii | publisher=E Typographeo Academico | year=1837 | title=Naturalis Auscultationis Libri VIII; De Caelo Libri IV; De Generatione et Corruptione Libri II | editor-first=Immanuelis | editor-last=Bekkeri | editor-link=August Immanuel Bekker}}
- {{cite book | author1=Aristotle | author2=Fredericus Syllburgius | year=1837 | title=Naturalis Auscultationis Libri VIII; De Caelo Libri IV; De Generatione et Corruptione Libri II | publisher=Internet Archive | url=https://archive.org/stream/AristotleworksIvAristotelisOperaGraece11Vols.2VolsComb.indices/02.AristotelisOpera.Graec.v2.NatAusPhysiicsL8.CoelL4.GenCorL2.IndicSylburg.RecBekker.Oxon.1837.#page/n9/mode/2up | author1-mask=2 | author2-mask=2 }} Different formats for display and downloading are available.
- {{cite book | author1=Aristotle | author2=Fredericus Syllburgius | year=1837 | title=Naturalis Auscultationis Libri VIII; De Caelo Libri IV; De Generatione et Corruptione Libri II | publisher=Institute for the Study of Nature | url=http://www.isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/Bekker_v2.pdf | author1-mask=2 | author2-mask=2 }} A pdf file.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotelis | title=Physicorum Libri VIII | series=Aristotelis Opera Omnia {{nowrap|V. I}} | year=1831 | location=Lipsiae | publisher=Sumptibus et Typis Car. Tauchnitii |url=https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=njp.32101079238174;view=1up;seq=7 | language=grc}}
- {{cite book | author=Aristoteles | title=ΦΥΣΙΚΗΣ ΑΚΡΟΑΣΕΩΣ | language=grc | editor=Immanuelis Bekkeri | editor-link=August Immanuel Bekker | volume=Prius | location=Berolini | publisher=Academia Regia Borussica (Prussian Academy of Sciences) | year=1831 | url=http://www.isnature.org/Files/Aristotle/Bekker_Physics.pdf}}
{{colend}}
= English translations of the ''Physics'' =
In reverse chronological order:
{{div col |colwidth=30em}}
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | translator-first=C. D. C. | translator-last= Reeve | title=Physics | location= Cambridge, MA | publisher=Hackett Publishing Company | year=2018}}
- {{cite book | translator1-first=R.P. | translator1-last=Hardie | translator2-first=R.K. | translator2-last=Gaye | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | editor-first=Gregory | editor-last=Koutrouby | publisher=Dover Publications | year=2017 | isbn=978-0-486-81351-6}} A republication of the 1930 edition. Available as an ebook.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | translator-first=Glen | translator-last=Coughlin | title=Physics, or, Natural Hearing | location=South Bend | publisher=St. Augustine's Press | year=2005}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Robin | translator-last=Waterfield | title=Physics | editor-first=David | editor-last=Bostock | author=Aristotle | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1999}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Daniel W. | translator-last=Graham | author=Aristotle | title=Physics: Book VIII | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1999 | series=Clarendon Aristotle Series | url=https://www.scribd.com/document/362536523/Aristotle-Graham-Physics-VIII}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Joe | translator-last=Sachs | author=Aristotle | title=Aristotle's Physics: A Guided Study | location=New Brunswick, NJ | publisher=Rutgers University Press | year=1995}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=William | translator-last=Charlton | author=Aristotle | title=Physics: Books I and II | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1984 | series=Clarendon Aristotle Series}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Edward | translator-last=Hussey | author=Aristotle | title=Physics: Books III and IV | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1983 | series=Clarendon Aristotle Series}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Hippocrates G. | translator-last=Apostle | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | location=Bloomington | publisher=Indiana University Press | year=1969}}
- {{cite book | translator-first=Richard | translator-last=Hope | author=Aristotle | title=Aristotle's Physics; with an Analytical Index of Technical Terms | location=Lincoln | publisher=University of Nebraska Press | year=1961 | url=http://addsdonna.com/old-website/ADDS_DONNA/Greek_Literature_files/Aristole%20Physics_Part%201.pdf}}
- {{cite book | translator-link=Charles Glenn Wallis | translator-first=Charles Glenn | translator-last=Wallis | author=Aristotle | title=Lectures on the Science of Natures, Books I-IV | location=Annapolis | publisher=The St. John's Bookstore | year=1940 | oclc=37790727}} Also includes On Coming-To-Be and Ceasing-To-Be I.4-5; On The Generation Of Animals I.22.
- {{cite book | translator-link=Philip Wheelwright | translator-first=Philip | translator-last=Wheelwright | title=Aristotle; containing selections from seven of the most important books of Aristotle ... Natural science, the Metaphysics, Zoology, Psychology, the Nicomachean ethics, On statecraft, and the Art of poetry | author=Aristotle | location=New York | publisher=Odyssey Press | year=1935 | oclc=3363066}} Includes Physics I-II, III.1, VIII.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics Books 5-8| translator1-first=P.H. | translator1-last=Wicksteed | translator1-link=Philip Wicksteed | translator2-first=F.M. | translator2-last=Cornford | translator2-link=F. M. Cornford | year=1934 | location=Cambridge, Massachusetts | publisher=Harvard University Press | series=Loeb Classical Library 255}} This is the oldest of Loeb 255, reprinted or reissued many times subsequently under different subseries: Volume 5 of a 23-volume Aristotle set or Volume 2 of a 2-volume Aristotle Physics set. The terminology Volume 5, Volume 2, Volume 255 is apt to be confusing. Whatever the volume and printing date, Loeb 255 is still in copyright and therefore cannot be offered as a work in the public domain.
- {{cite book | translator1-first=R.P. | translator1-last=Hardie | translator2-first=R.K. | translator2-last=Gaye | author=Aristotle | chapter=Physica | title=The Works of Aristotle | volume=II | editor-first=W.D. | editor-last=Ross | editor-link=W. D. Ross | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=1930}}
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physica | publisher=Internet Archive | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=https://archive.org/details/workstranslatedi02arisuoft}} Scanned as is. Includes the translators' emphases and divisions within chapters.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | publisher=University of Adelaide Library | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/physics/complete.html | access-date=2017-11-16 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140929200445/https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/physics/complete.html | archive-date=2014-09-29 | url-status=dead }} Formatted text divided into books and chapters only.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | publisher=Internet Classics Archive | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html | access-date=2008-10-26 | archive-date=2011-01-06 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110106095547/http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.html | url-status=dead }} Minimally formatted text divided into books and "parts." Book IV is incomplete.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=07. Aristotle, Physics: Entire | publisher=Wildman's Weird Wild Web (a professorial site at Boston University) | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=http://people.bu.edu/wwildman/WeirdWildWeb/courses/wphil/wphil_readings.htm}} Single text file arranged in paragraphs.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | publisher=Greek Texts | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=http://www.greektexts.com/library/Aristotle/Physics/eng/index.html}} Minimally formatted single pages accessed one at a time.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics | publisher=PinkMonkey.com | year=1930 | author-mask=2 | url=http://pinkmonkey.com/dl/library1/aris20.pdf}} Single pdf file of books and chapters.
- {{cite book | author=Aristotle | title=Physics Books 1-4 | translator1-first=P.H. | translator1-last=Wicksteed | translator1-link=Philip Wicksteed | translator2-first=F.M. | translator2-last=Cornford | translator2-link=F. M. Cornford | year=1929 | location=Cambridge, Massachusetts | publisher=Harvard University Press | series=Loeb Classical Library 228}} This is the oldest of Loeb 228, reprinted or reissued many times subsequently under different subseries: Volume 4 of a 23-volume Aristotle set or Volume 1 of a 2-volume Aristotle Physics set. The terminology Volume 4, Volume 1, Volume 228 is apt to be confusing. Whatever the volume and printing date, Loeb 228 is still in copyright and therefore cannot be offered as a work in the public domain.
- {{cite book | translator-link=Thomas Taylor (neoplatonist) | translator-first=Thomas | translator-last=Taylor | author1=Aristotle | author1-link=Aristotle | author2=Simplicius | author2-link=Simplicius of Cilicia | title=The Physics or Physical Auscultation of Aristotle. Translated from the Greek with Copious Notes, in Which the Substance is given of the Invaluable Commentaries of Simplicius. | series=Collected works.English.Taylor | year=1806 | location=London | publisher=Robert Wiles | hdl=2027/nyp.33433000341705 }}
{{div col end}}
= Classical and medieval commentaries on the ''Physics'' =
A commentary differs from a note in being a distinct work analyzing the language and subsumed concepts of some other work classically notable. A note appears within the annotated work on the same page or in a separate list. Commentaries are typically arranged by lemmas, or quotes from the notable work, followed by an analysis of the author of the commentary.
The commentaries on every work of Aristotle are a vast and mainly unpublished topic. They extend continuously from the death of the philosopher, representing the entire history of Graeco-Roman philosophy. There are thousands of commentators and commentaries known wholly or more typically in fragments of manuscripts. The latter especially occupy the vaults of institutions formerly responsible for copying them, such as monasteries. The process of publishing them is slow and ongoing.
Below is a brief representative bibliography of published commentaries on Aristotle's Physics available on or through the Internet. Like the topic itself, they are perforce multi-cultural, but English has been favored, as well as the original languages, ancient Greek and Latin.
{{div col |colwidth=30em}}
- {{cite book|last=Aquinas|first=Thomas|author-link=Thomas Aquinas|title=Commentary on Aristotle's Physics|translator1=Richard J. Blackwell|translator2=Richard J. Spath|translator3=W. Edmund Thirlkel|location=Notre Dame, Indiana|publisher=Dumb Ox Books|year=1999|url=https://archive.org/details/commentaryonaris0000thom}}
- {{cite book|author=Averroes|author-link=Averroes|title=Averroes' questions in physics: from the unpublished Sêfer ha-derûšîm ha-tibʼîyîm|translator=Helen Tunik Goldstein|location=Dordrecht; Boston|publisher=Kluwer Academic Publishers|year=1991}}
- {{cite book|author-last=Buridani|author-first=Johanis|author-link=Jean Buridan|title=Acutissimi philosophi reverendi magistri Johannis Buridani subtilissime questiones super octo Phisicorum libros Aristotelis diligenter recognite et revise a magistro Johanne Dullaert de Gandavo antea nusquam impresse|language=la|year=1509|location=Parhisiis|publisher=Opera ac industria magistri P. Ledru, impensis ... D. Roce|editor-first=Johanne |editor-last=Dullaert|url=https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=uc1.a0007671027;view=1up;seq=8}}
- {{cite book|author=Conimbricenses|author-link=Conimbricenses|title=Commentarii Collegii Conimbricensis Societatis Iesu. In octo libros Physicorum Aristotelis Stagiritae.|location=Conimbricae|publisher=typis et expensis Antonij à Mariz|year=1592|url=http://purl.pt/23056/1/index.html#/1/html|language=la}}
- {{cite book|author1=Jean de Jandun|author1-link=John of Jandun|author2=Elias Cretensis|author2-link=Elia del Medigo|title=Ioannis de Ianduno ... Super octo libros Aristotelis De physico auditu subtilissimae quaestiones: ... Eliae etiam hebraei Cretensis Quaestiones: uidelicet de primo motore, de mundi efficientia, de esse & essentia, & uno cum eiusdem in dictis Averrois super eosdem libros annotationibus quàm castigatissimae leguntur duo demum horum onium extant indices: alter questionum ac conclusionum singulorum librorum nuper additus, alter totius operis notabilia quaeque accuratissime demonstrans: ...|year=1551|location=Venetiis|publisher=apud Iuntas|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PXAAJ8zVSfsC|language=la}}
- {{cite book|author=Johannis maioris hadigtonani theologi|author-link=John Major (philosopher)|title=Octo libri physicorum, cum philosophia atque metaphysica|language=la|location=Parisiensis|publisher=a Johanne Paruo|year=1526|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=du5OAAAAcAAJ}}
- {{cite book|author=William of Ockham|author-link=William of Ockham|title=Philosophical Writings: A Selection|translator=Philotheus Boehner|translator-link=Philotheus Boehner|editor=Stephen F. Brown|publisher=Hackett Publishing Company|location=Indianapolis; Cambridge|year=1990|chapter=I. On the Notion of Knowledge or Science (Prologus in Expositionem super viii libros Physicorum)|language=la, en}}
- {{cite book|author=William of Ockham|author-link=William of Ockham|title=Ockham on Aristotle's Physics; A Translation of Ockham's Brevis Summa Libri Physicorum|translator=Julian Davies|editor=George Marcil|series=Text Series No. 17|location=St. Bonaventure, New York|publisher=The Franciscan Institute|year=1989|isbn=9781576590607 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RlHZAAAAMAAJ&q=Ockham+on+Aristotle%27s+Physics:+A+Translation+of+Ockham%27s+Brevis+Summa+Libri+Physicorum|author-mask=2}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator=Catherine Osborne|title=On Aristotle Physics 1.1-3|location=Ithaca, N.Y.|publisher=Cornell University Press|year=2006}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator=Catherine Osborne|title=On Aristotle Physics 1.4-9|location=London|publisher=Duckworth|year=2009|author-mask=2|editor-mask=2}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator=A.R. Lacey|title=On Aristotle Physics 2|location=Ithaca, N.Y.|publisher=Cornell University Press|year=1993|author-mask=2|editor-mask=2}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator=M.I. Edwards|title=On Aristotle Physics 3|location=Ithaca, N.Y.|publisher=Cornell University Press|year=1994|author-mask=2|editor-mask=2}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator1=Keimpe Algra|translator1-link=Keimpe Algra|translator2=Johannes M. van Ophuijsen|title=On Aristotle Physics 4.1-5|location=London|publisher=Bristol Classical Press|year=2012|author-mask=2|editor-mask=2}}
- {{cite book|author=Philoponus|author-link=John Philoponus|editor=Richard Sorabji|editor-link=Richard Sorabji|series=Ancient Commentators on Aristotle|translator=Pamela M. Huby|title=On Aristotle Physics 4.6-9|location=London|publisher=Bristol Classical Press|year=2012|author-mask=2|editor-mask=2}}
- Ramus, Petrus (Pierre de la Ramée), Scholarum physicarum libro octo... (Frankfurt: A Wecheli, 1683).
- Simplicius, On Aristotle's Physics, trans. (various) (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, Ancient Commentators on Aristotle series, 1993–2006).
- Romanus, Aegidius (Giles of Rome), In Octo Libros Physicorum Aristoteles (Venedig, 1502; Frankfurt: Minerva GMBH, 1968).
- Soto, Domingo de, Super octo libros physicorum Aristotelis quaestiones (Salamanca, 1555).
- Themistius, On the Physics (London: Bristol Classical Press, 2012).
{{div col end}}
= Some modern commentaries, monographs and articles =
{{div col |colwidth=30em}}
- {{cite book | last=Bolotin | first=David | title=An approach to Aristotle's physics: with particular attention to the role of his manner of writing | location=New York State | publisher=SUNY Press | year=1997}}
- {{cite book | last=Bostock | first=David | title=Space, Time, Matter, and Form: Essays on Aristotle's'' Physics | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=2006 | series=Oxford Aristotle Studies}}
- {{cite journal | author-link=Rémi Brague | last=Brague | first=Rémi | translator1=Pierre Adler | translator2=Laurent d'Ursel | title=Aristotle's Definition of Motion and Its Ontological Implications | journal=Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal | volume=13 | number=2 | year=1990 | pages=1–22 | doi=10.5840/gfpj19901321}} Aristotle's definition of motion, meaning any sort of a change, a technical concept from the Theory of Matter and Form, is especially difficult for moderns unfamiliar with the philosophy to understand. It is the actualization (the becoming visible) of a new instance of a form (or system of forms) in matter that has a potency (capability to receive) for it. Brague makes the attempt to elucidate to moderns.
- {{cite book | last=Connell | first=Richard J. | title=Matter and Becoming | url=https://archive.org/details/matterbecoming0000conn | url-access=registration | location=Chicago | publisher=Priory Press | year=1966}}
- {{cite book | last=Connell | first=Richard J. | title=Nature's Causes | location=New York | publisher=P. Lang | year=1995 | series=Revisioning Philosophy; Vol. 21 | author-mask=2}}
- {{cite book | last=Coope | first=Ursula | title=Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10–14 | location=Oxford | publisher=University Press | year=2005}}
- {{cite web | title=The Rediscovery of the Corpus Aristotelicum and the Birth of Aristotelianism | first=Raul | last=Corazzon | website=Theory and History of Ontology | year=2016 | url=https://www.ontology.co/pdf/corpus-aristotelicum.pdf}}
- {{cite book | editor-last=Gerson | editor-first=Lloyd P. | title=Aristotle: Critical Assessments | volume=2: Physics, Cosmology and Biology | location=New York | publisher=Routledge | year=1999}} Collects these papers:
- {{cite journal | author-link=Bas C. van Fraassen | first=Bas C. | last=Van Fraassen | title=A Re-examination of Aristotle's Philosophy of Science | journal=Dialogue | volume=19 | number=1 | year=1980 | pages=20–45 | doi=10.1017/s0012217300024719| s2cid=170882853 }}
- {{cite journal | first=Alan | last=Code | title=The Persistence of Aristotelian Matter | journal=Philosophical Studies | volume=29 | number=6 | year=1976 | pages=357–67 | doi=10.1007/bf00646313| s2cid=171045703 }}
- {{cite journal | first=Aryeh | last=Kosman |author-link=Aryeh Kosman | title=Aristotle's Definition of Motion | journal=Phronesis | volume=14 | number=1 | year=1969 | pages=40–62 | url=https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/e9a9/84d8dd3b317fe43502fd62059ad0e2042da3.pdf | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171207191930/https://pdfs.semanticscholar.org/e9a9/84d8dd3b317fe43502fd62059ad0e2042da3.pdf | url-status=dead | archive-date=2017-12-07 | doi=10.1163/156852869x00037| s2cid=9607748 }}
- {{cite journal | first=Daniel W. | last=Graham | title=Aristotle's Definition of Motion | journal=Ancient Philosophy | volume=8 | number=2 | year=1988 | pages=209–15 | doi=10.5840/ancientphil1988824}}
- {{cite journal | first=Sheldon M. | last=Cohen | title=Aristotle on Elemental Motion | journal=Phronesis | volume=39 | number=2 | year=1994 | pages=150–9 | doi=10.1163/156852894321052153}}
- {{cite journal | first1=Michael | last1=Bradie | first2=Fred D. Jr. | last2=Miller | title=Teleology and Natural Necessity in Aristotle | journal=History of Philosophy Quarterly | volume=1 | number=2 | year=1984 | pages=133–46}}
- {{cite journal | first=Susan Sauve | last=Meyer | title=Aristotle, Teleology, and Reduction | journal=The Philosophical Review | volume=101 | number=4 | year=1992 | pages=791–825 | doi=10.2307/2185925| jstor=2185925 }}
- {{cite journal | author-link=James G. Lennox | first=James G. | last=Lennox | title=Aristotle on Chance | journal=Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie | volume=66 | number=1 | year=1984 | pages=52–60 | doi=10.1515/agph.1984.66.1.52| s2cid=144352743 }}
- {{cite journal | author-link=Mary Louise Gill | first=Mary Louise | last=Gill | title=Aristotle's Theory of Causal Action in "Physics III 3" | journal=Phronesis | volume=25 | number=1 | year=1980 | pages=129–47 | doi=10.1163/156852880x00089}}
- {{cite journal | first=David | last=Bostock | title=Aristotle's Account of Time | journal=Phronesis | volume=25 | number=2 | year=1980 | pages=148–69| doi=10.1163/156852880X00098 }}
- {{cite journal | first=David | last=Bostock | title=Aristotle on the Transmutation of the Elements in De Generatione et Corruptione 1.1–4 | journal=Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy | volume=13 | year=1995 | pages=217–29 | doi=10.1093/oso/9780198250005.003.0010 | isbn=978-0-19-825000-5 | author-mask=2}}
- {{cite journal |author=Brad Inwood |title=1996.6.6, Taylor, ed., Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XIII |journal=Bryn Mawr Classical Review |url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/1996/96.06.06.html}}
- {{cite journal | first=Cynthia A. | last=Freeland |author-link1=Cynthia Freeland| title=Scientific Explanation and Empirical Data in Aristotle's Meteorology | journal=Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy | volume=8 | year=1990 | pages=67–102}}
- {{cite journal | first1=Mohan | last1=Matthen | first2=R.J. | last2=Hankinson | title=Aristotle's Universe: Its Form and Matter | journal=Synthese | volume=96 | number=3 | year=1993 | pages=417–35 | doi=10.1007/bf01064010| s2cid=46967012 }}
- {{cite journal | first=David | last=Charles | title=Aristotle on Substance, Essence and Biological Kinds | journal=Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy | volume=7 | number=1 | year=1991 | pages=227–61 | doi=10.1163/2213441791x00132}}
- {{cite journal | first=Herbert | last=Granger | title=Aristotle on Genus and Differentia | journal=Journal of the History of Philosophy | volume=22 | year=1984 | pages=1–23 | doi=10.1353/hph.1984.0001| s2cid=171032584 }}
- {{cite journal | first=Mohan | last=Matthen | title=The Four Causes in Aristotle's Embryology | journal=Apeiron | volume=22 | year=1989 | issue=4 | pages=159–79 | doi=10.1515/apeiron.1989.22.4.159| s2cid=171238235 }}
- {{cite journal | first=Alan | last=Code | title=Soul as Efficient Cause in Aristotle's Embryology' | journal=Philosophical Topics | volume=15 | number=2 | year=1987 | pages=51–59 | doi=10.5840/philtopics19871524}}
- {{cite journal | first=David J. | last=Depew | title=Human and Other Political Animals in Aristotle's 'History of Animals' | journal=Phronesis | volume=40 | year=1995 | issue=2 | pages=156–81 | url=https://works.bepress.com/david_depew/23/ | doi=10.1163/156852895321051937}}
- {{cite journal | first=Daryl McGowan | last=Tress | title=The Metaphysical Science of Aristotle's 'Generation of Animals' and its Feminist Critics | journal=Review of Metaphysics | volume=46 | year=1992 | pages=307–41 | isbn=9780415916028 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=czXMikid3OAC&q=The+Metaphysical+Science+of+Aristotle%27s+%27Generation+of+Animals%27+and+its+Feminist+Critics&pg=PA31}}
- {{cite journal | first=Rosamond Kent | last=Sprague | title=Plants as Aristotelian Substances | journal=Illinois Classical Studies | volume=56 | year=1991 | pages=221–9 | url=https://www.ideals.illinois.edu/bitstream/handle/2142/12292/illinoisclassica151991SPRAGUE.pdf?sequence=2}}
- {{cite book | first=George | last=Grote | editor1-first=Alexander | editor1-last=Bain | editor2-first=G.Croom | editor2-last=Robertson | author-link=George Grote | title=Aristotle | edition=2nd | year=1880 | location=London | publisher=John Murray | url=https://archive.org/details/aristotleedbyab00grotgoog}}
- {{cite book | editor-last=Judson | editor-first=Lindsay | title=Aristotle's Physics: a collection of essays | location=New York | publisher=Oxford University Press | year=1991}}
- {{cite book | last=Kouremenos | first=Theokritos | title=The proportions in Aristotle's Phys.7.5 | location=Stuttgart | publisher=Franz Steiner Verlag | year=2002 | series=Paligenesia, 76}}
- {{cite book | last=Lang | first=Helen S. | title=Aristotle's Physics and its Medieval Varieties | location=Albany | publisher=State University of New York (SUNY) | year=1992 | doi=10.1086/356750}}
- {{cite journal |author=Andre Goddu |date=March 1994 |title=Aristotle's Physics and Its Medieval Varieties. Helen S. Lang |journal=Isis |volume=85 |issue=1 |pages=146, 147 |doi=10.1086/356750}}
- {{cite book | last=Lang | first=Helen S. | title=The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1998 | doi=10.1086/432288 | author-mask=2}}
- {{cite journal |author=Monte Johnson |date=December 2004 |title=Helen S. Lang. The Order of Nature in Aristotle's Physics: Place and the Elements |journal=Isis |volume=95 |issue=4 |pages=687, 688 |doi=10.1086/432288}}
- {{cite book | first=John Patrick | last=Lynch | title=Aristotle's School: A Study of a Greek Educational Institution | location=Berkeley | publisher=University of California Press | year=1972}}
- {{cite book | author1-link=Ernan McMullin | last1=MacMullin | first1=Ernan | first2=Joseph | last2=Bobik | title=The Concept of Matter in Greek and Medieval Philosophy | location=Notre Dame | publisher=University of Notre Dame Press | year=1965}}
- Maritain, Jacques, Science and Wisdom, trans. Bernard Wall (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1954).
- Morison, Benjamin, On Location: Aristotle's Concept of Place (Oxford University Press, 2002).
- {{cite journal | author-first=Joseph A. | author-last=Novak | title=Abduction and Aristotle's Library | journal=Proceedings of the Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation Conference | volume=4 | year=2001 | publisher=University of Windsor | url=http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1670&context=ossaarchive}}
- Reizler, Kurt, Physics and Reality (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1940).
- {{cite book | title=Aristotle on Time: A Study of the Physics | first=Tony | last=Roark | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=2011}}
- {{cite journal | author-link=Friedrich Solmsen | last=Solmsen | first=Friedrich | title=Aristotle and Prime Matter: A Reply to Hugh R. King | journal=Journal of the History of Ideas | volume=19 | number=2 | year=1958 | pages=243–252 | doi=10.2307/2707937| jstor=2707937 }}
- {{cite book | author-link=Friedrich Solmsen | last=Solmsen | first=Friedrich | title=Aristotle's System of the Physical World: A Comparison with His Predecessors | location=Ithaca, NY | publisher=Cornell University Press | year=1960 | series=Cornell studies in classical philology, 33 | author-mask=2}}
- {{cite book | author-link=Friedrich Solmsen | last=Solmsen | first=Friedrich | chapter=Aristotle's Word for Matter | title=Didascaliæ: Studies in Honor of Anselm M. Albareda Prefect of the Vatican Library | editor-first=Sesto | editor-last=Prete | location=New York | year=1961a | publisher=Bernard M. Rosenthal | pages=393–408 | author-mask=2}} Alborado's birth name was Joaquín Albareda y Ramoneda.
- {{cite journal | author-link=Friedrich Solmsen | last=Solmsen | first=Friedrich | title=Misplaced Passages at the End of Aristotle's Physics | journal=American Journal of Philology | volume=82 | number=3 | year=1961b | pages=270–282 | author-mask=2 | doi=10.2307/292369| jstor=292369 }}
- Smith, Vincent Edward, The General Science of Nature (Milwaukee: The Bruce Publishing Company, 1958).
- Smith, Vincent Edward, Philosophical Physics (New York: Harper & Brothers, 1950).
- {{cite book | last=Wardy | first=Robert | title=The Chain of Change: A study of Aristotle's Physics VII | url=https://archive.org/details/chainofchangestu0000ward | url-access=registration |location=Cambridge; New York | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1990| isbn=9780521373272 }}
- {{cite book | first=Walter | last=Watson | title=The Lost Second Book of Aristotle's Poetics | location=Chicago; London | publisher=University of Chicago Press | year=2012}}
- {{cite book | last=White | first=Michael J. | title=The Continuous and the Discrete: Ancient Physical Theories from a Contemporary Perspective | location=Oxford | publisher=Clarendon Press | year=1992}}
- {{cite book | first=Eduard | last=Zeller | author-link=Eduard Zeller | title=Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics; being a translation from Zeller's Philosophy of the Greeks | translator1-first=B.F.C. | translator1-last=Costelloe | translator2-first=J.H. | translator2-last=Muirhead | volume=I | location=London | publisher=Longmans, Green, and Co. | year=1897a | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xwjJS-RwWCoC}}
- {{cite book | first=Eduard | last=Zeller | author-link=Eduard Zeller | title=Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics; being a translation from Zeller's Philosophy of the Greeks | translator1-first=B.F.C. | translator1-last=Costelloe | translator2-first=J.H. | translator2-last=Muirhead | volume=II | location=London | publisher=Longmans, Green, and Co. | year=1897b | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_yjuAAAAMAAJ | author-mask=2}}
{{div col end}}
Further reading
; Books
- Die Aristotelische Physik, W. Wieland, 1962, 2nd revised edition 1970.
; Articles
- Machamer, Peter K., "Aristotle on Natural Place and Motion," Isis 69:3 (Sept. 1978), 377–387.
External links
{{commons category}}
{{Wikisource|Physics (Aristotle)|Physics}}
{{Wikiquote|Aristotle: a Chapter from the History of Science}}
=Commentaries and comments=
- HTML Greek, in parallel with English translation: [http://dhspriory.org/thomas/Physics.htm Fr. Kenny's collection] (with Aquinas's commentary)
- HTML Greek, in parallel with French translation: [http://remacle.org/bloodwolf/philosophes/Aristote/table.htm P. Remacle's collection]
- [https://isidore.co/aquinas/Physics.htm Thomas Aquinas's Commentary]
- [http://isnature.org/Files/Augros_2009-Bigger_Physics.htm A 'Bigger' Physics] – lecture at MIT on how Aristotle's natural philosophy complements modern science and the need for a general science of nature
=Other=
- [http://oldschoolphysics.com/ Greek text of Physics, as edited by W.D. Ross]
- [https://scaife.perseus.org/reader/urn:cts:greekLit:tlg0086.tlg031.1st1K-grc1:1.1/ Perseus edition of Physics in Greek]
- [http://www.iep.utm.edu/aris-mot/ Aristotle: Motion and its Place in Nature] entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- {{librivox book | stitle=Physics | dtitle=Physics, English Translation by Thomas Taylor | author=Aristotle}}
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20080728140534/http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/physics/complete.html Text of Physics], (in html, epub or mobi format) as translated by R. P. Hardie and R. K. Gaye
{{Aristotelianism|state=collapsed}}
{{Authority control}}
Category:Ancient Greek physics
Category:Philosophy of science
Category:Philosophy of physics