Scope (logic)#Quantifiers

{{Short description|Range of application for a quantifier or connective in a logical formula}}

{{Use mdy dates|date=June 2024}}

In logic, the scope of a quantifier or connective is the shortest formula in which it occurs,{{Cite book |last=Bostock |first=David |title=Intermediate logic |date=1997 |publisher=Clarendon Press; Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-875141-0 |location=Oxford : New York |pages=8, 79}} determining the range in the formula to which the quantifier or connective is applied.{{Cite book |last=Cook |first=Roy T. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JfaqBgAAQBAJ |title=Dictionary of Philosophical Logic |date=March 20, 2009 |publisher=Edinburgh University Press |isbn=978-0-7486-3197-1 |pages=99,180,254 |language=en}}{{Cite book |last1=Rich |first1=Elaine |url=https://www.cs.utexas.edu/~dnp/frege/quantifier-scope.html |title=Quantifier Scope |last2=Cline |first2=Alan Kaylor |language=en-US}}{{Cite book |last=Makridis |first=Odysseus |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DoBgEAAAQBAJ |title=Symbolic Logic |date=February 21, 2022 |publisher=Springer Nature |isbn=978-3-030-67396-3 |pages=93–95 |language=en}} The notions of a free variable and bound variable are defined in terms of whether that formula is within the scope of a quantifier,{{Cite web |date=January 21, 2017 |title=3.3.2: Quantifier Scope, Bound Variables, and Free Variables |url=https://human.libretexts.org/Bookshelves/Philosophy/A_Modern_Formal_Logic_Primer_(Teller)/03%3A_Volume_II-_Predicate_Logic/3.03%3A_More_about_Quantifiers/3.3.02%3A_Quantifier_Scope_Bound_Variables_and_Free_Variables |access-date=June 10, 2024 |website=Humanities LibreTexts |language=en}} and the notions of a {{glossary link|glossary=Glossary of logic|dominant connective}} and {{glossary link|glossary=Glossary of logic|subordinate connective}} are defined in terms of whether a connective includes another within its scope.{{Cite book |last=Gillon |first=Brendan S. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8MuIDwAAQBAJ |title=Natural Language Semantics: Formation and Valuation |date=March 12, 2019 |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-03920-8 |pages=250–253 |language=en}}

Connectives

{{Logical connectives sidebar}}

The scope of a logical connective occurring within a formula is the smallest well-formed formula that contains the connective in question.{{Cite book |last=Lemmon |first=Edward John |title=Beginning logic |date=1998 |publisher=Chapman & Hall/CRC |isbn=978-0-412-38090-7 |location=Boca Raton, FL |pages=45–48}}{{Cite web |title=Examples {{!}} Logic Notes - ANU |url=https://users.cecs.anu.edu.au/~jks/LogicNotes/connectives.html |access-date=June 10, 2024 |website=users.cecs.anu.edu.au}} The connective with the largest scope in a formula is called its dominant connective,{{Cite book |last1=Suppes |first1=Patrick |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=38LCAgAAQBAJ |title=First Course in Mathematical Logic |last2=Hill |first2=Shirley |date=April 30, 2012 |publisher=Courier Corporation |isbn=978-0-486-15094-9 |pages=23–26 |language=en}}{{Cite book |last=Kirk |first=Donna |url=https://openstax.org/books/contemporary-mathematics/pages/2-2-compound-statements |title=Contemporary Mathematics |date=March 22, 2023 |publisher=OpenStax |chapter=2.2. Compound Statements}} main connective, main operator, major connective, or principal connective; a connective within the scope of another connective is said to be subordinate to it.

For instance, in the formula (\left( \left( P \rightarrow Q \right) \lor \lnot Q \right) \leftrightarrow \left( \lnot \lnot P \land Q \right)), the dominant connective is ↔, and all other connectives are subordinate to it; the → is subordinate to the ∨, but not to the ∧; the first ¬ is also subordinate to the ∨, but not to the →; the second ¬ is subordinate to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →; and the third ¬ is subordinate to the second ¬, as well as to the ∧, but not to the ∨ or the →. If an order of precedence is adopted for the connectives, viz., with ¬ applying first, then ∧ and ∨, then →, and finally ↔, this formula may be written in the less parenthesized form \left ( P \rightarrow Q \right) \lor \lnot Q \leftrightarrow \lnot \lnot P \land Q

, which some may find easier to read.

Quantifiers

The scope of a quantifier is the part of a logical expression over which the quantifier exerts control. It is the shortest full sentence written right after the quantifier, often in parentheses; some authors describe this as including the variable written right after the universal or existential quantifier. In the formula {{math|∀xP}}, for example, {{math|P}} (or {{math|xP}}){{cite book |last1=Bell |first1=John L. |title=A Course in Mathematical Logic |last2=Machover |first2=Moshé |date=April 15, 2007 |publisher=Elsevier Science Ltd |isbn=978-0-7204-2844-5 |page=[https://archive.org/details/courseinmathemat0000bell/page/17 17] |chapter=Chapter 1. Beginning mathematical logic |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/courseinmathemat0000bell/page/17 |authorlink1=John Lane Bell |authorlink2=Moshé Machover}} is the scope of the quantifier {{math|∀x}} (or {{math|∀}}).

This gives rise to the following definitions:{{refn|group=lower-alpha|These definitions follow the common practice of using Greek letters as metalogical symbols which may stand for symbols in a formal language for propositional or predicate logic. In particular, \phi and \psi are used to stand for any formulae whatsoever, whereas \xi and \zeta are used to stand for propositional variables.}}

  • An occurrence of a quantifier \forall or \exists, immediately followed by an occurrence of the variable \xi, as in \forall \xi or \exists \xi, is said to be \xi-binding.
  • An occurrence of a variable \xi in a formula \phi is free in \phi if, and only if, it is not in the scope of any \xi-binding quantifier in \phi; otherwise it is bound in \phi.
  • A closed formula is one in which no variable occurs free; a formula which is not closed is open.{{Citation |last=Uzquiano |first=Gabriel |title=Quantifiers and Quantification |date=2022 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2022/entries/quantification/ |access-date=June 10, 2024 |edition=Winter 2022 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri}}
  • An occurrence of a quantifier \forall \xi or \exists \xi is vacuous if, and only if, its scope is \forall \xi \psi or \exists \xi \psi, and the variable \xi does not occur free in \psi.
  • A variable \zeta is free for a variable \xi if, and only if, no free occurrences of \xi lie within the scope of a quantification on \zeta.
  • A quantifier whose scope contains another quantifier is said to have wider scope than the second, which, in turn, is said to have narrower scope than the first.{{Cite book |last=Allen |first=Colin |title=Logic primer |last2=Hand |first2=Michael |date=2001 |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-51126-1 |edition=2nd |location=Cambridge, Mass |pages=66}}

See also

Notes

{{reflist|group=lower-alpha}}

References