Selective conscientious objection

{{Short description|Practice of refusing some, but not all, military service}}

File:Fort Hood Three.jpg refused orders to go to Vietnam]]

Selective conscientious objection is the practice of refusing some, but not all, military service. It is much more controversial than blanket conscientious objection based on consistent pacifism.{{cite book |last1=Robinson |first1=Paul |title=Routledge Handbook of Military Ethics |date=2015 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-315-81351-6 |chapter=Selective Conscientious Objection}} Views on selective conscientious objection range from being morally impermissible, morally permissible, a right that may be exercised, or morally obligatory in the case of military personnel asked to fight an illegal war of aggression.{{cite journal |last1=Wolfendale |first1=Jessica |title=Professional Integrity and Disobedience in the Military |journal=Journal of Military Ethics |date=2009 |volume=8 |issue=2 |pages=127–140 |doi=10.1080/15027570903037934|s2cid=144405683 |url=https://philpapers.org/archive/JESPIA.pdf }}

Arguments for and against

The traditional view is that soldiers are obligated to obey superior orders to participate in a war, even when this is against their conscience. The moral culpability for fighting an unjust war, in this view, is visited entirely on the leaders and not on ordinary soldiers who are entirely innocent (see moral equality of combatants).{{cite journal |last1=Dannenbaum |first1=Tom |title=The Criminalization of Aggression and Soldiers' Rights |journal=European Journal of International Law |date=2018 |volume=29 |issue=3 |pages=859–886 |doi=10.1093/ejil/chy054|doi-access=free }} Arguments for this view include those based on social contract theory which posit that citizens should obey their state's decision to go to war, the argument that individual soldiers are ill-placed to determine whether a war is just.

In 1539, Francisco de Vitoria argued: {{quote|If the war seems patently unjust to the subject, he must not fight, even if he is ordered to do so by the prince. This is obvious, since one may not lawfully kill an innocent man on any authority, and in the case we are speaking of the enemy must be innocent. . . if their conscience tells subjects that the war is unjust, they must not go to war even if this conscience is wrong.}}

Those who reject the moral equality of combatants regardless of whether they are fighting for a just or unjust cause argue that individual soldiers have an obligation to refuse to fight an unjust war if they can do so without suffering death or other grave harms.{{cite book |last1=Syse |first1=Henrik |title=The Ashgate Research Companion to Military Ethics |date=2015 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-315-61324-6 |chapter=The Moral Equality of Combatants|page=261}} John Rawls argues that selective objection should be allowed as it may prevent the government from continuing an unjust war.

Historical examples

During the first several years of the United States participation in the Vietnam War, selective conscientious objection based on just war theory was widespread among Catholic war resisters as well as Jews, nonreligious men, and those of other faiths. Despite its strong grassroots support, selective conscientious objection was unacceptable to the state as it was feared that allowing conscripts to pick and choose what wars they would fight in would undermine national defense.{{cite book |last1=Cajka |first1=Peter |title=Follow Your Conscience: The Catholic Church and the Spirit of the Sixties |date=2021 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-76219-7 |pages=68–69 |language=en}} During the 2022 Russian invasion of Ukraine, some leaders including the president of Ukraine and president of Estonia argued that Russian soldiers should selectively object to the invasion.{{cite news |last1=Weinberg |first1=Justin |title=Philosophers On The Russian Attack On Ukraine |url=https://dailynous.com/2022/03/02/philosophers-on-the-russian-attack-on-ukraine/ |access-date=17 March 2022 |work=Daily Nous |date=2 March 2022}} Many Israelis who refuse to serve in the IDF are selective conscientious objectors who criticize certain actions such as the invasion of Lebanon or occupation of the West Bank as immoral or illegal.

Legal recognition

Legally, courts in most countries have distinguished between blanket objection and selective objection, allowing only the former.{{cite journal |last1=Paz-Fuchs |first1=Amir |last2=Sfard |first2=Michael |title=The Fallacies of Objections to Selective Conscientious Objection |journal=Israel Law Review |date=2002 |volume=36 |issue=3 |pages=111–143 |doi=10.1017/S0021223700017994|s2cid=142864016 }} Soldiers have a right and a responsibility to refuse to commit war crimes, but the right to refuse to fight an illegal war is not widely recognized.{{sfn|Dannenbaum|2018|pp=865, 867}} In the United States, the 1971 Gillette v. United States found that to be recognized as a conscientious objector, one must refuse all wars.{{cite journal |title=Reconsidering Selective Conscientious Objection |journal=University of Richmond Law Review |date= 2019 |url=https://lawreview.richmond.edu/2019/02/15/reconsidering-selective-conscientious-objection/|first1=Andrew J. |last1=Haile|pages=831–886|volume=52}} International law scholar Tom Dannenbaum argues that soldiers should have a right not to fight in illegal wars, and those who refuse to should be recognized as refugees.{{sfn|Dannenbaum|2018|pp=868, 870}}

References