argument from nonbelief
{{Short description|Philosophical argument that asserts an inconsistency with nonbelief and God's existence}}
{{Atheism sidebar |arguments}}
{{Philosophy of religion sidebar |God}}
An argument from nonbelief is a philosophical argument for the nonexistence of God that asserts an inconsistency between God's existence and a world that fails to recognize such an entity. It is similar to the classic argument from evil in affirming an inconsistency between the world that exists and the world that would exist if God had certain desires combined with the power to see them through.
There are two key varieties of the argument. The argument from reasonable nonbelief (or the argument from divine hiddenness) was first elaborated in J. L. Schellenberg's 1993 book Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason. This argument says that if God existed (and was perfectly good and loving) every reasonable person would have been brought to believe in God; however, there are reasonable nonbelievers; therefore, this God does not exist.
Theodore Drange subsequently developed the argument from nonbelief, based on the mere existence of nonbelief in God. Drange considers the distinction between reasonable (by which Schellenberg means inculpable) and unreasonable (culpable) nonbelief to be irrelevant and confusing. Nevertheless, the overwhelming majority of academic discussion is concerned with Schellenberg's formulation.
= God is perfectly loving =
Schellenberg says he has not seen any serious objections to this premise by theistic philosophers, but there certainly are other conceptions of God. Daniel Howard-Snyder writes about the possibility of believing in an unsurpassably great personal god that is nevertheless dispassionate towards its creatures. Drawing on the Stoic concept of Eudaimonia, he says one can think of a god more akin to a wise sage than the loving parent that Schellenberg envisions.{{Cite encyclopedia |last=Howard-Snyder |first=Daniel |year=2006 |title=Hiddenness of God |encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=2nd |editor=Donald M. Borchert |url=https://archive.org/details/encyclopediaofph0000unse |access-date=2007-01-15 |isbn=0-02-865780-2 }}
Theodore Drange, in his attempt to improve the argument (see below), states that there are many theists who do not view God as perfectly loving, and "some Christians think of him as an angry deity bent on punishing people for their sins."{{Cite conference |last=Drange |first=Theodore |author-link=Theodore Drange |year=1998 |title=Nonbelief as Support for Atheism |book-title=Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy |url=http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Reli/ReliDran.htm |access-date=2007-01-13| archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20070204050102/http://www.bu.edu/wcp/Papers/Reli/ReliDran.htm |archive-date= 4 February 2007 |url-status= live}} Drange concludes that the argument should be put forward only in relation to theists who already accept the first premise and believe in a god who is perfectly loving.
Most theists, in fact, do admit that love is a central concept in almost all of the world's religions. God is often directly associated with love, especially with agape. Theologians such as N.T. Wright suggest that our experience of love is itself a proof of God's existence. However, there are a few others (e.g. Brian Davies in the Thomist tradition) who suggest that the modern interpretation of what it means to say God loves human beings is incorrect, and so that God is able to be loving in a sense while actually willing disbelief.
= Nonresistant nonbelief, lack of evidence, and sin =
When asked what he would say when facing God on judgment day, Bertrand Russell famously replied that he would say "Not enough evidence, God! Not enough evidence!" Some nonbelievers may have hidden from themselves what seems to them to be possible evidence of the divine, but the view of the hiddenness argument is that others have tried hard to believe in God. Schellenberg addresses this difference with his distinction between culpable and inculpable nonbelief, with the latter defined as "non-belief that exists through no fault of the non-believer."
Historically, the Calvinist tradition has placed the blame on nonbelievers, who are predestined by God towards nonbelief. Calvin's religious epistemology is based on the sensus divinitatis (Sense of Divinity), the view that the presence of God is universally perceived by all humans. Paul Helm explains, "Calvin’s use of the term 'sense' signals that the knowledge of God is a common human endowment; mankind is created not only as capable of knowing God, but as actually knowing him."{{Cite journal |last=Helm |first=Paul |author-link=Paul Helm|year=1998 |title=John Calvin, the Sensus Divinitatis, and the noetic effects of sin |journal=International Journal for Philosophy of Religion |volume=43 |issue=2 |pages=87–107 |doi=10.1023/A:1003174629151|s2cid=169082078 }} According to this tradition, there is no inculpable or nonresistant nonbelief. Jonathan Edwards, the 18th century American theologian, claimed that while every human being has been granted the capacity to know God, successful use of these capacities requires an attitude of "true benevolence", a divinely gifted willingness to be open to the truth about God. Thus, the failure of non-believers to see "divine things" is in his view due to "a dreadful stupidity of mind, occasioning a sottish insensibility of their truth and importance."{{Cite book |last=Edwards |first=Jonathan |year=1970 |title=Original Sin |author-link=Jonathan Edwards (theologian) |editor=Clyde A. Holbrook |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=0-300-01198-9 |url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/originalsin0003edwa }} As quoted and represented in Howard-Snyder (2006).
= Demographics of theism and the problem of natural nonbelief =
In modern times, there are fewer proponents of these views. One reason is that, as Stephen Maitzen argues,{{Cite journal |first=Stephen |last=Maitzen |year=2006 |title=Divine Hiddenness and the Demographics of Theism |journal=Religious Studies |volume=42 |pages=177–191 |url=http://philosophy.acadiau.ca/tl_files/sites/philosophy/resources/documents/Maitzen_Hiddenness.pdf |doi=10.1017/S0034412506008274 |issue=2|s2cid=38829300 }} anthropology has long established that while religious belief in general is essentially universal, belief in what Calvin would recognize as God is very unevenly distributed among cultures (consider for example God in Buddhism, Jain cosmology, or non-theistic animism). If God exists, then why, Maitzen asks, does the prevalence of belief in God vary so dramatically with cultural and national boundaries? Jason Marsh has extended this kind of demographic challenge by focusing on human evolution and cognitive science of religion. Why is theistic belief apparently non-existent among early humans but common at later times, at least in some regions? According to Marsh, the hiddenness problem is harder to answer once we appreciate that much nonbelief is 'natural', owing to the kinds of minds people naturally possess and to their place in evolutionary and cultural history.{{Cite journal |first=Jason |last=Marsh |year=2013 |title=Darwin and the Problem of Natural Nonbelief |journal=The Monist |volume=42 |pages=177–191 |url=http://philpapers.org/archive/MARDAT-7.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150119044351/http://philpapers.org/archive/MARDAT-7.pdf |archive-date=2015-01-19 |url-status=live}}
Another reason why many philosophers no longer attribute nonbelief to human sinfulness has to do with respect. In fact, modern critics, such as Howard-Snyder, who praised Schellenberg's book for being "religiously sensitive,"{{Cite journal |last=Howard-Snyder |first=Daniel |year=1995 |title=Book review: John Schellenberg, Divine Hiddenness and Human Reason (Cornell 1993) |journal=Mind |volume=104 |issue=414 |pages=430–435 |url=http://www.wwu.edu/~howardd/bookreviews/schellenberg.pdf |access-date=2007-01-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060928070142/http://www.wwu.edu/~howardd/bookreviews/schellenberg.pdf |archive-date=2006-09-28 |url-status=dead |doi=10.1093/mind/104.414.430 }} are similarly sensitive towards the nonbeliever. Howard-Snyder wrote:
{{blockquote|Even though some nonbelievers lack true benevolence, the empirical evidence strongly suggests that others possess it since they really do earnestly seek the truth about God, love the Good, assess evidence judiciously, and, if anything, display a prejudice for God, not against Him.}}
= Would a perfectly loving God prevent nonresistant nonbelief? =
The most serious criticisms of the hiddenness argument have been leveled against the idea that a perfectly loving God would prevent nonresistant nonbelief. Schellenberg argues in two steps, by first claiming that a loving God would enable humans to partake in a relationship with it, and then, assuming that belief in that god is a necessary condition for such relationships to occur, inferring that a loving God would not permit nonbelief. He states:
{{blockquote|There is, first of all, the claim that if there is a personal God who is perfectly loving, creatures capable of explicit and positively meaningful relationship with God, who have not freely shut themselves off from God, are always in a position to participate in such relationship—able to do so just by trying to.}}
He justifies this claim by arguing that a conception of divine love can best be formed by extrapolating the best aspects of love in human relations, and draws an analogy with perfect parental love:
{{blockquote|The perfectly loving parent, for example, from the time the child can first respond to her at all until death separates them, will, insofar as she can help it, see to it that nothing she does ever puts relationship with herself out of reach for her child.}}
But, says Schellenberg, belief in God's existence is necessary for engaging in such a meaningful relationship with God. He therefore concludes that if there is a perfectly loving God, such creatures will always believe in it. He further argues that since belief is involuntary, these creatures should always have evidence "causally sufficient" for such belief:
{{blockquote|The presence of God will be for them like a light that—however much the degree of its brightness may fluctuate—remains on unless they close their eyes.}}
Objections and counterarguments
= Skeptical theism =
Skeptical theism is the view that we should remain skeptical of claims that our perceptions about God's purposes can reasonably be considered good evidence of what they are.{{Cite web|url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/sceptical-theism/v-1|title=Sceptical theism|last=McBrayer|first=Justin|date=2015|website=The Rutledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=10 October 2016|quote=Sceptical theists are ... sceptical of our abilities to discern whether the evils in our world constitute good evidence against the existence of God.}}{{Cite web|url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/sceptical-theism/v-1|title=Sceptical theism|last=McBrayer|first=Justin|date=2015|website=Rutledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy|access-date=10 October 2016|quote=The sceptical element of sceptical theism can be used to undermine various arguments for atheism including both the argument from evil and the argument from divine hiddenness.}} The central thesis of skeptical theism is that it would not be surprising for an infinitely intelligent and knowledgeable being's reasons for permitting a perception of evil or alleged hiddenness to be beyond human comprehension.[2] That is, what is perceived as hiddenness may be necessary for a greater good or to prevent equal or even greater evils.
Schellenberg has responded to skeptical theism (i.e. noseeum/unknown-purpose defense).Schellenberg, J.L., 2007a, The Wisdom to Doubt, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. First, Schellenberg says that he has given known reasons to think that a perfectly loving being would always be open to a personal relationship; ipso facto, God would not sacrifice some time in the relationship for the sake of unknown greater goods,Schellenberg, J. L. ‘Divine Hiddenness: Part 1 (Recent Work on the Hiddenness Argument).' Philosophy Compass, 2017. and if the greatest good for finite creatures is to be in a relationship with God, then God would not sacrifice that for the sake of unknown greater goods.Schellenberg, J.L., 2015, The Hiddenness Argument: Philosophy’s New Challenge to Belief in God, New York: Oxford University Press.Schellenberg, J. L., 2014, Skeptical Theism and Skeptical Atheism. In Justin McBrayer Trent Dougherty (ed.), _Skeptical Theism: New Essays_. Oxford University Press. Finally, Schellenberg's position is that all known and unknown goods are ultimately in God; hence, God can bring about unknown greater goods without hiddenness.Schellenberg, J.L., 2016, “Divine Hiddenness and Human Philosophy”, in Green and Stump 2016: 13–32.
== Noseeum defense ==
The philosophers Michael Bergmann and Michael Rea described the philosopher William Rowe's justification for the second premise of the argument from evil, which is equally applicable to a perception of hiddenness:
Some evidential arguments ... rely on a “noseeum” inference of the following sort: NI: If, after thinking hard, we can’t think of any God-justifying reason for permitting some horrific evil then it is likely that there is no such reason. (The reason NI is called a ‘noseeum’ inference is that it says, more or less, that because we don’t see ‘um, they probably ain’t there.){{Cite journal |last=Rowe|first=William|year=1979|title=The Problem of Evil and Some Varieties of Atheism, American|journal=American Philosophical Quarterly |volume=16 |pages=335–41}}{{Cite journal |year=2005 |title=Michael Bergmann and Michael Rea |url=https://www3.nd.edu/~mrea/papers/In%20Defense%20of%20Skeptical%20Theism.pdf |journal=The Australasian Journal of Philosophy |volume=83 |pages=241–51 |access-date=2016-10-31 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20161109033308/http://www3.nd.edu/~mrea/papers/In%20Defense%20of%20Skeptical%20Theism.pdf |archive-date=2016-11-09 |url-status=dead }}{{Cite journal |last=Rowe|first=William|year=1988|title=Evil and Theodicy|journal=Philosophical Topics|volume=16|issue=2|pages=119–32|doi=10.5840/philtopics198816216}}{{Cite journal |last=Rowe|first=William|title=Ruminations about Evil|journal=Philosophical Topics|volume=5|pages=69–88}}Various analogies are offered to show that the noseeum inference is logically unsound. For example, a novice chess player's inability to discern a chess master's choice of moves cannot be used to infer that there is no good reason for the move.{{Cite book|url=http://web.ics.purdue.edu/~bergmann/wp-content/uploads/2012/12/OHPT-bergmann-preprint.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140407231539/http://web.ics.purdue.edu/~bergmann/wp-content/uploads/2012/12/OHPT-bergmann-preprint.pdf |archive-date=2014-04-07 |url-status=live|title=Oxford Handbook to Philosophical Theology (Skeptical Theism and the Problem of Evil) |last=Bergmann |first=Michael|publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2009|editor-last=Flint|editor-first=Thomas|location=Oxford|pages=374–99}} The skeptical theist and noseeum defense place the burden of proof on the atheist to prove that their intuitions about God are trustworthy.
= Unreasonable demands on God =
This argument is sometimes seen as demanding God to prove his existence, for example by performing miracles. Critics have argued that even in Schellenberg's more refined version, the nonbeliever is imposing their own epistemological expectations on the will of God. A detailed discussion of these kinds of demands, and their moral and spiritual implications, is provided by Paul Moser,{{Cite book |last=Moser |first=Paul |year=2001 |chapter=Cognitive Idolatry and Divine Hiding |chapter-url=http://www.luc.edu/faculty/pmoser/idolanon/CognitiveIdolatry.html |title=Divine Hiddenness: New Essays |isbn=0-521-00610-4 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=New York}} who says that such demands amount to cognitive idolatry. He defines idolatry as "our not letting the true God be Lord in our lives" and instead committing to something other than God by pursuing a quest for self-realization in our own terms. If this is idolatry in our actions, then idolatry in our knowing, he says, is as follows:
{{blockquote|Cognitive idolatry relies on a standard for knowledge that excludes the primacy of the morally self-transforming knowledge of God central to knowing God as Lord. It rests on an epistemological standard, whether empiricist, rationalist, or some hybrid, that does not let God be Lord. Such idolatry aims to protect one's lifestyle from serious challenge by the God who calls, convicts, and reconciles. It disallows knowledge of God as personal subject and Lord to whom we are morally and cognitively responsible. It allows at most for knowledge of God as an undemanding object of human knowledge.}}
Schellenberg considers this criticism irrelevant to the argument, which in his opinion, does not impose any demands for demonstrations of God's power, but rather looks for evidence that "need only be such as will be causally sufficient for belief in the absence of resistance... This result might be effected through the much more spiritually appropriate means of religious experience, interpreted in the sensitive manner of a Pascal or a Kierkegaard." Schellenberg then expresses a certain frustration that theistic writers who otherwise extol the value of religious experiences deny non-theists the right to do so.
= Soul-making theodicy =
{{see also|Irenaean theodicy}}
John Hick used the term "soul-making" in his theodicy Evil and the God of Love to describe the kind of spiritual development that he believes justifies the existence of evil. This defense is employed by Michael Murray,{{Cite book |last=Murray |first=Michael J. |year=2001 |chapter=Deus Absconditus |chapter-url=http://server1.fandm.edu/Departments/Philosophy/staticpages/Murray/Hiddenness_Murray.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20041231201314/http://server1.fandm.edu/departments/Philosophy/staticpages/Murray/Hiddenness_Murray.pdf |archive-date=2004-12-31 |url-status=live |title=Divine Hiddenness: New Essays |isbn=0-521-00610-4 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=New York}} who explains how, in his view, divine hiddenness is essential to soul-making. It may seem that it is not hard to imagine a world where God is known and yet believers act freely with ample opportunities for spiritual development. But Murray gives a deep and careful analysis of the argument, concluding that if God's existence were revealed in such a way as to remove reasonable non-belief, then "any desire that we might have to believe or act in ways contrary to that which has been revealed would be overwhelmed."
Critics note here that, for example, in Christianity (and even more in Judaism, where God is represented as talking to Job and explaining why he is just), God is already believed to have exposed himself very distinctly: for example to the Apostles who saw his resurrection. One theistic explanation of this might be that God knows some people would not believe anyway but if God knows this before creating, there is a problem about God's liability for what is created. More fundamentally in relation to Murray's argument, there is the problem for orthodox believers of explaining the existence of Satan, a fallen angel who is obviously aware of God and yet, according to theistic scriptures, freely chose to rebel against God.{{Cite web|url=http://www.godonthe.net/evidence/satan.htm|title=Satan - the Devil and Demons - the Fallen Angels}}{{unreliable source?|date=November 2020}}
= Turning the tables =
Like with the argument from evil, one can "flip" the argument from divine hiddenness.Moser, Paul K. (2008). The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology. Cambridge University PressKelly, T.(2011).Consensus gentium: Reflections on the ‘common consent’ argument for the existence of God. In K.J. Clark & R.J. Vanarragon (Eds.), Evidence and Religious belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. In other words, one can argue that the fact that many or most people believe that God exists (and/or have experiences of God) is evidence that God does exist.Moser, Paul K. (2008). The Elusive God: Reorienting Religious Epistemology. Cambridge University Press.
= Unknown purpose defense =
Alvin Plantinga writes that the statement "We can see no good reason for God to do X" only implies "There is no good reason for God to do X" on the assumption that "If there were a good reason for God to do X, we would be able to see it," which he suggests is absurd.Alvin Plantinga Warranted Christian Belief {{ISBN|0-19-513192-4}} This point might be applied to versions of the argument from nonbelief that suggest without support that there is no good reason for God to permit nonbelief. Critics of Plantinga might suggest that if nobody is able to present an apparently good reason for God to allow nonbelief, then it is less ad hoc to merely posit God's non-existence, or indifference to people's belief, to explain this inability, than to posit both the existence of a God who cares about people's beliefs as well as some unthinkable reason obvious only to God to remain hidden.
= There really are no atheists defense =
This argument posits that all true atheists are, at their core, lying in order to live in a way that contradicts God's commands, as seen in certain interpretations of Romans 1:18-25. Critics point out that there are atheists who are genuinely not lying and are not using their atheism as an excuse to sin. However, proponents argue that atheists could still be deceiving themselves, even if they are not lying to others (for example, the argument about loving the wrong woman, which may need further clarification{{clarify|date=October 2015}}). Some have suggested that this argument overlooks Stephen Maitzen's point regarding the demographics of theism: if all atheists are liars, why are people in some societies more likely to lie than in others?{{cite web| url = http://philosophy.acadiau.ca/tl_files/sites/philosophy/resources/documents/Maitzen_Hiddenness.pdf| title = philosophy.acadiau.ca}} Additionally, others contend that the argument fails to address Jason Marsh's point about natural nonbelief in early humans. Since it is plausible that natural nonbelief existed in early humans, it doesn't make sense to claim that such nonbelief is self-deceptive. Natural nonbelief, they argue, entails nonresistant nonbelief.{{cite web| url = https://philpapers.org/rec/MARDAT-7| title = philpapers.org}}
Drange's argument from nonbelief
Theodore Drange proposed a version of the nonbelief argument in 1996. He considers the distinction between culpable and inculpable nonbelief to be unhelpful in the argument, arguing instead that the mere existence of nonbelief is evidence against the existence of God. A semi-formal presentation of the argument is as follows:{{Cite web |last=Drange |first=Theodore |author-link=Theodore Drange |year=1996 |title=The Arguments From Evil and Nonbelief |url=http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/theodore_drange/aeanb.html |access-date=2007-01-13| archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20070110135633/http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/theodore_drange/aeanb.html |archive-date= 10 January 2007 | url-status= live}}
- If God exists, God:
- wants all humans to believe God exists before they die;
- can bring about a situation in which all humans believe God exists before they die;
- does not want anything that would conflict with and be at least as important as its desire for all humans to believe God exists before they die; and
- always acts in accordance with what it most wants.
- If God exists, all humans would believe so before they die (from 1).
- But not all humans believe God exists before they die.
- Therefore, God does not exist (from 2 and 3).
Drange's argument is directed primarily to Christians, and the philosopher Laura Garcia has replied from that perspective. She says that Drange's argument hinges on the idea that belief in God's existence is, according to Christians, necessary for salvation. According to Garcia this idea is mistaken: "many Christians deny this claim and the Catholic Church explicitly rejects it."{{cite book |last=Garcia |first=Laura |editor1-first=Daniel |editor1-last=Howard-Snyder |editor2-first=Paul |editor2-last=Moser |title=Divine Hiddenness: New Essays |url=https://archive.org/details/divinehiddenness00howa |url-access=limited |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2002 |page=[https://archive.org/details/divinehiddenness00howa/page/n95 84] |chapter=St. John of the Cross and the Necessity of Divine Hiddenness |isbn=0-521-00610-4}} But as Garcia notes, Drange has answered that for many Christians—in particular, evangelical Christians—his point should remain convincing, and that there are in any case other good things that belief in God can bring for humans, which a good God would desire, such as peace of mind and a sense of meaning in life.{{cite book |last=Garcia |first=Laura |editor1-first=Daniel |editor1-last=Howard-Snyder |editor2-first=Paul |editor2-last=Moser |title=Divine Hiddenness: New Essays |url=https://archive.org/details/divinehiddenness00howa |url-access=limited |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2002 |page=[https://archive.org/details/divinehiddenness00howa/page/n96 85] |chapter=St. John of the Cross and the Necessity of Divine Hiddenness |isbn=0-521-00610-4}}
See also
- {{annotated link|Vincible and invincible ignorance}}
- {{annotated link|Fate of the unlearned}}
References
{{Reflist}}
External links
- [https://iep.utm.edu/divine-hiddenness-argument-against-gods-existence/ Divine Hiddenness Argument against God’s Existence], Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- [http://www.jlschellenberg.com "JL Schellenberg"]: Offers more information and updates on Schellenberg's hiddenness argument.
- [https://infidels.org/library/modern/nontheism-atheism-nonbelief/ "The Argument from (Reasonable) Nonbelief"] at Infidels.org: contains a large number of papers mainly focusing on Theodore Drange's formulation.
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20061220083551/http://www.philosophyofreligion.info/divinehiddennessandfaith.html "The Argument from Unbelief"] at [http://www.philosophyofreligion.info Philosophy of Religion .Info]: Offers a simple overview and rebuttal.
- [http://www.christiancadre.org/topics/cosarg.html#hid Responses to the problem of Divine Hiddenness] from the website of the Christian Colligation of Apologetics Debate Research & Evangelism.
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20070211201013/http://www.ac.wwu.edu/~howardd/papersandbooks.html Daniel Howard-Snyder]. Academic papers and books by one of the most respected critics of Schellenberg's argument. Many papers are relevant to the current article and all are available for download. Highly recommended as a starting point.
- [http://www.luc.edu/faculty/pmoser/idolanon/ Paul Moser's "Idolaters anonymous"]. Moser expressed the idea that arguing from nonbelief is engaging in cognitive idolatry.
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20060910220850/http://www3.baylor.edu/~Jonathan_Kvanvig/pubs.html Jonathan Kvanvig]. One paper critical of the argument, but all papers are available for download and may be of interest.
- [http://philosophy.acadiau.ca/maitzen.html Stephen Maitzen]. Has two papers in support of the argument, but many more on the philosophy of religion available for download [http://philosophy.acadiau.ca/maitzen_cv.html here].
- [http://chaospet.com/245-divine-hiddenness/ Chaospet] has a comic that summarizes the argument.
{{philosophy of religion}}
{{Theology}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Argument From Nonbelief}}