axiom of extensionality
{{short description|Axiom used in set theory}}
{{About|the axiom used in formal set theory|the article on extensionality in general|Extensionality}}
The axiom of extensionality,{{Cite web |title=AxiomaticSetTheory |url=https://www.cs.yale.edu/homes/aspnes/pinewiki/AxiomaticSetTheory.html |access-date=2024-08-20 |website=www.cs.yale.edu}}{{Cite web |title=Naive Set Theory |url=https://sites.pitt.edu/~jdnorton/teaching/paradox/chapters/sets/sets.html |access-date=2024-08-20 |website=sites.pitt.edu}} also called the axiom of extent,{{Cite book |last=Bourbaki |first=N. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7eclBQAAQBAJ |title=Theory of Sets |date=2013-12-01 |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |isbn=978-3-642-59309-3 |pages=67 |language=en}}{{Cite book |last=Deskins |first=W. E. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2KrDAgAAQBAJ |title=Abstract Algebra |date=2012-05-24 |publisher=Courier Corporation |isbn=978-0-486-15846-4 |pages=2 |language=en}} is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.{{Cite web |title=Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory |url=https://www.cs.odu.edu/~toida/nerzic/content/set/ZFC.html |access-date=2024-08-20 |website=www.cs.odu.edu}}{{Cite web |title=Intro to Axiomatic (ZF) Set Theory |url=https://www.andrew.cmu.edu/user/kk3n/complearn/sets.html |access-date=2024-08-20 |website=www.andrew.cmu.edu}} The axiom defines what a set is. Informally, the axiom means that the two sets A and B are equal if and only if A and B have the same members.
Etymology
The term extensionality, as used in
The logical term was introduced to set theory in 1893, Gottlob Frege attempted to use this idea of an extension formally in his Basic Laws of Arithmetic (German: Grundgesetze der Arithmetik),{{Cite book |last=Lévy |first=Azriel |url=https://archive.org/details/basicsettheory00levy_0/mode/2up?q=Frege |title=Basic set theory |date=1979 |publisher=Berlin ; New York : Springer-Verlag |isbn=978-0-387-08417-6 |pages=5}}{{Cite book |last=Frege |first=Gottlob |url=https://archive.org/details/bub_gb_LZ5tAAAAMAAJ/page/n105/ |title=Grundgesetze der arithmetik |date=1893 |publisher=Jena, H. Pohle |pages=69}} where, if is a predicate, its extension , is the set of all objects satisfying .{{Citation |last=Zalta |first=Edward N. |title=Frege's Theorem and Foundations for Arithmetic |date=2024 |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/frege-theorem/ |access-date=2025-01-16 |edition=Spring 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}} For example if is "x is even" then is the set . In his work, he defined his infamous Basic Law V as:{{Sfn|Ferreirós|2007|p=304}}Stating that if two predicates have the same extensions (they are satisfied by the same set of objects) then they are logically equivalent, however, it was determined later that this axiom led to Russell's paradox. The first explicit statement of the modern Axiom of Extensionality was in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo in a paper on the well-ordering theorem, where he presented the first axiomatic set theory, now called Zermelo set theory, which became the basis of modern set theories.{{Citation |last=Hallett |first=Michael |title=Zermelo's Axiomatization of Set Theory |date=2024 |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/zermelo-set-theory/ |access-date=2025-01-16 |edition=Fall 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy}} The specific term for "Extensionality" used by Zermelo was "Bestimmtheit".The specific English term "extensionality" only became common in mathematical and logical texts in the 1920s and 1930s,Oxford English Dictionary, s.v. “Extensionality (n.)” December 2024 particularly with the formalization of logic and set theory by figures like Alfred Tarski and John von Neumann.
In ZF set theory
In the formal language of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, the axiom reads:
:{{Cite web |title=Set Theory > Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZF) (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ZF.html |access-date=2024-11-24 |website=plato.stanford.edu |language=en}}{{Cite web |title=Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory |url=https://www.cs.odu.edu/~toida/nerzic/content/set/ZFC.html |access-date=2024-11-24 |website=www.cs.odu.edu}}{{Cite web |title=Naive Set Theory |url=https://sites.pitt.edu/~jdnorton/teaching/paradox/chapters/sets/sets.html |access-date=2024-11-24 |website=sites.pitt.edu}}
or in words:
:If the sets and have the same members, then they are the same set.
In {{glossary link|pure set theory|glossary=Glossary of set theory}}, all members of sets are themselves sets, but not in set theory with urelements. The axiom's usefulness can be seen from the fact that, if one accepts that , where is a set and is a formula that occurs free in but doesn't, then the axiom assures that there is a unique set whose members are precisely whatever objects (urelements or sets, as the case may be) satisfy the formula .
The converse of the axiom, , follows from the substitution property of equality. Despite this, the axiom is sometimes given directly as a biconditional, i.e., as .
In NF set theory
Quine's New Foundations (NF) set theory, in Quine's original presentations of it, treats the symbol for equality or identity as shorthand either for "if a set contains the left side of the equals sign as a member, then it also contains the right side of the equals sign as a member" (as defined in 1937), or for "an object is an element of the set on the left side of the equals sign if, and only if, it is also an element of the set on the right side of the equals sign" (as defined in 1951). That is, is treated as shorthand either for , as in the original 1937 paper, or for , as in Quine's Mathematical Logic (1951). The second version of the definition is exactly equivalent to the antecedent of the ZF axiom of extensionality, and the first version of the definition is still very similar to it. By contrast, however, the ZF set theory takes the symbol for identity or equality as a primitive symbol of the formal language, and defines the axiom of extensionality in terms of it. (In this paragraph, the statements of both versions of the definition were paraphrases, and quotation marks were only used to set the statements apart.)
In Quine's New Foundations for Mathematical Logic (1937), the original paper of NF, the name "principle of extensionality" is given to the postulate P1, ,{{Cite journal |last=Quine |first=W. V. |date=1937 |title=New Foundations for Mathematical Logic |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2300564 |journal=The American Mathematical Monthly |volume=44 |issue=2 |pages=74, 77 |doi=10.2307/2300564 |jstor=2300564 |issn=0002-9890}} which, for readability, may be restated as . The definition D8, which defines the symbol for identity or equality, defines as shorthand for . In his Mathematical Logic (1951), having already developed quasi-quotation, Quine defines as shorthand for (definition D10), and does not define an axiom or principle "of extensionality" at all.{{Cite journal |last=Quine |first=W. V. |date=1951-12-31 |title=Mathematical Logic |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.4159/9780674042469 |journal=DeGruyter |pages=134–136 |doi=10.4159/9780674042469|isbn=978-0-674-04246-9 }}
Thomas Forster, however, ignores these fine distinctions, and considers NF to accept the axiom of extensionality in its ZF form.{{Citation |last=Forster |first=Thomas |title=Quine's New Foundations |date=2019 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/quine-nf/ |access-date=2024-11-24 |edition=Summer 2019 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}
In ZU set theory
In the Scott–Potter (ZU) set theory, the "extensionality principle" is given as a theorem rather than an axiom, which is proved from the definition of a "collection".{{Cite book |last=Potter |first=Michael D. |url=https://www.worldcat.org/title/ocm53392572 |title=Set theory and its philosophy: a critical introduction |date=2004 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926973-0 |location=Oxford; New York |pages=31 |oclc=ocm53392572}}
In set theory with ur-elements
{{Unreferenced section|date=November 2024}}
An ur-element is a member of a set that is not itself a set.
In the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, there are no ur-elements, but they are included in some alternative axiomatisations of set theory.
Ur-elements can be treated as a different logical type from sets; in this case, makes no sense if is an ur-element, so the axiom of extensionality simply applies only to sets.
Alternatively, in untyped logic, we can require to be false whenever is an ur-element.
In this case, the usual axiom of extensionality would then imply that every ur-element is equal to the empty set.
To avoid this consequence, we can modify the axiom of extensionality to apply only to nonempty sets, so that it reads:
:
That is:
:Given any set A and any set B, if A is a nonempty set (that is, if there exists a member X of A), then if A and B have precisely the same members, then they are equal.
Yet another alternative in untyped logic is to define itself to be the only element of
whenever is an ur-element. While this approach can serve to preserve the axiom of extensionality, the axiom of regularity will need an adjustment instead.
See also
References
{{refbegin}}
- {{Citation |last=Ferreirós |first=José |title=Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought |year=2007 |edition=2nd revised |publisher=Birkhäuser |isbn=978-3-7643-8349-7}}
- Paul Halmos, Naive set theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. {{ISBN|0-387-90092-6}} (Springer-Verlag edition).
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. {{ISBN|3-540-44085-2}}.
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. {{ISBN|0-444-86839-9}}.
{{refend}}