greatest element and least element

{{Use American English|date = March 2019}}

{{Short description|Element ≥ (or ≤) each other element}}

File:Lattice of the divisors of 60, ordered by divisibility; with divisors of 30 in red.svg of the set P of divisors of 60, partially ordered by the relation "x divides y". The red subset S = \{ 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, 10, 15, 30 \} has one greatest element, viz. 30, and one least element, viz. 1. These elements are also maximal and minimal elements, respectively, of the red subset.]]

In mathematics, especially in order theory, the greatest element of a subset S of a partially ordered set (poset) is an element of S that is greater than every other element of S. The term least element is defined dually, that is, it is an element of S that is smaller than every other element of S.

Definitions

Let (P, \leq) be a preordered set and let S \subseteq P.

An element g \in P is said to be {{em|a greatest element of S}} if g \in S and if it also satisfies:

:s \leq g for all s \in S.

By switching the side of the relation that s is on in the above definition, the definition of a least element of S is obtained. Explicitly, an element l \in P is said to be {{em|a least element of S}} if l \in S and if it also satisfies:

:l \leq s for all s \in S.

If (P, \leq) is also a partially ordered set then S can have at most one greatest element and it can have at most one least element. Whenever a greatest element of S exists and is unique then this element is called {{em|the}} greatest element of S. The terminology {{em|the}} least element of S is defined similarly.

If (P, \leq) has a greatest element (resp. a least element) then this element is also called {{em|a top}} (resp. {{em|a bottom}}) of (P, \leq).

= Relationship to upper/lower bounds =

Greatest elements are closely related to upper bounds.

Let (P, \leq) be a preordered set and let S \subseteq P.

An {{em|upper bound of S in (P, \leq)}} is an element u such that u \in P and s \leq u for all s \in S. Importantly, an upper bound of S in P is {{em|not}} required to be an element of S.

If g \in P then g is a greatest element of S if and only if g is an upper bound of S in (P, \leq) {{em|and}} g \in S. In particular, any greatest element of S is also an upper bound of S (in P) but an upper bound of S in P is a greatest element of S if and only if it {{em|belongs}} to S.

In the particular case where P = S, the definition of "u is an upper bound of S {{em|in S}}" becomes: u is an element such that u \in S and s \leq u for all s \in S, which is {{em|completely identical}} to the definition of a greatest element given before.

Thus g is a greatest element of S if and only if g is an upper bound of S {{em|in S}}.

If u is an upper bound of S {{em|in P}} that is not an upper bound of S {{em|in S}} (which can happen if and only if u \not\in S) then u can {{em|not}} be a greatest element of S (however, it may be possible that some other element {{em|is}} a greatest element of S).

In particular, it is possible for S to simultaneously {{em|not}} have a greatest element {{em|and}} for there to exist some upper bound of S {{em|in P}}.

Even if a set has some upper bounds, it need not have a greatest element, as shown by the example of the negative real numbers.

This example also demonstrates that the existence of a least upper bound (the number 0 in this case) does not imply the existence of a greatest element either.

= Contrast to maximal elements and local/absolute maximums =

File:Lattice of the divisibility of 60 narrow 1,2,3,4.svg

A greatest element of a subset of a preordered set should not be confused with a maximal element of the set, which are elements that are not strictly smaller than any other element in the set.

Let (P, \leq) be a preordered set and let S \subseteq P.

An element m \in S is said to be a {{em|maximal element of S}} if the following condition is satisfied:

:whenever s \in S satisfies m \leq s, then necessarily s \leq m.

If (P, \leq) is a partially ordered set then m \in S is a maximal element of S if and only if there does {{em|not}} exist any s \in S such that m \leq s and s \neq m.

A {{em|maximal element of (P, \leq)}} is defined to mean a maximal element of the subset S := P.

A set can have several maximal elements without having a greatest element.

Like upper bounds and maximal elements, greatest elements may fail to exist.

In a totally ordered set the maximal element and the greatest element coincide; and it is also called maximum; in the case of function values it is also called the absolute maximum, to avoid confusion with a local maximum.The notion of locality requires the function's domain to be at least a topological space.

The dual terms are minimum and absolute minimum.

Together they are called the absolute extrema.

Similar conclusions hold for least elements.

;Role of (in)comparability in distinguishing greatest vs. maximal elements

One of the most important differences between a greatest element g and a maximal element m of a preordered set (P, \leq) has to do with what elements they are comparable to.

Two elements x, y \in P are said to be {{em|comparable}} if x \leq y or y \leq x; they are called {{em|incomparable}} if they are not comparable.

Because preorders are reflexive (which means that x \leq x is true for all elements x), every element x is always comparable to itself.

Consequently, the only pairs of elements that could possibly be incomparable are {{em|distinct}} pairs.

In general, however, preordered sets (and even directed partially ordered sets) may have elements that are incomparable.

By definition, an element g \in P is a greatest element of (P, \leq) if s \leq g, for every s \in P; so by its very definition, a greatest element of (P, \leq) must, in particular, be comparable to {{em|every}} element in P.

This is not required of maximal elements.

Maximal elements of (P, \leq) are {{em|not}} required to be comparable to every element in P.

This is because unlike the definition of "greatest element", the definition of "maximal element" includes an important {{em|if}} statement.

The defining condition for m \in P to be a maximal element of (P, \leq) can be reworded as:

:For all s \in P, {{em|IF}} m \leq s (so elements that are incomparable to m are ignored) then s \leq m.

;Example where all elements are maximal but none are greatest

Suppose that S is a set containing {{em|at least two}} (distinct) elements and define a partial order \,\leq\, on S by declaring that i \leq j if and only if i = j.

If i \neq j belong to S then neither i \leq j nor j \leq i holds, which shows that all pairs of distinct (i.e. non-equal) elements in S are {{em|in}}comparable.

Consequently, (S, \leq) can not possibly have a greatest element (because a greatest element of S would, in particular, have to be comparable to {{em|every}} element of S but S has no such element).

However, {{em|every}} element m \in S is a maximal element of (S, \leq) because there is exactly one element in S that is both comparable to m and \geq m, that element being m itself (which of course, is \leq m).Of course, in this particular example, there exists only one element in S that is comparable to m, which is necessarily m itself, so the second condition "and \geq m," was redundant.

In contrast, if a preordered set (P, \leq) does happen to have a greatest element g then g will necessarily be a maximal element of (P, \leq) and moreover, as a consequence of the greatest element g being comparable to {{em|every}} element of P, if (P, \leq) is also partially ordered then it is possible to conclude that g is the {{em|only}} maximal element of (P, \leq).

However, the uniqueness conclusion is no longer guaranteed if the preordered set (P, \leq) is {{em|not}} also partially ordered.

For example, suppose that R is a non-empty set and define a preorder \,\leq\, on R by declaring that i \leq j {{em|always}} holds for all i, j \in R. The directed preordered set (R, \leq) is partially ordered if and only if R has exactly one element. All pairs of elements from R are comparable and {{em|every}} element of R is a greatest element (and thus also a maximal element) of (R, \leq). So in particular, if R has at least two elements then (R, \leq) has multiple {{em|distinct}} greatest elements.

Properties

Throughout, let (P, \leq) be a partially ordered set and let S \subseteq P.

  • A set S can have at most {{em|one}} greatest element.If g_1 and g_2 are both greatest, then g_1 \leq g_2 and g_2 \leq g_1, and hence g_1 = g_2 by antisymmetry. Thus if a set has a greatest element then it is necessarily unique.
  • If it exists, then the greatest element of S is an upper bound of S that is also contained in S.
  • If g is the greatest element of S then g is also a maximal element of SIf g is the greatest element of S and s \in S, then s \leq g. By antisymmetry, this renders (g \leq s and g \neq s) impossible. and moreover, any other maximal element of S will necessarily be equal to g.If M is a maximal element, then M \leq g since g is greatest, hence M = g since M is maximal.
  • Thus if a set S has several maximal elements then it cannot have a greatest element.
  • If P satisfies the ascending chain condition, a subset S of P has a greatest element if, and only if, it has one maximal element.Only if: see above. — If: Assume for contradiction that S has just one maximal element, m, but no greatest element. Since m is not greatest, some s_1 \in S must exist that is incomparable to m. Hence s_1 \in S cannot be maximal, that is, s_1 < s_2 must hold for some s_2 \in S. The latter must be incomparable to m, too, since m < s_2 contradicts m's maximality while s_2 \leq m contradicts the incomparability of m and s_1. Repeating this argument, an infinite ascending chain s_1 < s_2 < \cdots < s_n < \cdots can be found (such that each s_i is incomparable to m and not maximal). This contradicts the ascending chain condition.
  • When the restriction of \,\leq\, to S is a total order (S = \{ 1, 2, 4 \} in the topmost picture is an example), then the notions of maximal element and greatest element coincide.Let m \in S be a maximal element, for any s \in S either s \leq m or m \leq s. In the second case, the definition of maximal element requires that m = s, so it follows that s \leq m. In other words, m is a greatest element.
  • However, this is not a necessary condition for whenever S has a greatest element, the notions coincide, too, as stated above.
  • If the notions of maximal element and greatest element coincide on every two-element subset S of P, then \,\leq\, is a total order on P.If a, b \in P were incomparable, then S = \{ a, b \} would have two maximal, but no greatest element, contradicting the coincidence.

Sufficient conditions

  • A finite chain always has a greatest and a least element.

Top and bottom

The least and greatest element of the whole partially ordered set play a special role and are also called bottom (⊥) and top (⊤), or zero (0) and unit (1), respectively.

If both exist, the poset is called a bounded poset.

The notation of 0 and 1 is used preferably when the poset is a complemented lattice, and when no confusion is likely, i.e. when one is not talking about partial orders of numbers that already contain elements 0 and 1 different from bottom and top.

The existence of least and greatest elements is a special completeness property of a partial order.

Further introductory information is found in the article on order theory.

Examples

File:KeinVerband.svg of example 2]]

  • The subset of integers has no upper bound in the set \mathbb{R} of real numbers.
  • Let the relation \,\leq\, on \{ a, b, c, d \} be given by a \leq c, a \leq d, b \leq c, b \leq d. The set \{ a, b \} has upper bounds c and d, but no least upper bound, and no greatest element (cf. picture).
  • In the rational numbers, the set of numbers with their square less than 2 has upper bounds but no greatest element and no least upper bound.
  • In \mathbb{R}, the set of numbers less than 1 has a least upper bound, viz. 1, but no greatest element.
  • In \mathbb{R}, the set of numbers less than or equal to 1 has a greatest element, viz. 1, which is also its least upper bound.
  • In \mathbb{R}^2 with the product order, the set of pairs (x, y) with 0 < x < 1 has no upper bound.
  • In \mathbb{R}^2 with the lexicographical order, this set has upper bounds, e.g. (1, 0). It has no least upper bound.

See also

Notes

{{reflist|group=note}}

References

{{reflist}}

  • {{cite book | last1=Davey | first1=B. A. | last2=Priestley | first2=H. A. | year = 2002 | title = Introduction to Lattices and Order |title-link= Introduction to Lattices and Order | edition = 2nd | publisher = Cambridge University Press | isbn = 978-0-521-78451-1}}

Category:Order theory

Category:Superlatives