logical positivism
{{short description|Movement in Western philosophy}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=March 2020}}
{{Philosophy sidebar}}
Logical positivism, also known as logical empiricism or neo-positivism, was a philosophical movement, in the empiricist tradition, that sought to formulate a scientific philosophy in which philosophical discourse would be, in the perception of its proponents, as authoritative and meaningful as empirical science.{{cite book |first=Michael |last=Friedman |year=1999 |title=Reconsidering Logical Positivism |publisher=Cambridge University Press |lccn=85030366|page=xiv}}
Logical positivism's central thesis was the verification principle, also known as the "verifiability criterion of meaning", according to which a statement is cognitively meaningful only if it can be verified through empirical observation or if it is a tautology (true by virtue of its own meaning or its own logical form).{{cite book|last=Godfrey-Smith |first=Peter |title=Theory and Reality: an Introduction to the Philosophy of Science |date=2010 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-1-282-64630-8 |oclc=748357235}} The verifiability criterion thus rejected statements of metaphysics, theology, ethics and aesthetics as cognitively meaningless in terms of truth value or factual content. Despite its ambition to overhaul philosophy by mimicking the structure and process of empirical science, logical positivism became erroneously stereotyped as an agenda to regulate the scientific process and to place strict standards on it.
The movement emerged in the late 1920s among philosophers, scientists and mathematicians congregated within the Vienna Circle and Berlin Circle and flourished in several European centres through the 1930s. By the end of World War II, many of its members had settled in the English-speaking world and the project shifted to less radical goals within the philosophy of science.{{cite encyclopedia |first=Thomas |last=Uebel |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2008 |title=Vienna Circle |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Spring 2024 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/vienna-circle/ |access-date=27 February 2025}}
By the 1950s, problems identified within logical positivism's central tenets became seen as intractable, drawing escalating criticism among leading philosophers, notably from Willard van Orman Quine and Karl Popper, and even from within the movement, from Carl Hempel. These problems would remain unresolved, precipitating the movement's eventual decline and abandonment by the 1960s. In 1967, philosopher John Passmore pronounced logical positivism "dead, or as dead as a philosophical movement ever becomes".
Origins
Logical positivism emerged in Germany and Austria amid a cultural background characterised by the dominance of Hegelian metaphysics and the work of Hegelian successors such as F. H. Bradley, whose metaphysics portrayed the world without reference to empirical observation.{{cite book |title=Scientific Inquiry |editor=Robert Klee |last=Suppe |first=Frederick |chapter=The Positivist Model of Scientific Theories |pages=16-24 |year=1999 |publisher=Oxford University Press}} The late 19th century also saw the emergence of neo-Kantianism as a philosophical movement, in the rationalist tradition.{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 3.7
The logical positivist program established its theoretical foundations in the empiricism of David Hume, Auguste Comte and Ernst Mach, along with the positivism of Comte and Mach, defining its exemplar of science in Einstein's general theory of relativity.{{cite book |title=A Dictionary of Philosophy |last=Flew|first=Antony G|page=156 |chapter=Science: Conjectures and refutations |year=1984|publisher=St Martin's Press|location=New York|editor= Andrew Bailey}} In accordance with Mach's phenomenalism, whereby material objects exist only as sensory stimuli rather than as observable entities in the real world, logical positivists took all scientific knowledge to be only sensory experience.{{cite book |last=Ray |first=Christopher |chapter=Logical Positivism |date=September 2017 |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781405164481.ch37 |title=A Companion to the Philosophy of Science |pages=243–251 |editor-last=Newton-Smith |editor-first=W. H. |access-date=2023-10-19 |edition=1st |publisher=Wiley |doi=10.1002/9781405164481.ch37 |isbn=978-0-631-23020-5}} Further influence came from Percy Bridgman's operationalism—whereby a concept is not knowable unless it can be measured experimentally—as well as Immanuel Kant's perspectives on aprioricity.{{cite journal |title=The Myth of Operationism |first=Thomas H. |last=Leahey |journal=The Journal of Mind and Behavior |volume=1 |issue=2 |year=1980 |pages=127-143}}
Ludwig Wittgenstein's Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus established the theoretical foundations for the verifiability principle. Tractatus Proposition 4.024 bears resemblance to Schlick's statement, "To state the circumstances under which a proposition is true is the same as stating its meaning".{{cite journal |last=Schlick |first=Moritz |year=1932 |title=Positivismus und realismus |journal=Erkenntnis |volume=3 |issue=1 |pages=1-31 |doi=10.1007/BF01886406}} English translation in: {{cite book |title=Logical Empiricism at its Peak: Schlick, Carnap, and Neurath |editor-last=Sarkar |editor-first=Sahotra |page=38 |year=1996 |location=New York |publisher=Garland Publishing}} His work introduced the view of philosophy as "critique of language", discussing theoretical distinctions between intelligible and nonsensical discourse. Tractatus adhered to a correspondence theory of truth, as opposed to a coherence theory of truth. Logical positivists were also influenced by Wittgenstein's interpretation of probability though, according to Neurath, some objected to the metaphysics in Tractatus.{{cite book |last=Rand |first=Rose |title=Entwicklung der Thesen des "Wiener Kreises" |year=1933}}
History
=Vienna and Berlin Circles=
{{Main|Vienna Circle}}
The Vienna Circle was led principally by Moritz Schlick, congregating around the University of Vienna and at the Café Central. A manifesto written by Otto Neurath, Hans Hahn and Rudolf Carnap in 1929 summarised the Vienna Circle's positions. Schlick had originally held a neo-Kantian position, but later converted, via Carnap's 1928 book Der logische Aufbau der Welt (The Logical Structure of the World). The Viennese maintained closely cooperative ties with the Berlin Circle, among whom Hans Reichenbach was pre-eminent. Carl Hempel, who studied under Reichenbach in Germany, was also to prove influential in the movement's later history. A friendly but tenacious critic of the movement was Karl Popper, whom Neurath nicknamed the "Official Opposition".{{cite journal |last=Bartley |first=W. W. |year=1982 |title=The Philosophy of Karl Popper Part III. Rationality, Criticism, and Logic |journal=Philosophia |volume=11 |issue=1-2 |pages=121–221 |doi=10.1007/bf02378809 |issn=0048-3893}}
Early in the movement, Carnap, Hahn, Neurath and others recognised that the verifiability criterion was too stringent in that it rejected universal statements, which are vital to scientific hypothesis. A radical left wing emerged from the Vienna Circle, led by Neurath and Carnap, who proposed revisions to weaken the criterion, a program they referred to as the "liberalisation of empiricism". A conservative right wing, led by Schlick and Waismann, instead sought to classify universal statements as analytic truths, thereby to reconcile them with the existing criterion.{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 3.1 Within the liberal wing Carnap emphasised fallibilism, as well as pragmatics, which he considered integral to empiricism. Neurath prescribed a move from Mach's phenomenalism to physicalism, though this would be opposed by Schlick. As Neurath and Carnap sought to pose science toward social reform, the split in the Vienna Circle also reflected political differences.
Both Schlick and Carnap had been influenced by and sought to define logical positivism versus the neo-Kantianism of Ernst Cassirer, the contemporary leading figure of the Marburg school, and against Edmund Husserl's phenomenology. Logical positivists especially opposed Martin Heidegger's obscure metaphysics, the epitome of what they had rejected through their epistemological doctrines. In the early 1930s, Carnap debated Heidegger over "metaphysical pseudosentences".{{harvnb|Friedman|1999}} p. xii
=Anglosphere=
As the movement's first emissary to the New World, Moritz Schlick visited Stanford University in 1929, yet otherwise remained in Vienna and was murdered in 1936 at the University by a former student, Johann Nelböck, who was reportedly deranged. That year, A. J. Ayer, a British attendee at various Vienna Circle meetings since 1933, published Language, Truth and Logic, which imported logical positivism to the English-speaking world. In 1933, the Nazi Party's rise to power in Germany had triggered flight of intellectuals, which accelerated upon Germany's annexation of Austria in 1938. The logical positivists, many of whom were Jewish, were targeted and continued flight throughout the pre-war period. Their philosophy thus became dominant in the English-speaking world.{{cite book |chapter=Logical Positivism The Vienna Circle |first=Bruce |last=Caldwell |year=1984 |title=Beyond Positivism |pages=29–36 |doi=10.4324/9780203565520-7 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-429-23433-0}}
By the late 1930s, many in the movement had replaced phenomenalism with Neurath's physicalism, whereby material objects are not reducible to sensory stimuli but exist as publicly observable entities in the real world. Neurath settled in England, where he died in 1945. Carnap, Reichenbach and Hempel settled permanently in America.
=Post-war period=
Following the Second World War, logical positivism—now referred to by some as logical empiricism—turned to less radical objectives in the philosophy of science. Led by Carl Hempel, who expounded the covering law model of scientific explanation, the movement became a major underpinning of analytic philosophy in the English-speaking world{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 2.1 and its influence extended beyond philosophy into the social sciences. At the same time, the movement drew intensifying scrutiny over its central problems{{cite book |first=L.D. |last=Smith |year=1986 |title=Behaviorism and Logical Positivism: A Reassessment of the Alliance |publisher=Stanford University Press |isbn=978-0804713016 |lccn=85030366 |page=314}}{{cite book |first=M.A. |last=Bunge |year=1996 |title=Finding Philosophy in Social Science |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0300066067 |lccn=lc96004399 |page=317 |quote=However, neo-positivism failed dismally to give a faithful account of science, whether natural or social. It failed because it remained anchored to sense-data and to a phenomenalist metaphysics, overrated the power of induction and underrated that of hypothesis, and denounced realism and materialism as metaphysical nonsense. Although it has never been practiced consistently in the advanced natural sciences and has been criticized by many philosophers, notably Popper (1959, 1963), logical positivism remains the tacit philosophy of many scientists.}} and its doctrines were increasingly criticised, most trenchantly by Willard Van Orman Quine, Norwood Hanson, Karl Popper, Thomas Kuhn and Carl Hempel.
Principles
=Verification and Confirmation=
{{Main|Verificationism}}
==Verifiability Criterion of Meaning==
According to the verifiability criterion of meaning, a statement is cognitively meaningful only if it is either verifiable by empirical observation or is an analytic truth (i.e. true by virtue of its own meaning or its own logical form).{{cite journal |last=Hempel |first=Carl G |title=Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning |journal=Revue Internationale de Philosophie |year=1950 |volume=41 |pages=41–63}} Cognitive meaningfulness was defined variably: possessing truth value; or corresponding to a possible state of affairs; or intelligible or understandable as are scientific statements. Other types of meaning—for instance, emotive, expressive or figurative—were dismissed from further review.Various different views are discussed in Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic, Schlick's "Positivism and realism" (reprinted in {{harvnb|Sarkar|1996}} and {{harvnb|Ayer|1959}}) and Carnap's Philosophy and Logical Syntax.
Metaphysics, theology, as well as much of ethics and aesthetics failed this criterion, and so were found cognitively meaningless and only emotively meaningful (though, notably, Schlick considered ethical and aesthetic statements cognitively meaningful).{{cite journal |last=Allen |first=Barry |year=2007 |title=Turning back the linguistic turn in the theory of knowledge |journal=Thesis Eleven |volume=89 |issue=1 |pages=6–22 |doi=10.1177/0725513607076129 |s2cid=145778455 |quote=In his famous novel Nineteen Eighty-Four George Orwell gave a nice (if for us ironical) explanation of the boon Carnap expects from the logical reform of grammar. Right-thinking Ingsoc party members are as offended as Carnap by the unruliness of language. It's a scandal that grammar allows such pseudo-statements as 'It is the right of the people to alter or abolish Government' (Jefferson), or 'Das Nichts nichtet' (Heidegger). Language as it is makes no objection to such statements, and to Carnap, as to the Party, that's a sore defect. Newspeak, a reformed grammar under development at the Ministry of Truth, will do what Carnap wants philosophical grammar to do.}}{{cite book |last=Schlick |first=Moritz |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LTOaM0X6e6cC&q=%22The+future+of+philosophy%22 |chapter=The future Of philosophy |title=The Linguistic Turn |editor=Richard Rorty |location=Chicago |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1992 |pages=43–53}} Ethics and aesthetics were considered subjective preferences, while theology and metaphysics contained "pseudostatements" that were neither true nor false. Thus, logical positivism indirectly asserted Hume's law, the principle that factual statements cannot justify evaluative statements, and that the two are separated by an unbridgeable gap. A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic (1936) presented an extreme version of this principle—the boo/hooray doctrine—whereby all evaluative judgments are merely emotional reactions.{{cite book |last=Ayer |first=A.J |title=Language, Truth, and Meaning |year=1936 |pages=2,63-77}}
==Revisions to the criterion==
Logical positivists in the Vienna Circle recognised quickly that the verifiability criterion was too restrictive. Specifically, universal statements were noted to be empirically unverifiable, rendering vital domains of science and reason, such as scientific hypothesis, cognitively meaningless under verificationism. This would pose significant problems for the logical positivist program, absent revisions to its criterion of meaning.{{cite encyclopedia |author=John Vicker |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2011 |title=The problem of induction |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Fall 2011 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/induction-problem/#VerCon |quote=This initial formulation of the criterion was soon seen to be too strong; it counted as meaningless not only metaphysical statements but also statements that are clearly empirically meaningful, such as that all copper conducts electricity and, indeed, any universally quantified statement of infinite scope, as well as statements that were at the time beyond the reach of experience for technical, and not conceptual, reasons, such as that there are mountains on the back side of the moon. |access-date=24 August 2012}}
In his 1936 and 1937 papers, Testability and Meaning, Carnap proposed confirmation in place of verification, determining that, though universal laws cannot be verified, they can be confirmed. Carnap employed abundant logical and mathematical tools to research an inductive logic that would account for probability according to degrees of confirmation. However, he was never able to formulate a model. In Carnap's inductive logic, a universal law's degree of confirmation was always zero.{{cite encyclopedia |last=Murzi |first=Mauro |url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/carnap |title=Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970) |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |year=2001}} The formulation of what eventually came to be called the "criterion of cognitive significance", stemming from this research, took three decades (Hempel 1950, Carnap 1956, Carnap 1961). Carl Hempel, who became a prominent critic of the logical positivist movement, elucidated the paradox of confirmation.{{cite encyclopedia |last=Crupi |first=Vincenzo |title=Confirmation |year=2021 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/confirmation/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2023-07-10 |edition=Spring 2021}}
In his 1936 book, Language, Truth and Logic, A. J. Ayer distinguished strong and weak verification. He stipulated that, "A proposition is said to be verifiable, in the strong sense of the term, if, and only if, its truth could be conclusively established by experience", but is verifiable in the weak sense "if it is possible for experience to render it probable". He would add that, "no proposition, other than a tautology, can possibly be anything more than a probable hypothesis". Thus, he would conclude that all are open to weak verification.{{harvnb|Ayer|1936}} pp. 50–51
=Analytic-synthetic distinction=
{{Main|Analytic-synthetic distinction}}
In theories of justification, a priori statements are those that can be known independently of observation, contrasting with a posteriori statements, which are dependent on observation. Statements may also be categorised into analytic and synthetic: Analytic statements are true by virtue of their own meaning or their own logical form, therefore are tautologies that are true by necessity but uninformative about the world. Synthetic statements, in comparison, are contingent propositions that refer to a state of facts concerning the world.{{cite encyclopedia |last=Rey |first=Georges |title=The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction |date=2023 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/analytic-synthetic/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2023-07-10 |edition=Spring 2023 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |editor2-last=Nodelman |editor2-first=Uri}}{{cite encyclopedia |title=Quine, Willard Van Orman: Analytic/Synthetic Distinction |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/quine-an/ |access-date=2023-07-10}}
David Hume proposed an unambiguous distinction between analytic and synthetic, categorising knowledge exclusively as either "relations of ideas" (which are a priori, analytic and abstract) or "matters of fact and real existence" (a posteriori, synthetic and concrete), a classification referred to as Hume's fork.{{cite book |last=Flew |first=Antony |title=A Dictionary of Philosophy |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MmJHVU9Rv3YC&pg=PA156 |edition=2nd |year=1984 |publisher=St. Martin's Press |location=New York |isbn=978-0-312-20923-0 |page=156}}{{cite book |last=Mitchell |first=Helen Buss |title=Roots of Wisdom: A Tapestry of Philosophical Traditions |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=P6o0OUzwmSAC&pg=PA249 |year=2010 |publisher=Cengage Learning |isbn=978-0-495-80896-1 |pages=249–50}} Immanuel Kant identified a further category of knowledge: Synthetic a priori statements, which are informative about the world, but known without observation. This principle is encapsulated in Kant's transcendental idealism, which attributes the mind a constructive role in phenomena whereby intuitive truths—including synthetic a priori conceptions of space and time—function as an interpretative filter for an observer's experience of the world.{{cite encyclopedia |last=Rohlf |first=Michael |title=Immanuel Kant |year=2010 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant/#TraIde |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2025-02-02 |edition=Summer 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}} His thesis would serve to rescue Newton's law of universal gravitation from Hume's problem of induction by determining uniformity of nature to be in the category of a priori knowledge.{{cite encyclopedia |last1=De Pierris |first1=Graciela |last2=Friedman |first2=Michael |title=Kant and Hume on Causality |year=2008 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-hume-causality/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |access-date=2025-02-02 |edition=Summer 2024 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University}}
The Vienna Circle rejected Kant's conception of synthetic a priori knowledge given its incompatibility with the verifiability criterion.{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 2.3 Yet, they adopted the Kantian position of defining mathematics and logic—ordinarily considered synthetic truths—as a priori.{{cite book |title=Early Analytic Philosophy: Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein |editor1=William W. Tait |editor2=Leonard Linsky |editor2-link=Leonard Linsky |author=Michael Friedman |chapter=Carnap and Wittgenstein's Tractatus |page=29 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eNA_TdDTNkMC&pg=PA29 |isbn=978-0812693447 |year=1997 |publisher=Open Court Publishing}} Carnap's solution to this discrepancy would be to reinterpret logical truths as tautologies, redefining logic as analytic, building upon theoretical foundations established in Wittgenstein's Tractatus. Mathematics, in turn, would be reduced to logic through the logicist approach proposed by Gottlob Frege. In effect, Carnap's reconstruction of analyticity expounded Hume's fork, affirming its analytic-synthetic distinction. This would be critically important in rendering the verification principle compatible with mathematics and logic.{{cite book |title=Realistic Rationalism |author=Jerrold J. Katz |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=szCaXDdhID8C&pg=PA69 |page=69 |chapter=The epistemic challenge to antirealism |isbn=978-0262263290 |year=2000 |publisher=MIT Press}}
=Observation-theory distinction=
{{See also|Ramsey sentence}}
Carnap devoted much of his career to the cornerstone doctrine of rational reconstruction, whereby scientific theories can be formalised into predicate logic and the components of a theory categorised into observation terms and theoretical terms.{{cite encyclopedia |first1=Hannes |last1=Leitgeb |first2=André |last2=Carus |year=2020 |title=Supplement to "Rudolf Carnap": E. The Reconstruction of Scientific Theories |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/carnap/reconstruct-sci-theories.html |access-date=2025-02-04 }} Observation terms are specified by direct observation and thus assumed to have fixed empirical definitions, whereas theoretical terms refer to the unobservables of a theory, including abstract conceptions such as mathematical formulas. The two categories of primitive terms would be interconnected in meaning via a deductive interpretative framework, referred to as correspondence rules.{{cite journal |first=John A. |last=Winnie |title=The Implicit Definition of Theoretical Terms |journal=J. Phil. Sci. |volume=18 |year=1967 |pages=223-229 }}
Early in his research, Carnap postulated that correspondence rules could be used to define theoretical terms from observation terms, contending that scientific knowledge could be unified by reducing theoretical laws to "protocol sentences" grounded in observable facts. He would soon abandon this model of reconstruction, suggesting instead that theoretical terms could be defined implicitly by the axioms of a theory. Furthermore, that observation terms could, in some cases, garner meaning from theoretical terms via correspondence rules.{{cite book |first=Sebastian |last=Lutz |editor1=S. Lutz |editor2=A.T. Tuboly |chapter=Two Constants in Carnap’s View on Scientific Theories |year=2021 |doi=10.4324/9780429429835 |title=Logical Empiricism and the Physical Sciences |publisher=Routledge |pages=354-378}} Here, definition is said to be 'implicit' in that the axioms serve to exclude those interpretations that falsify the theory. Thus, axioms define theoretical terms indirectly by restricting the set of possible interpretations to those that are true interpretations.
By reconstructing the semantics of scientific language, Carnap's thesis builds upon earlier research in the reconstruction of syntax, referring to Bertrand Russell's logical atomism—the view that statements in natural language can be converted to standardised subunits of meaning assembled via a logical syntax.{{cite book |last=Russell |first=Bertrand |chapter=The Philosophy of Logical Atomism [1918] |date=1988 |title=The Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell, Volume 8 |pages=157–244 |doi=10.4324/9781003557036-20 |location=London |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-003-55703-6 |editor=John G Slater}} Rational reconstruction is sometimes referred to as the received view or syntactic view of theories in the context of subsequent work by Carl Hempel, Ernest Nagel and Herbert Feigl.
=Logicism=
By reducing mathematics to logic, Bertrand Russell sought to convert the mathematical formulas of physics to symbolic logic. Gottlob Frege began this program of logicism, continuing it with Russell, but eventually lost interest. Russell then continued it with Alfred North Whitehead in their Principia Mathematica, inspiring some of the more mathematical logical positivists, such as Hans Hahn and Rudolf Carnap.{{cite book |last=Hintikka |first=Jaako |chapter=Logicism |title=Philosophy of Mathematics |editor1=Andrew D Irvine |publisher=North Holland |location=Burlington MA |year=2009 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mbn35b2ghgkC&pg=PA283 |pages=283–84}}
Carnap's early anti-metaphysical works employed Russell's theory of types.{{cite journal |last=Schlick |first=Moritz |year=1932 |title=The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language |journal=Erkenntnis |volume=2 |issue=1 |pages=1-31 |doi=10.1007/BF01886406}} Reprinted in {{cite book |title=Logical Positivism |last=Ayer |first=Alfred Jules |pages=60-81 |year=1959 |location=New York |publisher=Free Press}} Like Russell, Carnap envisioned a universal language that could reconstruct mathematics and thereby encode physics. Yet Kurt Gödel's incompleteness theorem showed this to be impossible, except in trivial cases, and Alfred Tarski's undefinability theorem finally undermined all hopes of reducing mathematics to logic. Thus, a universal language failed to stem from Carnap's 1934 work Logische Syntax der Sprache (Logical Syntax of Language). Still, some logical positivists, including Carl Hempel, continued support of logicism.
Philosophy of science
The logical positivist movement shed much of its revolutionary zeal following the defeat of Nazism and the decline of rival philosophies that sought radical reform, notably Marburg neo-Kantianism, Husserlian phenomenology and Heidegger's existential hermeneutics. Hosted in the climate of American pragmatism and common sense empiricism, its proponents no longer crusaded to revise traditional philosophy into a radical scientific philosophy, but became respectable members of a new philosophical subdiscipline, philosophy of science. Receiving support from Ernest Nagel, they were especially influential in the social sciences.{{cite book |last=Novick |first=Peter |title=That Noble Dream |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1988 |page=546}}
=Scientific explanation=
{{See also|Deductive-nomological model}}
Carl Hempel was prominent in the development of the deductive-nomological (DN) model, then the foremost model of scientific explanation defended even among critics of neo-positivism such as Popper.{{cite encyclopedia |first=James |last=Woodward |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scientific-explanation |title=Scientific explanation |editor=Edward N. Zalta |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Winter 2011}} According to the DN model, a scientific explanation is valid only if it takes the form of a deductive inference from a set of explanatory premises (explanans) to the observation or theory to be explained (explanandum).{{cite book |last=Frederick Suppe |first=Frederick |title=The Structure of Scientific Theories |publisher=University of Illinois Press |year=1977 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SpvZsxCA0TIC&pg=PA619 |edition=2nd |pages=619–21}} The model stipulates that the premises must refer to at least one law, which it defines as an unrestricted generalization of the conditional form: "If A, then B".{{cite book |first=Eleonora |last=Montuschi |title=Objects in Social Science |publisher=Continuum |year=2003 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=bQ24-BV8WSAC&pg=PA62 |pages=61–62}} Laws therefore differ from mere regularities ("George always carries only $1 bills in his wallet") which do not necessarily support counterfactual claims.{{cite book| last=Bechtel |first=William |title=Philosophy of Science: An Overview for Cognitive Science |location=Hillsdale NJ |publisher=Lawrence Erlbaum Assoc. |year=1988 |pages=25-28}} Furthermore, laws must be empirically verifiable in compliance with the verification principle.
The DN model ignores causal mechanisms beyond the principle of constant conjunction ("first event A and then always event B") in accordance with the Humean empiricist postulate that, though sequences of events are observable, the underpinning causal principles are not. Hempel stated that well-formulated natural laws (empirically confirmed regularities) are satisfactory in approximating causal explanation.
Hempel later proposed a probabilistic model of scientific explanation: The inductive-statistical (IS) model. Derivation of statistical laws from other statistical laws would further be designated as the deductive-statistical (DS) model. The DN and IS models are collectively referred to as the "covering law model" or "subsumption theory", the latter referring to the movement's stated goals of "theory reduction".{{cite book |first=Manfred |last=Riedel |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=It3ji_AuO3sC&dq=Covering+subsumption&pg=PA3 |chapter=Causal and Historical Explanation |pages=3–4 |editor1=Manninen J |editor2=Tuomela R. |title=Essays on Explanation and Understanding: Studies in the Foundation of Humanities and Social Sciences |location=Dordrecht |publisher=D. Reidel Publishing |year=1976}}
=Unity of science=
{{See also|Unity of science}}
Logical positivists were committed to the vision of a unified science encompassing all scientific fields (including the special sciences, such as biology, anthropology, sociology and economics, and the fundamental science, or fundamental physics) which would be synthesised into a singular epistemic entity.{{cite journal |first=Gregory |last=Frost-Arnold |url=https://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00002005/01/PSA2004Short.rtf |title=The Large Scale Structure of Logical Empiricism: Unity of Science and the Elimination of Metaphysics |journal=Philosophy of Science |volume=72 |issue=5 |year=2005 |pages=826-838 |doi=10.1086/508113}} Key to this concept was the doctrine of theory reduction, according to which the covering law model would be used to interconnect the special sciences and, thereupon, to reduce all laws in the special sciences to fundamental physics.{{cite book |last=Kuhn |first=Thomas S. |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.7208/chicago/9780226458106.001.0001 |title=The Structure of Scientific Revolutions |date=1996 |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-45808-3}}
The movement envisioned a universal scientific language that could express statements with common meaning intelligible to all scientific fields. Carnap sought to realise this goal through the systematic reduction of the linguistic terms of more specialised fields to those of more fundamental fields. Various methods of reduction were proposed, referring to the use of set theory to manipulate logically primitive concepts (as in Carnap's Logical Structure of the World, 1928) or via analytic and a priori deductive operations (as described in Testability and Meaning, 1936, 1937). A number of publications over a period of thirty years would attempt to elucidate this concept.{{cite book |last=Hinst |first=Peter |chapter=Carnap, Rudolf: Der logische Aufbau der Welt |date=2020 |title=Kindlers Literatur Lexikon (KLL) |pages=1–2 |doi=10.1007/978-3-476-05728-0_9509-1 |location=Stuttgart |publisher=J.B. Metzler |isbn=978-3-476-05728-0}}{{cite book |last=Sarkar |first=Sahotra |chapter=Rudolf Carnap Testability and Meaning |year=2021 |title=Logical Empiricism at its Peak |pages=200–265 |doi=10.4324/9781003249573-13 |location=New York |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-003-24957-3}}
Criticism
In the post-war period, key tenets of logical positivism, including the verifiability criterion, analytic-synthetic distinction and observation-theory distinction, drew escalated criticism. This would become sustained from various directions by the 1950s,{{cite book |first1=S |last1=Sarkar |first2=J |last2=Pfeifer |year=2005 |title=The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia |volume=1 |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-0415939270 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=od68ge7aF6wC&pg=PA83 |page=83}} so that, even among fractious philosophers who disagreed on the general objectives of epistemology, most would concur that the logical positivist program had become untenable.{{cite book |author=Hilary Putnam |year=1985 |title=Philosophical Papers: Volume 3, Realism and Reason |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0521313940 |lccn=lc82012903}} Notable critics included Karl Popper, W. V. O. Quine, Norwood Hanson, Thomas Kuhn, Hilary Putnam, as well as J. L. Austin, Peter Strawson, Nelson Goodman and Richard Rorty.{{cite journal |last=Franco |first=Paul L. |year=2018 |title= Ordinary Language Criticisms of Logical Positivism |journal=HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science |volume=8 |issue=1 |pages=157-190}} Hempel himself became a major critic from within the movement, denouncing the positivist thesis that empirical knowledge is restricted to basic statements, observation statements or protocol statements.{{cite encyclopedia |first=James |last=Fetzer |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2012 |title=Carl Hempel |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Summer 2012 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hempel/#SciRea |access-date=31 August 2012}}
=Karl Popper=
Karl Popper, a graduate of the University of Vienna, was an outspoken critic of the logical positivist movement from its inception. In Logik der Forschung (1934, published in English in 1959 as The Logic of Scientific Discovery) he attacked verificationism directly, contending that the problem of induction renders it impossible for scientific hypotheses and other universal statements to be verified conclusively. Any attempt to do so, he argued, would commit the fallacy of affirming the consequent, given that verification cannot—in itself—exclude alternative valid explanations for a specific phenomenon or instance of observation.{{cite book|first=Samir |last=Okasha |title=The Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction |location=New York |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2002 |page=23}} He would later affirm that the content of the verifiability criterion cannot be empirically verified, thus is meaningless by its own proposition and ultimately self-defeating as a principle.{{cite encyclopedia |url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/pop-sci/#H3 |title=Karl Popper: Philosophy of Science |last=Shea |first=Brendan |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=May 12, 2019}}
In the same book, Popper proposed falsifiability, which he presented, not as a criterion of cognitive meaning like verificationism (as commonly misunderstood),{{cite book |title=Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 1902–1945: Politics and Philosophy in Interwar Vienna |last=Hacohen |first=Malachi Haim |year=2000 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge |pages=212-13}} but as a criterion to distinguish scientific from non-scientific statements, thereby to demarcate the boundaries of science. Popper observed that, though universal statements cannot be verified, they can be falsified, and that the most productive scientific theories were apparently those that carried the greatest 'predictive risks' of being falsified by observation.{{cite book |title=Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge |last=Popper |first=Karl |year=1962 |publisher=Routledge |edition=2nd |pages=34-37}} He would conclude that the scientific method should be a hypothetico-deductive model, wherein scientific hypotheses must be falsifiable (per his criterion), held as provisionally true until proven false by observation, and are corroborated by supporting evidence rather than verified or confirmed.{{cite book |last=Popper |first=Karl |title=The Logic of Scientific Discovery |doi=10.4324/9780203994627 |publisher=Routledge |location=London |year=2005 |edition=2nd}}
In rejecting neo-positivist views of cognitive meaningfulness, Popper considered metaphysics to be rich in meaning and important in the origination of scientific theories and value systems to be integral to science's quest for truth. At the same time, he disparaged pseudoscience, referring to the confirmation biases that embolden support for unfalsifiable conjectures (notably those in psychology and psychoanalysis) and ad hoc arguments used to entrench predictive theories that have been proven conclusively false.
=Willard V. O. Quine=
In his influential 1951 paper Two Dogmas of Empiricism, American philosopher and logicist Willard Van Orman Quine challenged the analytic-synthetic distinction. Specifically, Quine examined the concept of analyticity, determining that all attempts to explain the idea reduce ultimately to circular reasoning. He would conclude that, if analyticity is untenable, so too is the neo-positivist proposition to redefine its boundaries.{{cite journal |first=Willard V. O. |last=Quine |title=Two Dogmas of Empiricism |journal=Philosophical Review |year=1951 |volume=60 |pages=20–43}} collected in {{cite book |first=Willard V. O. |last=Quine |title=From a Logical Point of View |location=Cambridge MA |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=1953}} Yet Carnap's reconstruction of analyticity was necessary for logic and mathematics to be deemed meaningful under verificationism. Quine's arguments encompassed numerous criticisms on this topic he had articulated to Carnap since 1933.{{cite encyclopedia |url=https://iep.utm.edu/quine-an/#H2 |title=Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction |last=Rocknak |first=Stefanie |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date= July 14, 2024}} His work effectively pronounced the verifiability criterion untenable, threatening to uproot the broader logical positivist project.{{cite book |last=Shieh |first=Sanford |chapter=Logical Positivism and Quine |title=A Companion to the Philosophy of Language |year=2012 |publisher=Routledge |pages=869-872 |editor1=D. Graff Fara |editor2=G. Russell}}
=Norwood Hanson=
In 1958, Norwood Hanson's Patterns of Discovery characterised the concept of theory-ladenness. Hanson and Thomas Kuhn held that even direct observations are never truly neutral in that they are laden with theory, i.e. influenced by a system of theoretical presuppositions that function as an interpretative framework for the senses.{{cite book |title=Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the 20th Century |last=Caldwell|first=Bruce|pages=47-48 |year=1994 |publisher=Routledge |location=London}} Accordingly, individuals subscribed to different theories might report radically different observations even as they investigate the same phenomena. Hanson's thesis attacked the observation-theory distinction, which draws a dividing line between observational and non-observational (theoretical) language. More broadly, its findings challenged the central-most tenets of empiricism in questioning the infallibility and objectivity of empirical observation.{{cite encyclopedia |first=Nora Mills |last=Boyd |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2009 |edition=2021 |title=Theory and Observation in Science |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/science-theory-observation/ |access-date=29 January 2025}}
=Thomas Kuhn=
Thomas Kuhn's landmark book of 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions—which discussed paradigm shifts in fundamental physics—critically undermined confidence in scientific foundationalism.{{cite book |title=Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction |last=Okasha|first=Samir|year=2002 |chapter=Scientific Change and Scientific Revolutions |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford}} Kuhn proposed in its place a coherentist model of science, whereby scientific progress revolves around cores of established, coherent ideas which periodically undergo abrupt revolutionary changes.{{cite journal |last=Daston |first=Lorraine |year=2020 |title=Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/08992363-8090152 |journal=Public Culture |volume=32 |issue=2 |pages=405–413 |doi=10.1215/08992363-8090152 |issn=0899-2363}}
Though foundationalism was often considered a constituent doctrine of logical positivism (and Kuhn's thesis an epistemological criticism of the movement) such views were simplistic:{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 3.3 In the 1930s, Neurath had argued for the adoption of coherentism, famously comparing the progress of science to reconstruction of a boat at sea.{{cite book|title=Otto Neurath: Philosophy Between Science and Politics |volume=38 |series=Ideas in Context |first1=Nancy |last1=Cartwright |author-link1=Nancy Cartwright (philosopher) |first2=Jordi |last2=Cat |first3=Lola |last3=Fleck |first4=Thomas E. |last4=Uebel |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2008 |isbn=978-0521041119 |chapter=On Neurath's Boat |pages=89–94}} Carnap had entertained foundationalism from 1929 to 1930, but he, Hans Hahn and others would later join Neurath in converting to a coherentist philosophy. The conservative wing of the Vienna Circle under Moritz Schlick subscribed to a form of foundationalism, but its principles were defined unconventionally or ambiguously.{{harvnb|Uebel|2008}} 3.3 Uebel writes, "Even Schlick conceded, however, that all scientific statements were fallible ones, so his position on foundationalism was by no means the traditional one. The point of his “foundations” remained less than wholly clear and different interpretation of it have been put forward."
In some sense, Kuhn's book unified science, but through historical and social assessment rather than by networking the scientific specialties using epistemological or linguistic models.{{harvnb|Novick|1988}} pp. 526–27 His ideas were adopted quickly by scholars in non-scientific disciplines, such as the social sciences in which neo-positivists were dominant, ushering academia into postpositivism or postempiricism.
=Hilary Putnam=
In his critique of the received view in 1962, Hilary Putnam attacked the observation-theory distinction.{{cite book |title=Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science |last=Putnam |first=Hilary |pages=240–251 |chapter=What Theories are Not |year=1962 |publisher=Stanford University Press |location=Stanford |editor1= E. Nagel |editor2=P. Suppes |editor3=A. Tarski }} Putnam proposed that the division between "observation terms" and "theoretical terms" was untenable, determining that both categories have the potential to be theory-laden. Accordingly, he remarked that observational reports frequently refer to theoretical terms in practice.{{cite book |first=Hilary |last=Putnam |chapter=Problems with the observational/theoretical distinction |title=Scientific Inquiry |editor=Robert Klee |location=New York |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1999 |pages=25–29}} He illustrated cases in which observation terms can be applied to entities that Carnap would classify as unobservables. For example, in Newton's corpuscular theory of light, observation concepts can be applied to the consideration of both sub-microscopic and macroscopic objects.{{cite encyclopedia |last=Andreas |first=Holger |editor=Edward N. Zalta |year=2013 |edition=August 2021 |title=Theoretical Terms in Science |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/theoretical-terms-science/ |access-date=30 January 2025}}
Putnam advocated scientific realism, whereby scientific theory describes a real world existing independently of the senses. He rejected positivism, which he dismissed as a form of metaphysical idealism, in that it precluded any possibility to acquire knowledge of the unobservable aspects of nature. He also spurned instrumentalism, according to which a scientific theory is judged, not by whether it corresponds to reality, but by the extent to which it allows empirical predictions or resolves conceptual problems.
Decline and legacy
In 1967, John Passmore wrote, "Logical positivism is dead, or as dead as a philosophical movement ever becomes".{{cite book |title=Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century |chapter=Logical positivism |last=Hanfling |first=Oswald| editor=Stuart G Shanker |year=1996 |publisher=Routledge |pages=193-94}} His opinions concurred with widespread sentiment in academic circles that the movement had run its course by the late 1960s.{{cite book |author=Nicholas G Fotion |editor=Ted Honderich |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |year=1995 |page=508 |isbn=978-0-19-866132-0 |url=https://archive.org/details/oxfordcompaniont00hond/page/508 }} Logical positivism's fall heralded postpositivism, distinguished by Popper's critical rationalism—which characterised human knowledge as continuously evolving via conjectures and refutations—and Kuhn's historical and social perspectives on the saltatory course of scientific progress.{{cite book |author1=William Stahl |author2=Robert A. Campbell |author3=Gary Diver |author4=Yvonne Petry |title=Webs of Reality: Social Perspectives on Science and Religion |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GY6i84rSKMcC&pg=PA180 |year=2002 |publisher=Rutgers University Press |isbn=978-0-8135-3107-6 |page=180}}
In a 1976 interview, A. J. Ayer, who had introduced logical positivism to the English-speaking world in the 1930s,{{cite book |title=Key ideas in linguistics and the philosophy of language |chapter=Logical positivism |last=Chapman |first=Siobhan| editor1=Siobhan Chapman |editor2=Christopher Routledge |year=2009 |publisher=Edinburgh University Press |location=Edinburgh}} was asked what he saw as its main defects and answered that, "nearly all of it was false". Yet, he maintained that it was "true in spirit", referring to the principles of empiricism and reductionism whereby mental phenomena resolve to the material or physical and philosophical questions largely resolve to ones of language and meaning.{{cite web |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=4cnRJGs08hE |title=Ayer on Logical Positivism: Section 4 |website=YouTube |at=6:30}} Despite its problems, logical positivism helped to anchor analytic philosophy in the English-speaking world and its influence extended beyond philosophy in shaping the course of psychology and the social sciences. In the post-war period, Carl Hempel's contributions were vitally important in establishing the subdiscipline of the philosophy of science.
Logical positivism's fall reopened the debate over the metaphysical merit of scientific theory, whether it can offer knowledge of the world beyond human experience (scientific realism) or whether it is simply an instrument to predict human experience (instrumentalism).{{cite book |first=Hilary |last=Putnam |chapter=What is realism? |editor=Jarrett Leplin |title=Scientific Realism |publisher=University of California Press |year=1984 |page=140 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zhBeVFm8WuAC&dq=Realism+realists+positivism+opera-tionalism&pg=PA140}}{{cite journal |first=Ruth |last=Lane |doi=10.1177/0951692896008003003 |title=Positivism, scientific realism and political science: Recent developments in the philosophy of science |journal=Journal of Theoretical Politics |year=1996 |volume=8 |issue=3 |pages=361–82}} Philosophers increasingly critiqued the movement's doctrine and history, often misrepresenting it without thorough examination,{{harvnb|Friedman|1999}} p. 1 sometimes reducing it to oversimplifications and stereotypes, such as its association with foundationalism.{{harvnb|Friedman|1999}} p. 2
See also
{{cols}}
- {{Annotated link |Definitions of philosophy}}
- {{Annotated link |Anti-realism}}
- {{Annotated link |Sociological positivism}}
- {{Annotated link |Academic skepticism}}
- {{Annotated link |The Structure of Science}}
- {{Annotated link |Raven paradox}}
- {{Annotated link |Unobservable}}
{{colend}}
=People=
- {{Annotated link |Ernst Mach}}
- {{Annotated link |Gottlob Frege}}
- {{Annotated link |Friedrich Waismann}}
- {{Annotated link |Gustav Bergmann}}
- {{Annotated link |Herbert Feigl}}
- {{Annotated link |Kurt Grelling}}
- {{Annotated link |R. B. Braithwaite}}
References
{{Reflist}}
Further reading
{{refbegin}}
- {{cite book |last1=Achinstein |first1=Peter |last2=Barker |first2=Stephen F. |title=The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science |location=Baltimore |publisher=Johns Hopkins Press |year=1969}}
- {{cite book |last=Bergmann |first=Gustav |title=The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism |location=New York |publisher=Longmans Green |year=1954}}
- {{cite book |last=Cirera |first=Ramon |title=Carnap and the Vienna Circle: Empiricism and Logical Syntax |location=Atlanta, GA |publisher=Rodopi |year=1994}}
- {{cite SEP |url-id=logical-empiricism/ |title=Logical Empiricism |last=Creath |first=Richard}}
- {{cite book |last=Gadol |first=Eugene T. |title=Rationality and Science: A Memorial Volume for Moritz Schlick in Celebration of the Centennial of his Birth |location=Wien |publisher=Springer |year=1982}}
- {{cite book |last1=Giere |first1=Ronald N. |last2=Richardson |first2=Alan W. |title=Origins of Logical Empiricism |location=Minneapolis |publisher=University of Minnesota Press |year=1997}}
- {{cite SEP |url-id=probability-interpret/ |title=Interpretations of Probability |last=Hájek |first=Alan}}
- {{cite journal |first=Jim |last=Holt |title=Positive Thinking |journal=The New York Review of Books |volume=64 |issue=20 |year=2017 |pages=74–76}}
- {{cite book |last=Jangam |first=R. T. |title=Logical Positivism and Politics |location=Delhi |publisher=Sterling Publishers |year=1970}}
- {{cite book |last1=Janik |first1=Allan |last2=Toulmin |first2=Stephen |title=Wittgenstein's Vienna |location=London |publisher=Weidenfeld and Nicolson |year=1973}}
- {{cite book |last=Kraft |first=Victor |title=The Vienna Circle: The Origin of Neo-positivism, a Chapter in the History of Recent Philosophy |location=New York |publisher=Greenwood Press |year=1953}}
- {{cite book |last=McGuinness |first=Brian |title=Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations Recorded by Friedrich Waismann |editor1=Joachim Schulte |editor2=Brian McGuinness |location=New York |publisher=Barnes & Noble Books |year=1979}}
- {{cite book |editor=Milkov, Nikolay |title=Die Berliner Gruppe. Texte zum Logischen Empirismus von Walter Dubislav, Kurt Grelling, Carl G. Hempel, Alexander Herzberg, Kurt Lewin, Paul Oppenheim und Hans Reichenbach |location=Hamburg |publisher=Meiner |year=2015}}
- {{cite book |last=Mises von |first=Richard |title=Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding |location=Cambridge |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=1951}}
- {{cite book |last=Murzi |first=Mauro |chapter=Logical Positivism |title=The New Encyclopedia of Unbelief |editor=Tom Flynn |publisher=Prometheus Books |year=2007}}
- {{cite book |last=Parrini |first=Paolo |title=Empirismo logico e convenzionalismo: saggio di storia della filosofia della scienza |location=Milano |publisher=F. Angeli |year=1983}}
- {{cite book |editor1=Parrini, Paolo |editor2=Salmon, Wesley C. |editor3=Salmon, Merrilee H. |title=Logical Empiricism – Historical and Contemporary Perspectives |location=Pittsburgh |publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press |year=2003}}
- {{cite book |last=Passmore |first=John |chapter=Logical Positivism |title=The Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor=Paul Edwards |location=New York |publisher=Macmillan |year=1967 |edition=1st}}
- {{cite book |last=Reisch |first=George |title=How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science: To the Icy Slopes of Logic |location=New York |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2005}}
- {{cite book |last=Rescher |first=Nicholas |title=The Heritage of Logical Positivism |location=Lanham, MD |publisher=University Press of America |year=1985}}
- {{cite book |editor1=Alan Richardson |editor2=Thomas Uebel |title=The Cambridge Companion to Logical Positivism |location=New York |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2007}}
- {{cite SEP |url-id=genrel-early/ |title=Early Philosophical Interpretations of General Relativity |last=Ryckman |first=Thomas A.}}
- {{cite book |editor1=Salmon, Wesley |editor2=Wolters, Gereon |title=Logic, Language, and the Structure of Scientific Theories: Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Konstanz, 21–24 May 1991 |location=Pittsburgh |publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press |year=1994}}
- {{cite book |editor=Sarkar, Sahotra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eS8jeSgy8eIC&q=positivism |title=The Emergence of Logical Empiricism: From 1900 to the Vienna Circle |location=New York |publisher=Garland Publishing |year=1996}}
- {{cite book |editor=Sarkar, Sahotra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=H-OdzRfpehEC&q=positivism |title=Logical Empiricism and the Special Sciences: Reichenbach, Feigl, and Nagel |location=New York |publisher=Garland Publishing |year=1996}}
- {{cite book |editor=Sarkar, Sahotra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NiQBRoKrVW0C&q=positivism |title=Decline and Obsolescence of Logical Empiricism: Carnap vs. Quine and the Critics |location=New York |publisher=Garland Publishing |year=1996}}
- {{cite book |editor=Sarkar, Sahotra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FJ68n_9XXAwC&q=positivism |title=The Legacy of the Vienna Circle: Modern Reappraisals |location=New York |publisher=Garland Publishing |year=1996}}
- {{cite book |editor=Spohn, Wolfgang |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ED3sCAAAQBAJ&q=positivism |title=Erkenntnis Orientated: A Centennial Volume for Rudolf Carnap and Hans Reichenbach |location=Boston |publisher=Kluwer Academic Publishers |year=1991}}
- {{cite book |last=Stadler |first=Friedrich |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2rAlCQAAQBAJ&q=positivism |title=The Vienna Circle. Studies in the Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism |location=Dordrecht|publisher=Springer |year=2015 |edition=2nd}}
- {{cite book |editor=Stadler, Friedrich |title=The Vienna Circle and Logical Empiricism. Re-evaluation and Future Perspectives |location=Dordrecht |publisher=Kluwer |year=2003}}
- {{cite journal |last=Werkmeister |first=William |title=Seven Theses of Logical Positivism Critically Examined |journal=The Philosophical Review |volume=46 |issue=3 |pages=276–297 |date=May 1937 |doi=10.2307/2181086 |jstor=2181086}}
{{refend}}
External links
- {{Commons category-inline}}
Articles by logical positivists
- [https://sites.google.com/site/gnadav/TheScientificConceptionoftheWorldeng.doc The Scientific Conception of the World: The Vienna Circle]
- [http://www.calstatela.edu/dept/phil/pdf/res/Carnap-Elimination-of-Metaphysics.pdf Carnap, Rudolf. 'The Elimination of Metaphysics Through Logical Analysis of Language']
- [http://www.ditext.com/carnap/carnap.html Carnap, Rudolf. 'Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.']
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20051215185548/http://philosophy.ru/edu/ref/sci/carnap.html Excerpt from Carnap, Rudolf. Philosophy and Logical Syntax.]
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20110511191629/http://etext.lib.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/dhicontrib2.cgi?id=dv3-69 Feigl, Herbert. 'Positivism in the Twentieth Century (Logical Empiricism)', Dictionary of the History of Ideas, 1974, Gale Group (Electronic Edition)]
Articles on logical positivism
- [http://www.philosophypages.com/hy/6q.htm Kemerling, Garth. 'Logical Positivism', Philosophy Pages]
- [http://murzim.net/LP/LP00.html Murzi, Mauro. 'The Philosophy of Logical Positivism.']
{{Navboxes
|title=Articles related to logical positivism
|list=
{{analytic philosophy}}
{{positivism}}
{{philosophy of language}}
}}
{{Authority control}}
Category:Epistemological theories
Category:Epistemology of science
Category:Meaning in religious language
Category:Philosophical schools and traditions