strong programme

{{Use dmy dates|date=April 2022}}

{{third-party|date=July 2019}}

The strong programme or strong sociology is a variety of the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK) particularly associated with David Bloor,David Bloor, "The strengths of the strong programme." Scientific rationality: The sociological turn (Springer Netherlands, 1984) pp. 75-94. Barry Barnes, Harry Collins, Donald A. MacKenzie,Donald MacKenzie, "Notes on the science and social relations debate." Capital & Class 5.2 (1981): 47-60. and John Henry. The strong programme's influence on science and technology studies is credited as being unparalleled (Latour 1999). The largely Edinburgh-based school of thought aims to illustrate how the existence of a scientific community, bound together by allegiance to a shared paradigm, is a prerequisite for normal scientific activity.

The strong programme is a reaction against "weak" sociologies of science, which restricted the application of sociology to "failed" or "false" theories, such as phrenology. Failed theories would be explained by citing the researchers' biases, such as covert political or economic interests. Sociology would be only marginally relevant to successful theories, which succeeded because they had revealed a fact of nature. The strong programme proposed that both "true" and "false" scientific theories should be treated the same way. Both are caused by social factors or conditions, such as cultural context and self-interest. All human knowledge, as something that exists in the human cognition, must contain some social components in its formation process.

Characteristics

As formulated by David Bloor,David Bloor, Knowledge and Social Imagery (1976) the strong programme has four indispensable components:

  1. Causality: it examines the conditions (psychological, social, and cultural) that bring about claims to a certain kind of knowledge.
  2. Impartiality: it examines successful as well as unsuccessful knowledge claims.
  3. Symmetry: the same types of explanations are used for successful and unsuccessful knowledge claims alike.
  4. Reflexivity: it must be applicable to sociology itself.

History

Because the strong programme originated at the 'Science Studies Unit,' University of Edinburgh, it is sometimes termed the Edinburgh School. However, there is also a Bath School associated with Harry Collins that makes similar proposals. In contrast to the Edinburgh School, which emphasizes historical approaches, the Bath School emphasizes microsocial studies of laboratories and experiments.Harry M. Collins, "Introduction: Stages in the empirical programme of relativism." Social studies of science (1981): 3-10. [https://www.jstor.org/stable/284733 in JSTOR] The Bath school, however, does depart from the strong programme on some fundamental issues. In the social construction of technology (SCOT) approach developed by Collins' student Trevor Pinch, as well as by the Dutch sociologist Wiebe Bijker, the strong programme was extended to technology. There are SSK-influenced scholars working in science and technology studies programs throughout the world.Wiebe E. Bijker, et al. The social construction of technological systems: New directions in the sociology and history of technology (MIT press, 2012)

Criticism

In order to study scientific knowledge from a sociological point of view, the strong programme has adhered to a form of radical relativism. In other words, it argues that – in the social study of institutionalised beliefs about "truth" – it would be unwise to use "truth" as an explanatory resource. To do so would (according to the relativist view) include the answer as part of the question (Barnes 1992), and propound a "whiggish" approach towards the study of history – a narrative of human history as an inevitable march towards truth and enlightenment.

Physicists Alan Sokal and Jean Bricmont wrote a scathing critique Fashionable Nonsense of the Strong Programme in 1997 and its reliance on social constructionism.{{cite book |last=Galaty |first=David |date=2022 |title=Modern European Intellectual History: Individuals, Groupings and Technological Change 1800-2000 |publisher=Bloomsbury Academic |page=336 |isbn=978-1-350-10539-3}} In their view postmodernists on the far left attempted to recast scientific controversy as a political struggle between good (progressivism) and bad (conservatism), a form of Marxist class struggle, one that leads to a dead end that obscures, rather than enlightens.{{cite book|last1=Bricmont | first1=jean | last2=Sokal| first2=Alan| title=Fashionable Nonsense: Postmodern Intellectuals Abuse of Science| pages=107-200,206-207 | publisher=Picador | location=New York, NY| year=1998| isbn=0-312-19545-1}} They assert that the main error of the "Strong Program" is to ignore that scientists primarily use nature and mathematicians logic, not social pressures, to validate their findings.{{r|Bricmont And Sokal|pages=85-87,90}} They demonstrated that academics such as Feyerabend, Latour, Lacan, Irigaray, Kristeva (Ch3) and Deleuze regularly attempted to apply nonsensical metaphor from the physical sciences and mathematics to bolster their theories of how scientific agreements were achieved.{{r|Bricmont And Sokal|pages=78-85, 92-99, 27-37, 38-49 106-123, 154-168}}

Markus Seidel attacks the main arguments – underdetermination and norm-circularity – provided by Strong Programme proponents for their relativism.Markus Seidel Epistemic Relativism. A Constructive Critique, 2014, Palgrave Macmillan It has also been argued that the strong programme has incited climate denial.{{Cite journal |last=Hansson |first=Sven Ove |date=2020-08-29 |title=Social constructionism and climate science denial |journal=European Journal for Philosophy of Science |language=en |volume=10 |issue=3 |pages=37 |doi=10.1007/s13194-020-00305-w |issn=1879-4920|doi-access=free }}

Notes

See also

  • {{annotated link|Sociology of Scientific Knowledge}}
  • {{annotated link|Philosophy of science}}
  • {{annotated link|Science studies}}
  • {{annotated link|Social constructivism}}
  • {{annotated link|Sokal affair}}

Bibliography

  • Barnes, B. (1977). Interests and the Growth of Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • Barnes, B. (1982). T. S. Kuhn and Social Science. London: Macmillan.
  • Barnes, B. (1985). About Science. Oxford: Blackwell.
  • Barnes, B. (1987). 'Concept Application as Social Activity', Critica 19: 19–44.
  • Barnes, B. (1992). "Realism, relativism and finitism". Pp. 131–147 in Cognitive Relativism and Social Science, eds. D. Raven, L. van Vucht Tijssen, and J. de Wolf.
  • Barnes, B., D. Bloor, and J. Henry. (1996), Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. University of Chicago Press. [An introduction and summary of strong sociology]
  • Bijker, Wiebe E., et al. The social construction of technological systems: New directions in the sociology and history of technology (MIT press, 2012)
  • Bloor, D. (1991 [1976]), Knowledge and Social Imagery, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. [outlines the strong programme]
  • Bloor, D. (1997). Wittgenstein, Rules and Institutions. London: Routledge.
  • Bloor, D. (1999). "Anti-Latour," Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20#1 pp: 81–112.
  • Collins, Harry, and Trevor Pinch. The Golem at large: What you should know about technology (Cambridge University Press, 2014)
  • [https://web.archive.org/web/20061130125504/http://www.ensmp.fr/~latour/poparticles/poparticle/p075.html Latour, B. (1999). "For David Bloor and Beyond ... a reply to David Bloor's 'Anti-Latour',"] Studies in History & Philosophy of Science Part A 30(1): 113–129.