well-quasi-ordering
{{Short description|Mathematical concept for comparing objects}}
{{stack|{{Binary relations}}}}
In mathematics, specifically order theory, a well-quasi-ordering or wqo on a set is a quasi-ordering of for which every infinite sequence of elements from contains an increasing pair with
Motivation
Well-founded induction can be used on any set with a well-founded relation, thus one is interested in when a quasi-order is well-founded. (Here, by abuse of terminology, a quasiorder is said to be well-founded if the corresponding strict order is a well-founded relation.) However the class of well-founded quasiorders is not closed under certain operations—that is, when a quasi-order is used to obtain a new quasi-order on a set of structures derived from our original set, this quasiorder is found to be not well-founded. By placing stronger restrictions on the original well-founded quasiordering one can hope to ensure that our derived quasiorderings are still well-founded.
An example of this is the power set operation. Given a quasiordering for a set one can define a quasiorder on 's power set by setting if and only if for each element of one can find some element of that is larger than it with respect to . One can show that this quasiordering on needn't be well-founded, but if one takes the original quasi-ordering to be a well-quasi-ordering, then it is.
Formal definition
A well-quasi-ordering on a set is a quasi-ordering (i.e., a reflexive, transitive binary relation) such that any infinite sequence of elements from contains an increasing pair with . The set is said to be well-quasi-ordered, or shortly wqo.
A well partial order, or a wpo, is a wqo that is a proper ordering relation, i.e., it is antisymmetric.
Among other ways of defining wqo's, one is to say that they are quasi-orderings which do not contain infinite strictly decreasing sequences (of the form ){{ref|a}} nor infinite sequences of pairwise incomparable elements. Hence a quasi-order (X, ≤) is wqo if and only if (X, <) is well-founded and has no infinite antichains.
Ordinal type
Let be well partially ordered. A (necessarily finite) sequence of elements of that contains no pair with is usually called a bad sequence. The tree of bad sequences is the tree that contains a vertex for each bad sequence, and an edge joining each nonempty bad sequence to its parent . The root of corresponds to the empty sequence. Since contains no infinite bad sequence, the tree contains no infinite path starting at the root.{{cn|reason=This is far from being obvious, and requires a (reference to a) proof.|date=February 2024}} Therefore, each vertex of has an ordinal height , which is defined by transfinite induction as . The ordinal type of , denoted , is the ordinal height of the root of .
A linearization of is an extension of the partial order into a total order. It is easy to verify that is an upper bound on the ordinal type of every linearization of . De Jongh and Parikh{{cite journal |last1=de Jongh |first1=Dick H. G. |last2=Parikh |first2=Rohit |title=Well-partial orderings and hierarchies |journal=Indagationes Mathematicae (Proceedings) |date=1977 |volume=80 |issue=3 |pages=195-207 |doi=10.1016/1385-7258(77)90067-1|doi-access=free }} proved that in fact there always exists a linearization of that achieves the maximal ordinal type .
Examples
File:Infinite lattice of divisors.svg of the natural numbers ordered by divisibility]]
- , the set of natural numbers with standard ordering, is a well partial order (in fact, a well-order). However, , the set of positive and negative integers, is not a well-quasi-order, because it is not well-founded (see Pic.1).
- , the set of natural numbers ordered by divisibility, is not a well-quasi-order: the prime numbers are an infinite antichain (see Pic.2).
- , the set of vectors of natural numbers (where is finite) with component-wise ordering, is a well partial order (Dickson's lemma; see Pic.3). More generally, if is well-quasi-order, then is also a well-quasi-order for all .
- Let be an arbitrary finite set with at least two elements. The set of words over ordered lexicographically (as in a dictionary) is not a well-quasi-order because it contains the infinite decreasing sequence . Similarly, ordered by the prefix relation is not a well-quasi-order, because the previous sequence is an infinite antichain of this partial order. However, ordered by the subsequence relation is a well partial order.{{citation | last = Gasarch | first = W. | author1-link=William Gasarch | contribution = A survey of recursive combinatorics | doi = 10.1016/S0049-237X(98)80049-9 | location = Amsterdam | mr = 1673598 | pages = 1041–1176 | publisher = North-Holland | series = Stud. Logic Found. Math. | title = Handbook of Recursive Mathematics, Vol. 2 | volume = 139 | year = 1998}}. See in particular page 1160. (If has only one element, these three partial orders are identical.)
- More generally, , the set of finite -sequences ordered by embedding is a well-quasi-order if and only if is a well-quasi-order (Higman's lemma). Recall that one embeds a sequence into a sequence by finding a subsequence of that has the same length as and that dominates it term by term. When is an unordered set, if and only if is a subsequence of .
- , the set of infinite sequences over a well-quasi-order , ordered by embedding, is not a well-quasi-order in general. That is, Higman's lemma does not carry over to infinite sequences. Better-quasi-orderings have been introduced to generalize Higman's lemma to sequences of arbitrary lengths.
- Embedding between finite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo is a wqo (Kruskal's tree theorem).
- Embedding between infinite trees with nodes labeled by elements of a wqo is a wqo (Nash-Williams' theorem).
- Embedding between countable scattered linear order types is a well-quasi-order (Laver's theorem).
- Embedding between countable boolean algebras is a well-quasi-order. This follows from Laver's theorem and a theorem of Ketonen.
- Finite graphs ordered by a notion of embedding called "graph minor" is a well-quasi-order (Robertson–Seymour theorem).
- Graphs of finite tree-depth ordered by the induced subgraph relation form a well-quasi-order,{{citation | last1 = Nešetřil | first1 = Jaroslav | author1-link = Jaroslav Nešetřil | last2 = Ossona de Mendez | first2 = Patrice | author2-link = Patrice Ossona de Mendez | contribution = Lemma 6.13 | doi = 10.1007/978-3-642-27875-4 | isbn = 978-3-642-27874-7 | location = Heidelberg | mr = 2920058 | pages = 137 | publisher = Springer
| series = Algorithms and Combinatorics | title = Sparsity: Graphs, Structures, and Algorithms | volume = 28 | year = 2012 }}. as do the cographs ordered by induced subgraphs.{{citation | last = Damaschke | first = Peter | doi = 10.1002/jgt.3190140406 | issue = 4 | journal = Journal of Graph Theory | mr = 1067237 | pages = 427–435 | title = Induced subgraphs and well-quasi-ordering | volume = 14 | year = 1990}}.
Constructing new wpo's from given ones
Let and be two disjoint wpo sets. Let , and define a partial order on by letting if and only if for the same and . Then is wpo, and , where denotes natural sum of ordinals.
Given wpo sets and , define a partial order on the Cartesian product , by letting if and only if and . Then is wpo (this is a generalization of Dickson's lemma), and , where denotes natural product of ordinals.
Given a wpo set , let be the set of finite sequences of elements of , partially ordered by the subsequence relation. Meaning, let if and only if there exist indices
Given a wpo set
Wqo's versus well partial orders
In practice, the wqo's one manipulates are quite often not orderings (see examples above), and the theory is technically smoother{{fact|date=March 2017}} if we do not require antisymmetry, so it is built with wqo's as the basic notion. On the other hand, according to Milner 1985, no real gain in generality is obtained by considering quasi-orders rather than partial orders... it is simply more convenient to do so.
Observe that a wpo is a wqo, and that a wqo gives rise to a wpo between equivalence classes induced by the kernel of the wqo. For example, if we order
Infinite increasing subsequences
If
This can be proved by a Ramsey argument: given some sequence
The existence of such infinite increasing subsequences is sometimes taken as a definition for well-quasi-ordering, leading to an equivalent notion.
Properties of wqos
- Given a quasiordering
(X,\le) the quasiordering(P(X), \le^+) defined byA \le^+ B \iff \forall a \in A, \exists b \in B, a \le b is well-founded if and only if(X,\le) is a wqo. - A quasiordering is a wqo if and only if the corresponding partial order (obtained by quotienting by
x \sim y \iff x\le y \land y \le x ) has no infinite descending sequences or antichains. (This can be proved using a Ramsey argument as above.) - Given a well-quasi-ordering
(X,\le) , any sequence of upward-closed subsetsS_0 \subseteq S_1 \subseteq \cdots \subseteq X eventually stabilises (meaning there existsn \in \N such thatS_n = S_{n+1} = \cdots ; a subsetS \subseteq X is called upward-closed if\forall x,y \in X, x \le y \wedge x \in S \Rightarrow y \in S ): assuming the contrary\forall i \in \N, \exists j \in \N, j > i, \exists x \in S_j \setminus S_i , a contradiction is reached by extracting an infinite non-ascending subsequence. - Given a well-quasi-ordering
(X,\le) , any subsetS ofX has a finite number of minimal elements with respect to\le , for otherwise the minimal elements ofS would constitute an infinite antichain.
See also
- {{annotated link|Better-quasi-ordering}}
- {{annotated link|Prewellordering}}
- {{annotated link|Well-order}}
Notes
{{note|a}}Here x < y means:
References
{{Reflist|
refs=
}}
- {{cite journal | last = Dickson | first = L. E. | authorlink = Leonard Dickson | title=Finiteness of the odd perfect and primitive abundant numbers with r distinct prime factors | journal=American Journal of Mathematics | year = 1913 | volume = 35 | pages=413–422 | doi=10.2307/2370405 | jstor = 2370405 | issue = 4 }}
- {{cite journal | last = Higman | first = G. |authorlink = Graham Higman | title=Ordering by divisibility in abstract algebras | journal=Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society | year=1952 | volume=2 | pages=326–336 | doi=10.1112/plms/s3-2.1.326}}
- {{cite journal | authorlink = Joseph Kruskal | last=Kruskal |first= J. B. | title=The theory of well-quasi-ordering: A frequently discovered concept | journal=Journal of Combinatorial Theory | series = Series A | year=1972 | volume=13 | pages=297–305 | doi=10.1016/0097-3165(72)90063-5 | issue = 3| doi-access=free }}
- {{cite journal | last = Ketonen | first = Jussi | title = The structure of countable Boolean algebras | journal = Annals of Mathematics | volume = 108 | pages = 41–89 | year = 1978 | doi = 10.2307/1970929 | jstor = 1970929 | issue = 1}}
- {{cite book | last=Milner | first = E. C. | authorlink = Eric Charles Milner | year=1985 | chapter = Basic WQO- and BQO-theory | editor-first=I.|editor-last=Rival|editor-link=Ivan Rival | title = Graphs and Order. The Role of Graphs in the Theory of Ordered Sets and Its Applications | pages=487–502 | publisher=D. Reidel Publishing Co. | isbn=90-277-1943-8}}
- {{cite journal | last = Gallier | first = Jean H. |authorlink= Jean Gallier | title= What's so special about Kruskal's theorem and the ordinal Γo? A survey of some results in proof theory | journal = Annals of Pure and Applied Logic | year = 1991 | volume = 53 | pages= 199–260 | doi= 10.1016/0168-0072(91)90022-E | issue = 3| doi-access = }}
{{Order theory}}