Emergence#Living, biological systems

{{Short description|Unpredictable phenomenon in complex systems}}

{{Other uses}}

{{See also|Emergent (disambiguation)|Irreducibility (disambiguation)|Spontaneous order|Self-organization}}

File:SnowflakesWilsonBentley.jpg patterns in snowflakes exemplifies emergence in a physical system.]]

File:Termite Cathedral DSC03570.jpg offers a classic example of emergence in nature.]]

{{Complex systems}}

In philosophy, systems theory, science, and art, emergence occurs when a complex entity has properties or behaviors that its parts do not have on their own, and emerge only when they interact in a wider whole.

Emergence plays a central role in theories of integrative levels and of complex systems. For instance, the phenomenon of life as studied in biology is an emergent property of chemistry and physics.

In philosophy, theories that emphasize emergent properties have been called emergentism.

In philosophy

{{Main|Emergentism}}

Philosophers often understand emergence as a claim about the etiology of a system's properties. An emergent property of a system, in this context, is one that is not a property of any component of that system, but is still a feature of the system as a whole. Nicolai Hartmann (1882–1950), one of the first modern philosophers to write on emergence, termed this a categorial novum (new category).{{cite book |last=Hartmann |first=Nicolai |url=https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110246681 |title=Possibility and actuality |date=2013 |publisher=Walter De Gruyter |isbn=9783110246681 |page=223 |translator-last1=Adair |translator-first1=Stephanie |translator-last2=Scott |translator-first2=Alex |doi=10.1515/9783110246681 |quote=The higher nexus is, in many of its structural elements, dependent on the lower, but is autonomous in its particular nature (its categorial novum). The chain of conditions of a real thing in the higher stratum contains an ample number of components from the lower strata; but they are only partial aspects of it, and therefore do not make its real possibility complete; they make it, in fact, neither necessary nor actual. The chain becomes complete only through the addition of real components of its own stratum. But these are under a categorially different kind of determination. Structurally, they belong to the higher real nexus itself, and are not found outside of it.}}

=Definitions=

This concept of emergence dates from at least the time of Aristotle.Aristotle, Metaphysics (Aristotle), Book VIII (Eta) 1045a 8–10: "... the totality is not, as it were, a mere heap, but the whole is something besides the parts ...", i.e., the whole is other than the sum of the parts. Many scientists and philosophers

{{cite book

| last1 = Winning

| first1 = Jason

| last2 = Bechtel

| first2 = William

| author-link2 = William Bechtel

| chapter = Being emergence vs. pattern emergence: complexity, control, and goal-directedness in biological systems

| chapter-url = https://philpapers.org/rec/WINBEV

| editor1-last = Gibb

| editor1-first = Sophie

| editor2-last = Hendry

| editor2-first = Robin Findlay

| editor3-last = Lancaster

| editor3-first = Tom

| title = The Routledge Handbook of Emergence

| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=0Tz3DwAAQBAJ

| series = Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy

| location = Abingdon

| publisher = Routledge

| date = 2019

| page = 134

| isbn = 9781317381501

| access-date = 25 October 2020

| quote = Emergence is much discussed by both philosophers and scientists.

}}

have written on the concept, including John Stuart Mill (Composition of Causes, 1843)"The chemical combination of two substances produces, as is well known, a third substance with properties entirely different from those of either of the two substances separately, or of both of them taken together." and Julian HuxleyJulian Huxley: "now and again there is a sudden rapid passage to a totally new and more comprehensive type of order or organization, with quite new emergent properties, and involving quite new methods of further evolution" {{Harv|Huxley|Huxley|1947|p=120}} (1887–1975).

The philosopher G. H. Lewes coined the term "emergent" in 1875, distinguishing it from the merely "resultant":

Every resultant is either a sum or a difference of the co-operant forces; their sum, when their directions are the same – their difference, when their directions are contrary. Further, every resultant is clearly traceable in its components, because these are homogeneous and commensurable. It is otherwise with emergents, when, instead of adding measurable motion to measurable motion, or things of one kind to other individuals of their kind, there is a co-operation of things of unlike kinds. The emergent is unlike its components insofar as these are incommensurable, and it cannot be reduced to their sum or their difference.

{{cite book

| last1 = Lewes

| first1 = George Henry

| author-link1 = George Henry Lewes

| title = Problems of Life and Mind

| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=0J8RAAAAYAAJ

| series = First Series: The Foundations of a Creed

| volume = 2

| location = Boston

| publisher = Osgood

| date = 1875

| page = 369

| access-date = 24 Mar 2019

}}

{{sfn|Blitz|1992}}

=Strong and weak emergence=

{{further|Emergent materialism|Reductive materialism}}

Usage of the notion "emergence" may generally be subdivided into two perspectives, that of "weak emergence" and "strong emergence". One paper discussing this division is Weak Emergence, by philosopher Mark Bedau. In terms of physical systems, weak emergence is a type of emergence in which the emergent property is amenable to computer simulation or similar forms of after-the-fact analysis (for example, the formation of a traffic jam, the structure of a flock of starlings in flight or a school of fish, or the formation of galaxies). Crucial in these simulations is that the interacting members retain their independence. If not, a new entity is formed with new, emergent properties: this is called strong emergence, which it is argued cannot be simulated, analysed or reduced.{{sfn|Bedau|1997}}

David Chalmers writes that emergence often causes confusion in philosophy and science due to a failure to demarcate strong and weak emergence, which are "quite different concepts". Chalmers, David J. (2002). "Strong and Weak Emergence" [http://consc.net/papers/emergence.pdf] Republished in P. Clayton and P. Davies, eds. (2006) The Re-Emergence of Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press

Some common points between the two notions are that emergence concerns new properties produced as the system grows, which is to say ones which are not shared with its components or prior states. Also, it is assumed that the properties are supervenient rather than metaphysically primitive.{{sfn|Bedau|1997}}

Weak emergence describes new properties arising in systems as a result of the interactions at a fundamental level. However, Bedau stipulates that the properties can be determined only by observing or simulating the system, and not by any process of a reductionist analysis. As a consequence the emerging properties are scale dependent: they are only observable if the system is large enough to exhibit the phenomenon. Chaotic, unpredictable behaviour can be seen as an emergent phenomenon, while at a microscopic scale the behaviour of the constituent parts can be fully deterministic.{{cn|date=June 2024}}

Bedau notes that weak emergence is not a universal metaphysical solvent, as the hypothesis that consciousness is weakly emergent would not resolve the traditional philosophical questions about the physicality of consciousness. However, Bedau concludes that adopting this view would provide a precise notion that emergence is involved in consciousness, and second, the notion of weak emergence is metaphysically benign.{{sfn|Bedau|1997}}

Strong emergence describes the direct causal action of a high-level system on its components; qualities produced this way are irreducible to the system's constituent parts.{{sfn|Laughlin|2005}} The whole is other than the sum of its parts. It is argued then that no simulation of the system can exist, for such a simulation would itself constitute a reduction of the system to its constituent parts.{{sfn|Bedau|1997}} Physics lacks well-established examples of strong emergence, unless it is interpreted as the impossibility in practice to explain the whole in terms of the parts. Practical impossibility may be a more useful distinction than one in principle, since it is easier to determine and quantify, and does not imply the use of mysterious forces, but simply reflects the limits of our capability.{{cite book|last= Luisi|first= Pier L.|title= The Emergence of Life: From Chemical Origins to Synthetic Biology|year= 2006|publisher= Cambridge University Press|location= Cambridge, England|isbn= 978-0521821179|page= 119|url= http://www.cambridge.org/us/academic/subjects/chemistry/organic-chemistry/emergence-life-chemical-origins-synthetic-biology|url-status=live|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20151117023700/http://www.cambridge.org/us/academic/subjects/chemistry/organic-chemistry/emergence-life-chemical-origins-synthetic-biology|archive-date= 2015-11-17}}

==Viability of strong emergence==

One of the reasons for the importance of distinguishing these two concepts with respect to their difference concerns the relationship of purported emergent properties to science. Some thinkers question the plausibility of strong emergence as contravening our usual understanding of physics. Mark A. Bedau observes:

{{blockquote|Although strong emergence is logically possible, it is uncomfortably like magic. How does an irreducible but supervenient downward causal power arise, since by definition it cannot be due to the aggregation of the micro-level potentialities? Such causal powers would be quite unlike anything within our scientific ken. This not only indicates how they will discomfort reasonable forms of materialism. Their mysteriousness will only heighten the traditional worry that emergence entails illegitimately getting something from nothing.{{sfn|Bedau|1997}}}}

The concern that strong emergence does so entail is that such a consequence must be incompatible with metaphysical principles such as the principle of sufficient reason or the Latin dictum ex nihilo nihil fit, often translated as "nothing comes from nothing".{{cite web |author= |title=EX NIHILO NIHIL FIT Definition & Meaning |url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/ex%20nihilo%20nihil%20fit |website=merriam-webster.com |publisher=Encyclopaedia Britannica company |access-date= 27 April 2025}}

Strong emergence can be criticized for leading to causal overdetermination. The canonical example concerns emergent mental states (M and M∗) that supervene on physical states (P and P∗) respectively. Let M and M∗ be emergent properties. Let M∗ supervene on base property P∗. What happens when M causes M∗? Jaegwon Kim says:

{{blockquote|In our schematic example above, we concluded that M causes M∗ by causing P∗. So M causes P∗. Now, M, as an emergent, must itself have an emergence base property, say P. Now we face a critical question: if an emergent, M, emerges from basal condition P, why cannot P displace M as a cause of any putative effect of M? Why cannot P do all the work in explaining why any alleged effect of M occurred? If causation is understood as nomological (law-based) sufficiency, P, as M's emergence base, is nomologically sufficient for it, and M, as P∗'s cause, is nomologically sufficient for P∗. It follows that P is nomologically sufficient for P∗ and hence qualifies as its cause...If M is somehow retained as a cause, we are faced with the highly implausible consequence that every case of downward causation involves overdetermination (since P remains a cause of P∗ as well). Moreover, this goes against the spirit of emergentism in any case: emergents are supposed to make distinctive and novel causal contributions.{{cite journal | last1 = Kim | first1 = Jaegwon | year = 2006 | title = Emergence: Core ideas and issues | journal = Synthese | volume = 151 | issue = 3| pages = 547–59 | doi = 10.1007/s11229-006-9025-0 | s2cid = 875121 }}}}

If M is the cause of M∗, then M∗ is overdetermined because M∗ can also be thought of as being determined by P. One escape-route that a strong emergentist could take would be to deny downward causation. However, this would remove the proposed reason that emergent mental states must supervene on physical states, which in turn would call physicalism into question, and thus be unpalatable for some philosophers and physicists.

Carroll and Parola propose a taxonomy that classifies emergent phenomena by how the macro-description relates to the underlying micro-dynamics.{{cite journal |last1=Carroll |first1=Sean M. |last2=Parola |first2=Achyuth |year=2024 |title=What Emergence Can Possibly Mean |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/CARWEC-6 |pages=1–23|arxiv=2410.15468 }}

; Type‑0 (Featureless) Emergence:

: A coarse-graining map Φ from a micro state space A to a macro state space B that commutes with time evolution, without requiring any further decomposition into subsystems.

; Type‑1 (Local) Emergence:

: Emergence where the macro theory is defined in terms of localized collections of micro-subsystems. This category is subdivided into:

:: Type‑1a (Direct) Emergence: When the emergence map Φ is algorithmically simple (i.e. compressible), so that the macro behavior is easily deduced from the micro-states.

:: Type‑1b (Incompressible) Emergence: When Φ is algorithmically complex (i.e. incompressible), making the macro behavior appear more novel despite being determined by the micro-dynamics.

; Type‑2 (Nonlocal) Emergence:

: Cases in which both the micro and macro theories admit subsystem decompositions, yet the macro entities are defined nonlocally with respect to the micro-structure, meaning that macro behavior depends on widely distributed micro information.

; Type‑3 (Augmented) Emergence:

: A form of strong emergence in which the macro theory introduces additional ontological variables that do not supervene on the micro-states, thereby positing genuinely novel macro-level entities.

=Objective or subjective quality=

Crutchfield regards the properties of complexity and organization of any system as subjective qualities determined by the observer.

Defining structure and detecting the emergence of complexity in nature are inherently subjective, though essential, scientific activities. Despite the difficulties, these problems can be analysed in terms of how model-building observers infer from measurements the computational capabilities embedded in non-linear processes. An observer's notion of what is ordered, what is random, and what is complex in its environment depends directly on its computational resources: the amount of raw measurement data, of memory, and of time available for estimation and inference. The discovery of structure in an environment depends more critically and subtly, though, on how those resources are organized. The descriptive power of the observer's chosen (or implicit) computational model class, for example, can be an overwhelming determinant in finding regularity in data.

{{cite journal

| last1 = Crutchfield

| first1 = James P.

| author-link1 = James P. Crutchfield

| year = 1993

| title = The Calculi of Emergence: Computation, Dynamics, and Induction

| url = http://csc.ucdavis.edu/~cmg/compmech/pubs/CalcEmergTitlePage.htm

| journal = Physica

| location = Utrecht

| publication-date = 1994

| volume = 75

| issue = 1–3

| pages = 11–54

| access-date = 24 Mar 2019

| bibcode = 1994PhyD...75...11C

| doi = 10.1016/0167-2789(94)90273-9

}}

The low entropy of an ordered system can be viewed as an example of subjective emergence: the observer sees an ordered system by ignoring the underlying microstructure (i.e. movement of molecules or elementary particles) and concludes that the system has a low entropy.

See f.i. Carlo Rovelli: The mystery of time, 2017, part 10: Perspective, p.105-110

On the other hand, chaotic, unpredictable behaviour can also be seen as subjective emergent, while at a microscopic scale the movement of the constituent parts can be fully deterministic.

In science

In physics, emergence is used to describe a property, law, or phenomenon which occurs at macroscopic scales (in space or time) but not at microscopic scales, despite the fact that a macroscopic system can be viewed as a very large ensemble of microscopic systems.{{Cite book|last=Anderson|first=Philip W.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9HhQDwAAQBAJ|title=Basic Notions Of Condensed Matter Physics|date=2018-03-09|publisher=CRC Press|isbn=978-0-429-97374-1|language=en}}{{Cite book|last1=Girvin|first1=Steven M.|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2ESIDwAAQBAJ|title=Modern Condensed Matter Physics|last2=Yang|first2=Kun|date=2019-02-28|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-108-57347-4|language=en}}

An emergent behavior of a physical system is a qualitative property that can only occur in the limit that the number of microscopic constituents tends to infinity.{{cite journal |last1=Kivelson |first1=Sophia |last2=Kivelson |first2=Steve |title=Defining Emergence in Physics |journal=npj Quantum Materials |volume=1 |publisher=Nature Research |doi=10.1038/npjquantmats.2016.24 |year=2016 |issue=1 |page=16024 |doi-access=free |bibcode=2016npjQM...116024K }}

According to Robert Laughlin,{{sfn|Laughlin|2005}} for many-particle systems, nothing can be calculated exactly from the microscopic equations, and macroscopic systems are characterised by broken symmetry: the symmetry present in the microscopic equations is not present in the macroscopic system, due to phase transitions. As a result, these macroscopic systems are described in their own terminology, and have properties that do not depend on many microscopic details.

Novelist Arthur Koestler used the metaphor of Janus (a symbol of the unity underlying complements like open/shut, peace/war) to illustrate how the two perspectives (strong vs. weak or holistic vs. reductionistic) should be treated as non-exclusive, and should work together to address the issues of emergence.{{sfn|Koestler|1969}} Theoretical physicist Philip W. Anderson states it this way:

{{blockquote|The ability to reduce everything to simple fundamental laws does not imply the ability to start from those laws and reconstruct the universe. The constructionist hypothesis breaks down when confronted with the twin difficulties of scale and complexity. At each level of complexity entirely new properties appear. Psychology is not applied biology, nor is biology applied chemistry. We can now see that the whole becomes not merely more, but very different from the sum of its parts.{{sfn|Anderson|1972}}}}

Meanwhile, others have worked towards developing analytical evidence of strong emergence. Renormalization methods in theoretical physics enable physicists to study critical phenomena that are not tractable as the combination of their parts.{{Cite journal|last1= Longo|first1= Giuseppe|last2= Montévil|first2= Maël|last3= Pocheville|first3= Arnaud|date= 2012-01-01|title= From bottom-up approaches to levels of organization and extended critical transitions|journal= Frontiers in Physiology|volume= 3|page= 232|doi= 10.3389/fphys.2012.00232|pmc= 3429021|pmid= 22934001|doi-access= free}} In 2009, Gu et al. presented a class of infinite physical systems that exhibits non-computable macroscopic properties.{{cite journal | last1 = Gu | first1 = Mile | display-authors = etal | year = 2009 | title = More really is different | journal = Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena | volume = 238 | issue = 9| pages = 835–39 | doi=10.1016/j.physd.2008.12.016| arxiv = 0809.0151 | bibcode = 2009PhyD..238..835G | s2cid = 61197980 }}{{cite journal | last1 = Binder | first1 = P-M | year = 2009 | title = Computation: The edge of reductionism | journal = Nature | volume = 459 | issue = 7245| pages = 332–34 | doi=10.1038/459332a| pmid = 19458701 | bibcode = 2009Natur.459..332B| s2cid = 205046586 }} More precisely, if one could compute certain macroscopic properties of these systems from the microscopic description of these systems, then one would be able to solve computational problems known to be undecidable in computer science. These results concern infinite systems, finite systems being considered computable. However, macroscopic concepts which only apply in the limit of infinite systems, such as phase transitions and the renormalization group, are important for understanding and modeling real, finite physical systems. Gu et al. concluded that

{{blockquote|Although macroscopic concepts are essential for understanding our world, much of fundamental physics has been devoted to the search for a 'theory of everything', a set of equations that perfectly describe the behavior of all fundamental particles. The view that this is the goal of science rests in part on the rationale that such a theory would allow us to derive the behavior of all macroscopic concepts, at least in principle. The evidence we have presented suggests that this view may be overly optimistic. A 'theory of everything' is one of many components necessary for complete understanding of the universe, but is not necessarily the only one. The development of macroscopic laws from first principles may involve more than just systematic logic, and could require conjectures suggested by experiments, simulations or insight.}}

In humanity

{{see also|Spontaneous order|Self-organization}}

Human beings are the basic elements of social systems, which perpetually interact and create, maintain, or untangle mutual social bonds. Social bonds in social systems are perpetually changing in the sense of the ongoing reconfiguration of their structure.{{Cite book|title=Social systems|last=Luhmann, N.|publisher=Stanford University Press|year=1995|location=Stanford}} An early argument (1904–05) for the emergence of social formations can be found in Max Weber's most famous work, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism.{{cite journal | last1 = McKinnon | first1 = AM | year = 2010 | title = Elective affinities of the Protestant ethic: Weber and the chemistry of capitalism | url = http://aura.abdn.ac.uk/bitstream/2164/3035/1/McKinnon_Elective_Affinities_final_non_format.pdf | journal = Sociological Theory | volume = 28 | issue = 1| pages = 108–26 | doi = 10.1111/j.1467-9558.2009.01367.x | hdl = 2164/3035 | s2cid = 144579790 | hdl-access = free }} Recently, the emergence of a new social system is linked with the emergence of order from nonlinear relationships among multiple interacting units, where multiple interacting units are individual thoughts, consciousness, and actions.{{Cite book|title=Complexification: Explaining a paradoxical world through the science of surprise|last=Casti, J. L.|publisher=Harper Collins|year=1994|location=New York}} In the case of the global economic system, under capitalism, growth, accumulation and innovation can be considered emergent processes where not only does technological processes sustain growth, but growth becomes the source of further innovations in a recursive, self-expanding spiral. In this sense, the exponential trend of the growth curve reveals the presence of a long-term positive feedback among growth, accumulation, and innovation; and the emergence of new structures and institutions connected to the multi-scale process of growth. {{cite journal |last1=Bonauiti |first1=Mauro |title=Degrowth: Tools for a Complex Analysis of the Multidimensional Crisis |journal=Capitalism Nature Socialism |date=2012 |volume=23 |issue=1 |pages=30–50 |doi=10.1080/10455752.2011.648838 |url=http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/10455752.2011.648838 |access-date=2024-04-10}} This is reflected in the work of Karl Polanyi, who traces the process by which labor and nature are converted into commodities in the passage from an economic system based on agriculture to one based on industry.{{cite book |last1=Polanyi |first1=Karl |title=The Great Transformation |date=1944}} This shift, along with the idea of the self-regulating market, set the stage not only for another economy but also for another society. The principle of emergence is also brought forth when thinking about alternatives to the current economic system based on growth facing social and ecological limits. Both degrowth and social ecological economics have argued in favor of a co-evolutionary perspective for theorizing about transformations that overcome the dependence of human wellbeing on economic growth.{{cite journal |last1=Spash |first1=Clive L |title=A tale of three paradigms_ Realising the revolutionary potential of ecological economics |journal=Ecological Economics |date=2020 |volume=169|doi=10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.106518 |bibcode=2020EcoEc.16906518S }}{{cite book |last1=Kallis |first1=Giorgos |title=Another Economy is Possible: Culture and Economy in a Time of Crisis |date=2017 |publisher=Wiley |pages=34–54}}

Economic trends and patterns which emerge are studied intensively by economists.{{Cite journal |last=Arthur |first=W. Brian |title=Complexity and the economy |journal=Science |year=2015 |volume=284 |issue=5411 |pages=107–9 |location=Oxford |doi=10.1126/science.284.5411.107 |pmid=10103172 |oclc=876140942}} Within the field of group facilitation and organization development, there have been a number of new group processes that are designed to maximize emergence and self-organization, by offering a minimal set of effective initial conditions. Examples of these processes include SEED-SCALE, appreciative inquiry, Future Search, the world cafe or knowledge cafe, Open Space Technology, and others (Holman, 2010{{Cite journal|last=Holman|first=Peggy|date=December 2010 – January 2011|title=Engaging Emergence: Turning Upheaval into Opportunity|url=http://peggyholman.com/wp-content/uploads/2010/06/211001pkSystems-Thinkerarticle.pdf|journal=Pegasus Communication: The Systems Thinker|volume=21|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130418075443/http://peggyholman.com/wp-content/uploads/2010/06/211001pkSystems-Thinkerarticle.pdf|archive-date=2013-04-18}}). In international development, concepts of emergence have been used within a theory of social change termed SEED-SCALE to show how standard principles interact to bring forward socio-economic development fitted to cultural values, community economics, and natural environment (local solutions emerging from the larger socio-econo-biosphere). These principles can be implemented utilizing a sequence of standardized tasks that self-assemble in individually specific ways utilizing recursive evaluative criteria.Daniel C. Taylor, Carl E. Taylor, Jesse O. Taylor, Empowerment on an Unstable Planet: From Seeds of Human Energy to a Scale of Global Change (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012)

Looking at emergence in the context of social and systems change, invites us to reframe our thinking on parts and wholes and their interrelation. Unlike machines, living systems at all levels of recursion - be it a sentient body, a tree, a family, an organisation, the education system, the economy, the health system, the political system etc - are continuously creating themselves. They are continually growing and changing along with their surrounding elements, and therefore are more than the sum of their parts. As Peter Senge and co-authors put forward in the book Presence: Exploring profound change in People, Organizations and Society, "as long as our thinking is governed by habit - notably industrial, "machine age" concepts such as control, predictability, standardization, and "faster is better" - we will continue to recreate institutions as they have been, despite their disharmony with the larger world, and the need for all living systems to evolve."{{Cite book |title=Presence: exploring profound change in people, organizations, and society |date=2012 |publisher=Brealey |isbn=978-1-85788-355-8 |editor-last=Senge |editor-first=Peter M. |edition=Repr |location=London}} While change is predictably constant, it is unpredictable in direction and often occurs at second and nth orders of systemic relationality.{{Cite journal |last=Bateson |first=Nora |date=September 2022 |title=An essay on ready-ing: Tending the prelude to change |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/sres.2896 |journal=Systems Research and Behavioral Science |language=en |volume=39 |issue=5 |pages=990–1004 |doi=10.1002/sres.2896 |issn=1092-7026}} Understanding emergence and what creates the conditions for different forms of emergence to occur, either insidious or nourishing vitality, is essential in the search for deep transformations.

The works of Nora Bateson and her colleagues at the International Bateson Institute delve into this. Since 2012, they have been researching questions such as what makes a living system ready to change? Can unforeseen ready-ness for change be nourished? Here being ready is not thought of as being prepared, but rather as nourishing the flexibility we do not yet know will be needed. These inquiries challenge the common view that a theory of change is produced from an identified preferred goal or outcome. As explained in their paper An essay on ready-ing: Tending the prelude to change: "While linear managing or controlling of the direction of change may appear desirable, tending to how the system becomes ready allows for pathways of possibility previously unimagined." This brings a new lens to the field of emergence in social and systems change as it looks to tending the pre-emergent process. Warm Data Labs are the fruit of their praxis, they are spaces for transcontextual mutual learning in which aphanipoetic phenomena unfold.{{Cite journal |last=Bateson |first=Nora |date=2021 |title=Aphanipoiesis |url=https://journals.isss.org/index.php/jisss/article/view/3887 |journal=Journal of the International Society for the Systems Sciences |language=en |volume=65 |issue=1 |issn=1999-6918}} Having hosted hundreds of Warm Data processes with 1000s of participants, they have found that these spaces of shared poly-learning across contexts lead to a realm of potential change, a necessarily obscured zone of wild interaction of unseen, unsaid, unknown flexibility. It is such flexibility that nourishes the ready-ing living systems require to respond to complex situations in new ways and change. In other words, this readying process preludes what will emerge. When exploring questions of social change, it is important to ask ourselves, what is submerging in the current social imaginary and perhaps, rather than focus all our resources and energy on driving direct order responses, to nourish flexibility with ourselves, and the systems we are a part of.

Another approach that engages with the concept of emergence for social change is Theory U, where "deep emergence" is the result of self-transcending knowledge after a successful journey along the U through layers of awareness.{{Cite book |last=Scharmer |first=Claus Otto |title=Theory U: leading from the future as it emerges: the social technology of presencing |date=2016 |publisher=Berrett-Koehler Publishers, Inc., a BK Business Book |isbn=978-1-62656-798-6 |edition=Second |location=San Francisco, California}} This practice nourishes transformation at the inner-being level, which enables new ways of being, seeing and relating to emerge. The concept of emergence has also been employed in the field of facilitation. In Emergent Strategy, adrienne maree brown defines emergent strategies as "ways for humans to practice complexity and grow the future through relatively simple interactions".{{Cite book |last=Brown |first=Adrienne M. |title=Emergent Strategy |date=2017|page=20|publisher=AK Press |isbn=978-1-84935-260-4 |location=Chico, CA}}

In linguistics, the concept of emergence has been applied in the domain of stylometry to explain the interrelation between the syntactical structures of the text and the author style (Slautina, Marusenko, 2014).{{cite journal | last1 = Slautina | first1 = Maria | last2 = Marusenko | first2 = Mikhail | year = 2014 | title = L'émergence du style. Les méthodes stylométriques pour la recherche de paternité des textes médiévaux | url = https://www.academia.edu/9466688 | journal = Les Cahiers du Numérique | volume = 10 | issue = 4| pages = 179–215 | doi = 10.3166/lcn.10.4.179-215 }} It has also been argued that the structure and regularity of language grammar, or at least language change, is an emergent phenomenon.{{cite book |last1=Hopper |first1=Paul J. |title=The new psychology of language: Cognitive and functional approaches to language structure |date=1998 |pages=155–175 |chapter=Emergent grammar}} While each speaker merely tries to reach their own communicative goals, they use language in a particular way. If enough speakers behave in that way, language is changed.{{sfn|Keller|1994}} In a wider sense, the norms of a language, i.e. the linguistic conventions of its speech society, can be seen as a system emerging from long-time participation in communicative problem-solving in various social circumstances.{{cite journal |last1=Määttä |first1=Urho |title=Kielitieteen emergenttinen metateoria |journal=Virittäjä |date=4 January 2000 |volume=104 |issue=4 |pages=498 |url=https://journal.fi/virittaja/article/view/40040 |access-date=24 March 2022 |language=fi |issn=2242-8828}}

In technology

The bulk conductive response of binary (RC) electrical networks with random arrangements, known as the Universal dielectric response (UDR), can be seen as emergent properties of such physical systems. Such arrangements can be used as simple physical prototypes for deriving mathematical formulae for the emergent responses of complex systems.{{cite journal| doi=10.1016/j.physa.2012.10.035 | volume=392 | issue=4 | title=The origin of power-law emergent scaling in large binary networks | year=2013 | journal=Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and Its Applications | pages=1004–1027 | last1 = Almond | first1 = D.P. | last2 = Budd | first2 = C.J. | last3 = Freitag | first3 = M.A. | last4 = Hunt | first4 = G.W. | last5 = McCullen | first5 = N.J. | last6 = Smith | first6 = N.D.| arxiv=1204.5601 | bibcode=2013PhyA..392.1004A | s2cid=15801210 }} Internet traffic can also exhibit some seemingly emergent properties. In the congestion control mechanism, TCP flows can become globally synchronized at bottlenecks, simultaneously increasing and then decreasing throughput in coordination. Congestion, widely regarded as a nuisance, is possibly an emergent property of the spreading of bottlenecks across a network in high traffic flows which can be considered as a phase transition.See review of related research in {{Harv|Smith|2008|pp=1–31}} Some artificially intelligent (AI) computer applications simulate emergent behavior.{{Cite journal|doi=10.1098/rstb.2018.0029|title=Social behaviour as an emergent property of embodied curiosity: A robotics perspective|year=2019|last1=Gordon|first1=Goren|journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences|volume=374|issue=1771|pmid=30853006|pmc=6452242}} One example is Boids, which mimics the swarming behavior of birds.{{Cite journal|doi=10.1098/rsta.2016.0351|title=Life as an emergent phenomenon: Studies from a large-scale boid simulation and web data|year=2017|last1=Ikegami|first1=Takashi|last2=Mototake|first2=Yoh-Ichi|last3=Kobori|first3=Shintaro|last4=Oka|first4=Mizuki|last5=Hashimoto|first5=Yasuhiro|journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences|volume=375|issue=2109|pmid=29133449|pmc=5686407|bibcode=2017RSPTA.37560351I}}

In religion and art

In religion, emergence grounds expressions of religious naturalism and syntheism in which a sense of the sacred is perceived in the workings of entirely naturalistic processes by which more complex forms arise or evolve from simpler forms. Examples are detailed in The Sacred Emergence of Nature by Ursula Goodenough & Terrence Deacon and Beyond Reductionism: Reinventing the Sacred by Stuart Kauffman, both from 2006, as well as Syntheism – Creating God in The Internet Age by Alexander Bard & Jan Söderqvist from 2014 and Emergentism: A Religion of Complexity for the Metamodern World by Brendan Graham Dempsey (2022).{{cn|date=June 2024}}

Michael J. Pearce has used emergence to describe the experience of works of art in relation to contemporary neuroscience.{{cite book|last=Pearce|first=Michael J.|title=Art in the Age of Emergence|year=2015|publisher=Cambridge Scholars Publishing|location=Manchester, England|isbn=978-1443870573|url=http://www.cambridgescholars.com/art-in-the-age-of-emergence|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150522021953/http://www.cambridgescholars.com/art-in-the-age-of-emergence|archive-date=2015-05-22}} Practicing artist Leonel Moura, in turn, attributes to his "artbots" a real, if nonetheless rudimentary, creativity based on emergent principles.{{cite journal |author=Leonel Moura|date=16 July 2018|title=Robot Art: An Interview with Leonel Moura|journal=Arts|volume=7|issue=3|page=28|doi=10.3390/arts7030028|doi-access=free}}

See also

{{cols|colwidth=21em}}

  • {{annotated link|Abiogenesis}}
  • {{annotated link|Anthropic principle}}
  • {{annotated link|Connectionism}}
  • {{annotated link|Dual-phase evolution}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergenesis}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergent algorithm}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergent evolution}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergent gameplay}}
  • {{annotated link|Entropic gravity|Emergent gravity}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergent organization|only=explicit}}
  • {{annotated link|Emergentism}}
  • {{annotated link|Externality}}
  • {{annotated link|Free will}}
  • {{annotated link|Generative science}}
  • {{annotated link|Irreducible complexity}}
  • {{annotated link|Langton's ant}}
  • {{annotated link|Law of Complexity-Consciousness}}
  • {{annotated link|Libertarianism (metaphysics)}}
  • {{annotated link|Mass action (sociology)}}
  • {{annotated link|G. E. Moore#Organic wholes|Organic Wholes of G.E. Moore}}
  • {{annotated link|Polytely}}
  • {{annotated link|Society of Mind}}
  • {{annotated link|Superorganism}}
  • {{annotated link|Swarm intelligence}}
  • {{annotated link|System of systems}}
  • {{annotated link|Spontaneous order}}

{{colend}}

References

{{Reflist|30em|refs=

{{cite encyclopedia |author1=O'Connor, Timothy |author2=Wong, Hong Yu |title=Emergent Properties|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition) |editor1=Edward N. Zalta |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/properties-emergent/ |date=February 28, 2012}}

}}

=Bibliography=

{{div col|colwidth=30em}}

{{refbegin}}

  • {{cite journal |last1 = Albert | first1 = Réka | last2 = Jeong | first2 = Hawoong | last3 = Barabási | first3 = Albert-László | title = Diameter of the World-Wide Web | journal = Nature |date = 9 September 1999 | volume = 401 | issue = 6749 | pages = 130–131 | doi = 10.1038/43601| arxiv = cond-mat/9907038 | bibcode = 1999Natur.401..130A | s2cid = 4419938 }}
  • {{Citation | surname = Anderson | given = P.W. | title = More is Different: Broken Symmetry and the Nature of the Hierarchical Structure of Science | journal = Science | volume = 177 | year = 1972 | pages = 393–96 | doi = 10.1126/science.177.4047.393 | pmid=17796623 | issue=4047|bibcode = 1972Sci...177..393A | s2cid = 34548824 }}
  • {{cite journal | last = Bedau | first = Mark A. | year = 1997 | title = Weak Emergence | journal = Philosophical Perspectives | volume = 11 | pages = 375–399 | doi = 10.1111/0029-4624.31.s11.17 |url = http://people.reed.edu/~mab/papers/weak.emergence.pdf}}
  • {{Citation |surname=Bejan |given=Adrian |year=2016 |title=The Physics of Life: The Evolution of Everything |publisher=St. Martin's Press |isbn=978-1250078827}}
  • Bejan, Adrian; Zane, J. P. (2012). Design in Nature: How the Constructal Law Governs Evolution in Biology, Physics, Technology, and Social Organizations. Doubleday. {{ISBN|978-0-385-53461-1}}
  • {{cite book|last=Blitz|first=David|date=1992|title=Emergent Evolution: Qualitative Novelty and the Levels of Reality|location=Dordrecht|publisher=Kluwer Academic}}
  • {{Citation | surname = Corning | given = Peter A. | title = The Synergism Hypothesis: A Theory of Progressive Evolution | year = 1983 | publisher = McGraw-Hill | place = New York}}
  • {{Cite book|last=Corning|first=Peter A.|date=2005|title=Holistic Darwinism: Synergy, Cybernetics and the Bioeconomics of Evolution|location=Chicago|publisher=University of Chicago Press}}
  • {{cite book|last1=Huxley|first1=J. S.|last2=Huxley|first2=T. H.|date=1947|title=Evolution and Ethics: 1983–1934|location=London|publisher=The Pilot Press}}
  • {{Citation | surname = Koestler | given = Arthur | author-link = Arthur Koestler |editor1=A. Koestler |editor2=J. R. Smythies | title = Beyond Reductionism: New Perspectives in the Life Sciences | year = 1969 | publisher = Hutchinson | place = London}}
  • {{Citation | surname = Laughlin | given = Robert | author-link = Robert B. Laughlin | title = A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down | year = 2005 | publisher = Basic Books | isbn = 978-0-465-03828-2| title-link = A Different Universe: Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down }}

{{div col end}}

  • {{cite book|last=Steels|first=L|chapter=Towards a Theory of Emergent Functionality|editor-last1=Meyer|editor-first1=J.-A.|editor-last2=Wiloson|editor-first2=S. W.|title=From Animals to Animats: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior|pages=451–461|location=Cambridge|publisher=MIT Press|date=1991}}

{{refend}}

Further reading

{{div col|colwidth=30em}}

{{refbegin}}

  • Alexander, V. N. (2011). The Biologist's Mistress: Rethinking Self-Organization in Art, Literature and Nature. Litchfield Park AZ: Emergent Publications.
  • {{Citation | last = Bateson | first=Gregory | author-link = Gregory Bateson | title = Steps to an Ecology of Mind | year = 1972 | publisher = Ballantine Books | isbn = 978-0-226-03905-3}}
  • {{Citation | last = Batty | first=Michael | author-link = Michael Batty | title = Cities and Complexity | year = 2005 | publisher = MIT Press | isbn = 978-0-262-52479-7}}
  • {{Citation | last = Bunge | first=Mario Augusto | author-link = Mario Bunge | title = Emergence and Convergence: Qualitiative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge | publisher = Toronto: University of Toronto Press| year = 2003}}
  • Chalmers, David J. (2002). "Strong and Weak Emergence" [http://consc.net/papers/emergence.pdf ] Republished in P. Clayton and P. Davies, eds. (2006) The Re-Emergence of Emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Philip Clayton & Paul Davies (eds.) (2006). The Re-Emergence of Emergence: The Emergentist Hypothesis from Science to Religion Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Felipe Cucker and Stephen Smale (2007), The Japanese Journal of Mathematics, [http://ttic.uchicago.edu/~smale/papers/math-of-emergence.pdf The Mathematics of Emergence]
  • {{Citation | last = Delsemme | first=Armand | title = Our Cosmic Origins: From the Big Bang to the Emergence of Life and Intelligence | year = 1998 | publisher = Cambridge University Press}}
  • {{Citation | last = Goodwin | first=Brian | title = How the Leopard Changed Its Spots: The Evolution of Complexity | year = 2001 | publisher = Princeton University Press}}
  • Hoffmann, Peter M. "Life's Ratchet: How Molecular Machines Extract Order from Chaos" (2012), Basic Books.
  • {{Citation | last = Hofstadter | first=Douglas R. | author-link = Douglas Hofstadter | title = Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid | year = 1979 | publisher = Harvester Press| title-link=Gödel, Escher, Bach }}
  • {{Citation | last = Holland | first=John H. | author-link = John Henry Holland | title = Emergence from Chaos to Order | year = 1998 | publisher = Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-7382-0142-9}}
  • {{Citation | last = Kauffman | author-link = Stuart Kauffman | first=Stuart | title = The Origins of Order: Self-Organization and Selection in Evolution | year = 1993 | publisher = Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-19-507951-7}}
  • {{Citation | last = Keller | author-link = Rudi Keller | first=Rudi | title = On Language Change: The Invisible Hand in Language | place = London/New York | publisher = Routledge | year = 1994 | isbn = 978-0-415-07671-5}}
  • {{Citation | last = Kauffman | author-link = Stuart Kauffman | first=Stuart | title = At Home in the Universe | place = New York | publisher = Oxford University Press | year = 1995}}
  • {{Citation | last = Kelly | first = Kevin | author-link = Kevin Kelly (editor) | title = Out of Control: The New Biology of Machines, Social Systems, and the Economic World | year = 1994 | publisher = Perseus Books | isbn = 978-0-201-48340-6 | url = https://archive.org/details/outofcontrolnewb00kell }}
  • {{Citation | last = Krugman | first=Paul | author-link = Paul Krugman | title = The Self-organizing Economy | year = 1996 | publisher = Blackwell | place = Oxford | isbn = 978-1-55786-698-1 | quote = {{ISBN|0-87609-177-X}}}}
  • {{Citation | last = Lewin | first=Roger | title = Complexity - Life at the Edge of Chaos| year = 2000 | edition = second | publisher = University of Chicago Press | isbn = 978-0-226-47654-4 | quote = {{ISBN|0-226-47655-3}}}}
  • Ignazio Licata & Ammar Sakaji (eds) (2008). [https://web.archive.org/web/20110824142338/http://www.worldscibooks.com/physics/6692.html Physics of Emergence and Organization], {{ISBN|978-981-277-994-6}}, World Scientific and Imperial College Press.
  • {{Citation | last = Marshall | first=Stephen | title = Cities Design and Evolution | year = 2009 | publisher = Routledge | isbn = 978-0-415-42329-8 | quote = {{ISBN|0-415-42329-5}} }}
  • {{Citation | last = Morowitz | first=Harold J. | title = The Emergence of Everything: How the World Became Complex | year = 2002 | publisher = Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-19-513513-8}}
  • {{Citation | last = Pearce | first=Michael J. | title = Art in the Age of Emergence. | year = 2015 | publisher = Cambridge Scholars Publishing | isbn = 978-1-443-87057-3 | quote = {{ISBN|1-443-87057-9}}}}
  • {{Citation | last = Schelling | first = Thomas C. | author-link = Thomas Schelling | title = Micromotives and Macrobehaviour | year = 1978 | publisher = W. W. Norton | isbn = 978-0-393-05701-0 | url = https://archive.org/details/micromotivesmacr00sche }}
  • {{Citation | last1 = Smith | first1=John Maynard | author-link = John Maynard Smith | last2 = Szathmáry | given2 = Eörs | title = The Major Transitions in Evolution | year = 1997 | publisher = Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-19-850294-4}}
  • {{Citation | last = Smith | first = Reginald D. | title = The Dynamics of Internet Traffic: Self-Similarity, Self-Organization, and Complex Phenomena | year = 2008 | arxiv = 0807.3374|bibcode = 2008arXiv0807.3374S | doi=10.1142/S0219525911003451 | volume=14 | issue = 6 | journal=Advances in Complex Systems | pages=905–949| s2cid = 18937228 }}
  • Solé, Ricard and Goodwin, Brian (2000) Signs of life: how complexity pervades biology, Basic Books, New York
  • Jakub Tkac & [https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Jiri_Kroc Jiri Kroc] (2017), Cellular Automaton Simulation of Dynamic Recrystallization: Introduction into Self-Organization and Emergence (Software) [https://www.researchgate.net/publication/316989956_Cellular_Automaton_Simulation_of_Dynamic_Recrystallization_Introduction_into_Self-Organization_and_Emergence?ev=prf_high (PDF) Cellular Automaton Simulation of Dynamic Recrystallization: Introduction into Self-Organization and Emergence] [https://www.researchgate.net/publication/317013011_Self-Organization_Video_Sequence_Depicting_Numerical_Experiments_with_Cellular_Automaton_Model_of_Dynamic_Recrystallization_with_source-code_link "Video - Simulation of DRX"]
  • {{Citation | last = Wan | first=Poe Yu-ze | title =Emergence à la Systems Theory: Epistemological Totalausschluss or Ontological Novelty? | journal=Philosophy of the Social Sciences | volume=41 | issue=2 | pages = 178–210 | year = 2011 | doi=10.1177/0048393109350751| s2cid=144965056 }}
  • {{Citation | last = Wan | first = Poe Yu-ze | title = Reframing the Social: Emergentist Systemism and Social Theory | publisher = Ashgate Publishing | year = 2011 | url = http://www.ashgate.com/isbn/9781409411529 | access-date = 2012-02-13 | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20130311101716/http://www.ashgate.com/isbn/9781409411529 | archive-date = 2013-03-11 | url-status = dead }}
  • {{Citation | last = Weinstock | first=Michael | author-link = Michael Weinstock | title = The Architecture of Emergence - the evolution of form in Nature and Civilisation | year = 2010 |publisher = John Wiley and Sons |isbn = 978-0-470-06633-1}}[https://web.archive.org/web/20110912083233/http://www.architectureofemergence.com/ architectureofemergence.com]
  • {{Citation | last = Wolfram | first=Stephen | author-link = Stephen Wolfram | title = A New Kind of Science | year = 2002 | isbn = 978-1-57955-008-0| title-link=A New Kind of Science | publisher=Wolfram Media }}
  • {{Citation | last = Young | first=Louise B. | title = The Unfinished Universe | year = 2002 | publisher=Oxford University Press | isbn = 978-0-19-508039-1}}

{{div col end}}

{{refend}}