Epistemology#Acquiring knowledge

{{Short description|Philosophical study of knowledge}}

{{Hatnote group|

{{Redirect|Theory of knowledge}}

{{Redirect|Epistemic|the alternative name for cognitive science|Cognitive science#Epistemics{{!}}Epistemics}}

{{For|the Keep of Kalessin album|Epistemology (album){{!}}Epistemology (album)}}

{{Distinguish|Epidemiology}}

}}

{{Featured article}}

{{Use dmy dates|date=April 2020}}

Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowledge in the form of skills, and knowledge by acquaintance as a familiarity through experience. Epistemologists study the concepts of belief, truth, and justification to understand the nature of knowledge. To discover how knowledge arises, they investigate sources of justification, such as perception, introspection, memory, reason, and testimony.

The school of skepticism questions the human ability to attain knowledge while fallibilism says that knowledge is never certain. Empiricists hold that all knowledge comes from sense experience, whereas rationalists believe that some knowledge does not depend on it. Coherentists argue that a belief is justified if it coheres with other beliefs. Foundationalists, by contrast, maintain that the justification of basic beliefs does not depend on other beliefs. Internalism and externalism debate whether justification is determined solely by mental states or also by external circumstances.

Separate branches of epistemology focus on knowledge in specific fields, like scientific, mathematical, moral, and religious knowledge. Naturalized epistemology relies on empirical methods and discoveries, whereas formal epistemology uses formal tools from logic. Social epistemology investigates the communal aspect of knowledge, and historical epistemology examines its historical conditions. Epistemology is closely related to psychology, which describes the beliefs people hold, while epistemology studies the norms governing the evaluation of beliefs. It also intersects with fields such as decision theory, education, and anthropology.

Early reflections on the nature, sources, and scope of knowledge are found in ancient Greek, Indian, and Chinese philosophy. The relation between reason and faith was a central topic in the medieval period. The modern era was characterized by the contrasting perspectives of empiricism and rationalism. Epistemologists in the 20th century examined the components, structure, and value of knowledge while integrating insights from the natural sciences and linguistics.

Definition

Epistemology is the philosophical study of knowledge and related concepts, such as justification. Also called theory of knowledge,{{efn|Less commonly, the term "gnoseology" is also used as a synonym.{{harvnb|Merriam-Webster|2024}}}} it examines the nature and types of knowledge. It further investigates the sources of knowledge, like perception, inference, and testimony, to understand how knowledge is created. Another set of questions concerns the extent and limits of knowledge, addressing what people can and cannot know.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Truncellito|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=49–50}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=16}} | {{harvnb|Carter|Littlejohn|2021|loc=Introduction: 1. What Is Epistemology?}} | {{harvnb|Moser|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=5NJjAwAAQBAJ 3]}} }} Central concepts in epistemology include belief, truth, evidence, and reason.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Fumerton|2006|pp=1–2}} | {{harvnb|Moser|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=5NJjAwAAQBAJ 4]}} }} As one of the main branches of philosophy, epistemology stands alongside fields like ethics, logic, and metaphysics.{{multiref |1={{harvnb|Brenner|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=DFoFDgAAQBAJ&pg=PT16 16]}} |2={{harvnb|Palmquist|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=NOKjGp7NHtUC&pg=PA800 800]}} |3={{harvnb|Jenicek|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=kWC1DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 31]}} }} The term can also refer specific positions of philosophers within this branch, as in Plato's epistemology and Immanuel Kant's epistemology.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Moss|2021|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Dq8SEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–2]}} }}

Epistemology explores how people should acquire beliefs. It determines which beliefs or forms of belief acquisition meet the standards or epistemic goals of knowledge and which ones fail, thereby providing an evaluation of beliefs. The fields of psychology and cognitive sociology are also interested in beliefs and related cognitive processes, but examine them from a different perspective. Unlike epistemology, they study the beliefs people actually have and how people acquire them instead of examining the evaluative norms of these processes.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=16}} | {{harvnb|Carter|Littlejohn|2021|loc=Introduction: 1. What Is Epistemology?}} }} In this regard, epistemology is a normative discipline,{{efn|Normative disciplines study how things ought to be, focusing on norms of right and wrong or criteria of evaluation. They contrast with descriptive disciplines, which examine individual facts and general patterns of how things actually are.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Barseghyan|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=hxRoCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 12–14]}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=16}} }}}} whereas psychology and cognitive sociology are descriptive disciplines.{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=16}}{{efn|Despite this contrast, epistemologists may rely on insights from the empirical sciences in formulating their normative theories.{{harvnb|O′Donohue|Kitchener|1996|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=T7uYSFSxxVkC&pg=PA2 2]}} According to one interpretation, the aim of naturalized epistemology is to answer descriptive questions, but this characterization is disputed.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=192}} | {{harvnb|Mi|2007|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=wDx1SG8tS5oC&pg=PA113 113, 115]}} }}}} Epistemology is relevant to many descriptive and normative disciplines, such as the other branches of philosophy and the sciences, by exploring the principles of how they may arrive at knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Audi|2003|pp=258–259}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=3–4}} | {{harvnb|Campbell|2024|loc=Lead section}} }}

The word epistemology comes from the ancient Greek terms {{lang|grc|ἐπιστήμη}} ({{Transliteration|grc|episteme}}, meaning knowledge or understanding) and {{lang|grc|λόγος}} ({{Transliteration|grc|logos}}, meaning study of or reason), literally, the study of knowledge. Despite its ancient roots, the word itself was coined only in the 19th century to designate this field as a distinct branch of philosophy.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Scott|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=G8aOAwAAQBAJ&pg=PT30 30]}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=3}} }}{{efn|As a label for a branch of philosophy, the term "epistemology" was first employed in 1854 by James E. Ferrier.{{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=3}} In a different context, the word was used as early as 1847 in New York's Eclectic Magazine.{{harvnb|Oxford University Press|2024}} As the term had not been coined before the 19th century, earlier philosophers did not explicitly label their theories as epistemology and often explored it in combination with psychology.{{harvnb|Alston|2006|pp=1–2}} According to philosopher Thomas Sturm, it is an open question how relevant the epistemological problems addressed by past philosophers are to contemporary philosophy.{{harvnb|Sturm|2011|pp=308–309}}}}

Central concepts

Epistemologists examine several foundational concepts to understand their essences and rely on them to formulate theories. Various epistemological disagreements have their roots in disputes about the nature and function of these concepts, like the controversies surrounding the definition of knowledge and the role of justification in it.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Goldman|McGrath|2015|pp=3–6}} | {{harvnb|Truncellito|loc=§ 2. The Nature of Propositional Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ Issues in epistemology}} }}

= Knowledge =

{{main|Knowledge}}

Knowledge is an awareness, familiarity, understanding, or skill. Its various forms all involve a cognitive success through which a person establishes epistemic contact with reality.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|1999|p=109}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=Lead section, § 1. The Varieties of Cognitive Success}} | {{harvnb|HarperCollins|2022a}}}} Epistemologists typically understand knowledge as an aspect of individuals, generally as a cognitive mental state that helps them understand, interpret, and interact with the world. While this core sense is of particular interest to epistemologists, the term also has other meanings. For example, the epistemology of groups examines knowledge as a characteristic of a group of people who share ideas.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Klausen|2015|pp=[https://portal.findresearcher.sdu.dk/da/publications/bbee5873-28f2-46d5-94b6-49ef5b18a38b 813–818]}} | {{harvnb|Lackey|2021|pp=111–112}} }} The term can also refer to information stored in documents and computers.{{multiref | {{harvnb|HarperCollins|2022a}} | {{harvnb|Magee|Popper|1971|pp=[https://archive.org/details/modernbritishphi0000mage/page/74 74–75]}} | {{harvnb|HarperCollins|2022b}} | {{harvnb|Walton|2005|pp=59, 64}} }}

Knowledge contrasts with ignorance, often simply defined as the absence of knowledge. Knowledge is usually accompanied by ignorance because people rarely have complete knowledge of a field, forcing them to rely on incomplete or uncertain information when making decisions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Gross|McGoey|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=D75hCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–4]}} | {{harvnb|Haas|Vogt|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=D75hCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA17 17–18]}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=79}} }} Even though many forms of ignorance can be mitigated through education and research, certain limits to human understanding result in inevitable ignorance.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=2, 6}} | {{harvnb|Stoltz|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pTkqEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA120 120]}} }} Some limitations are inherent in the human cognitive faculties themselves, such as the inability to know facts too complex for the human mind to conceive.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=10, 93}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009a|pp=x–xi, 57–58}} | {{harvnb|Dika|2023|p=163}} }} Others depend on external circumstances when no access to the relevant information exists.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009|pp=2, 6}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|2009a|pp=140–141}} }}

Epistemologists disagree on how much people know, for example, whether fallible beliefs can amount to knowledge or whether absolute certainty is required. The most stringent position is taken by radical skeptics, who argue that there is no knowledge at all.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wilson|2008|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=b8n609PDSrsC&pg=PA314 314]}} | {{harvnb|Pritchard|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=DGVcCIDbUQ8C&pg=PA18 18]}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|ref=Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|loc=Lead section, § 8. Implications of Fallibilism: No Knowledge?}} }}

== Types ==

File:Honourable_Bertrand_Russell.jpg originated the distinction between propositional knowledge and knowledge by acquaintance.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Brown|2016|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=gMdyCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 104]}} | {{harvnb|Hasan|Fumerton|2024|loc=§ 1. The Distinction}} }}]]

Epistemologists distinguish between different types of knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1. Kinds of Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Barnett|1990|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=eTjlAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA40 40]}} | {{harvnb|Lilley|Lightfoot|Amaral|2004|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=HT8VDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA162 162–163]}} }} Their primary interest is in knowledge of facts, called propositional knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Klein|1998|loc=§ 1. The Varieties of Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1b. Knowledge-That}} | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ The Nature of Knowledge}} }} It is theoretical knowledge that can be expressed in declarative sentences using a that-clause, like "Ravi knows that kangaroos hop". For this reason, it is also called knowledge-that.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1b. Knowledge-That}} | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ The Nature of Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|1999|p=92}} }}{{efn|Other synonyms include declarative knowledge and descriptive knowledge.{{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1b. Knowledge-That}}}} Epistemologists often understand it as a relation between a knower and a known proposition, in the case above between the person Ravi and the proposition "kangaroos hop". It is use-independent since it is not tied to one specific purpose, unlike practical knowledge. It is a mental representation that embodies concepts and ideas to reflect reality.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Morrison|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=znbkHaC8QeMC&pg=PA371 371]}} | {{harvnb|Reif|2008|p=33}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|1999|p=93}} }} Because of its theoretical nature, it is typically held that only creatures with highly developed minds, such as humans, possess propositional knowledge.{{harvnb|Pritchard|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 4]}}

Propositional knowledge contrasts with non-propositional knowledge in the form of knowledge-how and knowledge by acquaintance.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1. Kinds of Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ The Nature of Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Stanley|Willlamson|2001|pp=[https://philpapers.org/rec/WILKHV 411–412]}} }} Knowledge-how is a practical ability or skill, like knowing how to read or how to prepare lasagna.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1d. Knowing-How}} | {{harvnb|Pritchard|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA3 3]}} }} It is usually tied to a specific goal and not mastered in the abstract without concrete practice.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Merriënboer|1997|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=o0I3IXLfXuAC&pg=PA32 32]}} | {{harvnb|Klauer|Manstetten|Petersen|Schiller|2016|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=YjglDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA105 105–6]}} | {{harvnb|Pavese|2022|loc=[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-how/ Lead section]}} }} To know something by acquaintance means to have an immediate familiarity with or awareness of it, usually as a result of direct experiential contact. Examples are "familiarity with the city of Perth", "knowing the taste of tsampa", and "knowing Marta Vieira da Silva personally".{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 1a. Knowing by Acquaintance}} | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ St. Anselm of Canterbury}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|1999|p=92}} | {{harvnb|Benton|2024|p=4}} }}

File:Immanuel Kant portrait c1790.jpg.{{harvnb|Juhl|Loomis|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=8kiPAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 4]}}]]

Another influential distinction in epistemology is between a posteriori and a priori knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Stroll|2023|loc=§ A Priori and a Posteriori Knowledge}} | {{harvnb|Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|ref=Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Russell|2020|loc=Lead section}} }}{{efn|The distinction came to prominence in the 17th century and acted as a crucial factor in the philosophies of David Hume and Immanuel Kant.{{sfn|Stroll|2023|loc=§ A priori and a posteriori Knowledge}}}} A posteriori knowledge is knowledge of empirical facts based on sensory experience, like "seeing that the sun is shining" and "smelling that a piece of meat has gone bad".{{multiref | {{harvnb|Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|ref=Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Moser|2016|loc=Lead section}} }} This type of knowledge is associated with the empirical science and everyday affairs. A priori knowledge, by contrast, pertains to non-empirical facts and does not depend on evidence from sensory experience, like knowing that 2 + 2=4. It belongs to fields such as mathematics and logic.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Russell|2020|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|ref=Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori"|loc=Lead section, § 1. An Initial Characterization}} | {{harvnb|Moser|2016|loc=Lead section}}}} The distinction between a posteriori and a priori knowledge is central to the debate between empiricists and rationalists regarding whether all knowledge depends on sensory experience.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Carter|Littlejohn|2021|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=w98mEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA79 § 3. The Apriori]}} | {{harvnb|Popper|2014|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pXd9AwAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 2. Deductivism and Inductivism]}} }}

A closely related contrast is between analytic and synthetic truths. A sentence is analytically true if its truth depends only on the meanings of the words it uses. For instance, the sentence "all bachelors are unmarried" is analytically true because the word "bachelor" already includes the meaning "unmarried". A sentence is synthetically true if its truth depends on additional facts. For example, the sentence "snow is white" is synthetically true because its truth depends on the color of snow in addition to the meanings of the words snow and white. A priori knowledge is primarily associated with analytic sentences, whereas a posteriori knowledge is primarily associated with synthetic sentences. However, it is controversial whether this is true for all cases. Some philosophers, such as Willard Van Orman Quine, reject the distinction, saying that there are no analytic truths.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Juhl|Loomis|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=8kiPAgAAQBAJ&pg=PR9 ix–x, 1–2]}} | {{harvnb|Russell|2023}} | {{harvnb|Pradhan|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=DR-VDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 75]}} }}

== Analysis ==

{{main|Definitions of knowledge}}

The analysis of knowledge is the attempt to identify the essential components or conditions of all and only propositional knowledge states. According to the so-called traditional analysis,{{efn|The accuracy of the label traditional analysis is debated since it suggests widespread acceptance within the history of philosophy, an idea not shared by all scholars.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=54–55}} | {{harvnb|Ayers|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Qt-RDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 4]}} }}}} knowledge has three components: it is a belief that is justified and true.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=53–54}} }} In the second half of the 20th century, this view was challenged by a series of thought experiments aiming to show that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=61–62}} | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 3. The Gettier Problem}} }} In one of them, a person is unaware of all the fake barns in their area. By coincidence, they stop in front of the only real barn and form a justified true belief that it is a real barn.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rodríguez|2018|pp=29–32}} | {{harvnb|Goldman|1976|pp=771–773}} | {{harvnb|Sudduth|loc=§ 2b. Defeasibility Analyses and Propositional Defeaters}} | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 10.2 Fake Barn Cases}} }} Many epistemologists agree that this is not knowledge because the justification is not directly relevant to the truth.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=61–62}} | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 8. Epistemic Luck}} }} More specifically, this and similar counterexamples involve some form of epistemic luck, that is, a cognitive success that results from fortuitous circumstances rather than competence.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pritchard|2005|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=DGVcCIDbUQ8C&pg=PA1 1–4]}} | {{harvnb|Broncano-Berrocal|Carter|2017|loc=Lead section}} }}

File:Justified_True_Belief_model_of_knowledge.svg tried to show that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=65}} | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=Lead section, § 3. The Gettier Problem}} }}]]

Following these thought experiments, philosophers proposed various alternative definitions of knowledge by modifying or expanding the traditional analysis. According to one view, the known fact has to cause the belief in the right way.{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=67–68}} Another theory states that the belief is the product of a reliable belief formation process.{{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 6.1 Reliabilist Theories of Knowledge}} Further approaches require that the person would not have the belief if it was false,{{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 5.1 Sensitivity}} that the belief is not inferred from a falsehood,{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=75}} | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 4. No False Lemmas}} }} that the justification cannot be undermined,{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=69}} or that the belief is infallible.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 5c. Questioning the Gettier Problem, § 6. Standards for Knowing}} | {{harvnb|Kraft|2012|pp=49–50}} }} There is no consensus on which of the proposed modifications and reconceptualizations is correct.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 3. The Gettier Problem, § 7. Is Knowledge Analyzable?}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|1999|pp=93–94, 104–105}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 2.3 Knowing Facts}} }} Some philosophers, such as Timothy Williamson, reject the basic assumption underlying the analysis of knowledge by arguing that propositional knowledge is a unique state that cannot be dissected into simpler components.{{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 7. Is Knowledge Analyzable?}}

== Value ==

The value of knowledge is the worth it holds by expanding understanding and guiding action. Knowledge can have instrumental value by helping a person achieve their goals.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Degenhardt|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=FuCsDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–6]}} | {{harvnb|Pritchard|2013|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 10–11]}} | {{harvnb|Olsson|2011|pp=874–875}} }} For example, knowledge of a disease helps a doctor cure their patient.{{harvnb|McCormick|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=3BAhBQAAQBAJ&pg=PA42 42]}} The usefulness of a known fact depends on the circumstances. Knowledge of some facts may have little to no uses, like memorizing random phone numbers from an outdated phone book.{{harvnb|Pritchard|2013|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 11–12]}} Being able to assess the value of knowledge matters in choosing what information to acquire and share. It affects decisions like which subjects to teach at school and how to allocate funds to research projects.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Stehr|Adolf|2016|pp=483–485}} | {{harvnb|Powell|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GYdnEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA132 132–133]}} | {{harvnb|Meirmans|Butlin|Charmantier|Engelstädter|2019|pp=754–756}} | {{harvnb|Degenhardt|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=FuCsDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–6]}} }}

Epistemologists are particularly interested in whether knowledge is more valuable than a mere true opinion.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pritchard|Turri|Carter|2022|loc=§ 1. Value Problems}} | {{harvnb|Olsson|2011|pp=874–875}} | {{harvnb|Greco|2021|loc=§ The Value of Knowledge}} }} Knowledge and true opinion often have a similar usefulness since both accurately represent reality. For example, if a person wants to go to Larissa, a true opinion about the directions can guide them as effectively as knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Olsson|2011|pp=874–875}} | {{harvnb|Pritchard|Turri|Carter|2022|loc=§ 1. Value Problems}} | {{harvnb|Plato|2002|pp=[https://archive.org/details/fivedialogueseut00plat/page/89 89–90, 97b–98a]}} }} Considering this problem, Plato proposed that knowledge is better because it is more stable.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Olsson|2011|p=875}} | {{harvnb|Greco|2021|loc=§ The Value of Knowledge}} }} Another suggestion focuses on practical reasoning, arguing that people put more trust in knowledge than in mere true opinions when drawing conclusions and deciding what to do.{{harvnb|Pritchard|Turri|Carter|2022|loc=§ 6. Other Accounts of the Value of Knowledge}} A different response says that knowledge has intrinsic value in addition to instrumental value. This view asserts that knowledge is always valuable, whereas true opinion is only valuable in circumstances where it is useful.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pritchard|2013|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA15 15–16]}} | {{harvnb|Greco|2021|loc=§ The Value of Knowledge}} }}

= Belief and truth =

{{main|Belief|Truth}}

Beliefs are mental states about what is the case, like believing that snow is white or that God exists.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Braddon-Mitchell|Jackson|2011|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Bunnin|Yu|2008|pp=80–81}} | {{harvnb|Dretske|2005|p=85}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=18}} }} In epistemology, they are often understood as subjective attitudes that affirm or deny a proposition, which can be expressed in a declarative sentence. For instance, to believe that snow is white is to affirm the proposition "snow is white". According to this view, beliefs are representations of what the universe is like. They are stored in memory and retrieved when actively thinking about reality or deciding how to act.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Braddon-Mitchell|Jackson|2011|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2024|loc=Lead section, § 1.1 Representationalism}} | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2011|pp=14–15}} }} A different view understands beliefs as behavioral patterns or dispositions to act rather than as representational items stored in the mind. According to this perspective, to believe that there is mineral water in the fridge is nothing more than a group of dispositions related to mineral water and the fridge. Examples are the dispositions to answer questions about the presence of mineral water affirmatively and to go to the fridge when thirsty.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2024|loc=§ 1.2 Dispositionalism}} | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2011|pp=17–18}} }} Some theorists deny the existence of beliefs, saying that this concept borrowed from folk psychology oversimplifies much more complex psychological or neurological processes.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2024|loc=§ 1.5 Eliminativism, Instrumentalism, and Fictionalism}} | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2011|p=20}} }} Beliefs are central to various epistemological debates, which cover their status as a component of propositional knowledge, the question of whether people have control over and responsibility for their beliefs, and the issue of whether beliefs have degrees, called credences.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=14–15}} | {{harvnb|Schwitzgebel|2024|loc=§ 2.3 Degree of Belief, § 2.5 Belief and Knowledge}} }}

As propositional attitudes, beliefs are true or false depending on whether they affirm a true or a false proposition.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Dretske|2005|p=85}} | {{harvnb|Lowe|2005|p=926}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=18}} }} According to the correspondence theory of truth, to be true means to stand in the right relation to the world by accurately describing what it is like. This means that truth is objective: a belief is true if it corresponds to a fact.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lowe|2005|p=926}} | {{harvnb|Dowden|Swartz|loc=§ 3. Correspondence Theory}} | {{harvnb|Lynch|2011|pp=3–5}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=58}} }} The coherence theory of truth says that a belief is true if it belongs to a coherent system of beliefs. A result of this view is that truth is relative since it depends on other beliefs.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Glanzberg|2023|loc=§ 1.2 The Coherence Theory}} | {{harvnb|Lowe|2005|pp=926–927}} | {{harvnb|Lynch|2011|p=3}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=58}} }} Further theories of truth include pragmatist, semantic, pluralist, and deflationary theories.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lynch|2011|pp=5–7, 10}} | {{harvnb|Glanzberg|2023|loc=§ 1. The Neo-classical Theories of Truth, § 2. Tarski's Theory of Truth, § 4.4 Truth Pluralism, § 5. Deflationism}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=148–149}} }} Truth plays a central role in epistemology as a goal of cognitive processes and an attribute of propositional knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lynch|2011|p=5}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=148}} }}

= Justification =

{{main|Justification (epistemology)}}

In epistemology, justification is a property of beliefs that meet certain norms about what a person should believe.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Goldman|Bender|2005|p=465}} | {{harvnb|Kvanvig|2011|pp=25–26}} }} According to a common view, this means that the person has sufficient reasons for holding this belief because they have information that supports it. Another view states that a belief is justified if it is formed by a reliable belief formation process, such as perception.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=83–84}} | {{harvnb|Olsson|2016}} }} The terms reasonable, warranted, and supported are sometimes used as synonyms of the word justified.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kvanvig|2011|p=25}} | {{harvnb|Foley|1998|loc=Lead section}} }} Justification distinguishes well-founded beliefs from superstition and lucky guesses.{{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 1.3 The Justification Condition}} However, it does not guarantee truth. For example, a person with strong but misleading evidence may form a justified belief that is false.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=149}} | {{harvnb|Comesaña|Comesaña|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=LaFhEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT44 44]}} }}

Epistemologists often identify justification as a key component of knowledge.{{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=92–93}} Usually, they are not only interested in whether a person has a sufficient reason to hold a belief, known as propositional justification, but also in whether the person holds the belief because or based on{{efn|The relation between a belief and the reason on which it rests is called basing relation.{{harvnb|Silva|Oliveira|2022|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=99FkEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT10 1–4]}}}} this reason, known as doxastic justification. For example, if a person has sufficient reason to believe that a neighborhood is dangerous but forms this belief based on superstition then they have propositional justification but lack doxastic justification.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ichikawa|Steup|2018|loc=§ 1.3.2 Kinds of Justification}} | {{harvnb|Silva|Oliveira|2022|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=99FkEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT10 1–4]}} }}

== Sources ==

Sources of justification are ways or cognitive capacities through which people acquire justification. Often-discussed sources include perception, introspection, memory, reason, and testimony, but there is no universal agreement to what extent they all provide valid justification.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kern|2017|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=eyh5DQAAQBAJ&pg=PA8 8–10, 133]}} | {{harvnb|Smith|2023|p=3}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5. Sources of Knowledge and Justification}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 3. Ways of Knowing}}}} Perception relies on sensory organs to gain empirical information. Distinct forms of perception correspond to different physical stimuli, such as visual, auditory, haptic, olfactory, and gustatory perception.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5.1 Perception}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 3. Ways of Knowing}} }} Perception is not merely the reception of sense impressions but an active process that selects, organizes, and interprets sensory signals.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Khatoon|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Ha1KBZm9CXQC&pg=PA104 104]}} | {{harvnb|Martin|1998|loc=Lead section}} }} Introspection is a closely related process focused on internal mental states rather than external physical objects. For example, seeing a bus at a bus station belongs to perception while feeling tired belongs to introspection.{{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5.2 Introspection}}

Rationalists understand reason as a source of justification for non-empirical facts, explaining how people can know about mathematical, logical, and conceptual truths. Reason is also responsible for inferential knowledge, in which one or more beliefs serve as premises to support another belief.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 3d. Knowing by Thinking-Plus-Observing}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5.4 Reason}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2002|pp=85, 90–91}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-YPTEeIhOXYC&pg=PA38 38]}} }} Memory depends on information provided by other sources, which it retains and recalls, like remembering a phone number perceived earlier.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5.3 Memory}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2002|pp=72–75}} | {{harvnb|Gardiner|2001|pp=1351–1352}} | {{harvnb|Michaelian|Sutton|2017|loc=§ 3. Episodicity}} }} Justification by testimony relies on information one person communicates to another person. This can happen by talking to each other but can also occur in other forms, like a letter, a newspaper, and a blog.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5.5 Testimony}} | {{harvnb|Leonard|2021|loc=Lead section, § 1. Reductionism and Non-Reductionism}} | {{harvnb|Green|2022|loc=Lead section}} }}

= Other concepts =

Rationality is closely related to justification and the terms rational belief and justified belief are sometimes used interchangeably. However, rationality has a wider scope that encompasses both a theoretical side, covering beliefs, and a practical side, covering decisions, intentions, and actions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=123–124}} | {{harvnb|Foley|2011|pp=37, 39–40}} | {{harvnb|Harman|2013|loc=§ Theoretical and Practical Rationality}} | {{harvnb|Mele|Rawling|2004|pp=3–4}} }} There are different conceptions about what it means for something to be rational. According to one view, a mental state is rational if it is based on or responsive to good reasons. Another view emphasizes the role of coherence, stating that rationality requires that the different mental states of a person are consistent and support each other.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Heinzelmann|2023|pp=312–314}} | {{harvnb|Kiesewetter|2020|pp=332–334}} }} A slightly different approach holds that rationality is about achieving certain goals. Two goals of theoretical rationality are accuracy and comprehensiveness, meaning that a person has as few false beliefs and as many true beliefs as possible.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Foley|2011|pp=39–40}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=123–124}} }}

Epistemologists rely on the concept of epistemic norms as criteria to assess the cognitive quality of beliefs, like their justification and rationality. They distinguish between deontic norms, which prescribe what people should believe, and axiological norms, which identify the goals and values of beliefs.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=109}} | {{harvnb|Engel|2011|p=47}} }} Epistemic norms are closely linked to intellectual or epistemic virtues, which are character traits like open-mindedness and conscientiousness. Epistemic virtues help individuals form true beliefs and acquire knowledge. They contrast with epistemic vices and act as foundational concepts of virtue epistemology.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=88}} | {{harvnb|Choo|2016|pp=91–92}} | {{harvnb|Montmarquet|1987|pp=482–483]}} }}{{efn|Interest in epistemic virtues has increased since Ernest Sosa's formulation of virtue epistemology in the 1980s.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Turri|Alfano|Greco|2021|loc=§ 2. Precursors and Contemporary Origins}} | {{harvnb|Greco|2005|p=288}} }}}}

Epistemologists understand evidence for a belief as information that favors or supports it. They conceptualize evidence primarily in terms of mental states, such as sensory impressions or other known propositions. But in a wider sense, it can also include physical objects, like bloodstains examined by forensic analysts or financial records studied by investigative journalists.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=50–51}} | {{harvnb|DiFate|loc=Lead section, § 1. The Nature of Evidence: What Is It and What Does It Do?}} | {{harvnb|Kelly|2016|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|McGrew|2011|pp=58–59}} }} Evidence is often understood in terms of probability: evidence for a belief makes it more likely that the belief is true.{{harvnb|McGrew|2011|p=59}} A defeater is evidence against a belief or evidence that undermines another piece of evidence. For instance, witness testimony linking a suspect to a crime is evidence of their guilt, while an alibi is a defeater.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sudduth|loc=Lead section, § 2c. Constraints on Propositional Defeaters}} | {{harvnb|McPherson|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=6I7fDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 10]}} }} Evidentialists analyze justification in terms of evidence by asserting that for a belief to be justified, it needs to rest on adequate evidence.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=51}} | {{harvnb|Kelly|2016|loc=§ 1. Evidence as That Which Justifies Belief}} }}

The presence of evidence usually affects doubt and certainty, which are subjective attitudes toward propositions that differ regarding their level of confidence. Doubt involves questioning the validity or truth of a proposition. Certainty, by contrast, is a strong affirmative conviction, indicating an absence of doubt about the proposition's truth. Doubt and certainty are central to ancient Greek skepticism and its goal of establishing that no belief is immune to doubt. They are also crucial in attempts to find a secure foundation of all knowledge, such as René Descartes' foundationalist epistemology.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|pp=18–19, 44}} | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005a|p=134}} | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005b|p=220}} }}

While propositional knowledge is the main topic in epistemology, some theorists focus on understanding instead. Understanding is a more holistic notion that involves a wider grasp of a subject. To understand something, a person requires awareness of how different things are connected and why they are the way they are. For example, knowledge of isolated facts memorized from a textbook does not amount to understanding. According to one view, understanding is a unique epistemic good that, unlike propositional knowledge, is always intrinsically valuable.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=150}} | {{harvnb|Grimm|2011|pp=84, 88}} | {{harvnb|Gordon|loc=Lead section}} }} Wisdom is similar in this regard and is sometimes considered the highest epistemic good. It encompasses a reflective understanding with practical applications, helping people grasp and evaluate complex situations and lead a good life.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kekes|2005|p=959}} | {{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=157}} | {{harvnb|Whitcomb|2011|p=95}} }}

In epistemology, knowledge ascription is the act of attributing knowledge to someone, expressed in sentences like "Sarah knows that it will rain today".{{harvnb|Brown|Gerken|2012|pp=1–2}} According to invariantism, knowledge ascriptions have fixed standards across different contexts. Contextualists, by contrast, argue that knowledge ascriptions are context-dependent. From this perspective, Sarah may know about the weather in the context of an everyday conversation even though she is not sufficiently informed to know it in the context of a rigorous meteorological debate.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Brown|Gerken|2012|pp=3–4}} | {{harvnb|Rysiew|2023|loc=Lead section, § 3. Support for EC: Apparently Inconsistent Knowledge Claims, Skeptical and Everyday}} }} Contrastivism, another view, argues that knowledge ascriptions are comparative, meaning that to know something involves distinguishing it from relevant alternatives. For example, if a person spots a bird in the garden, they may know that it is a sparrow rather than an eagle, but they may not know that it is a sparrow rather than an indistinguishable sparrow hologram.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Cockram|Morton|2017}} | {{harvnb|Baumann|2016|pp=59–60}} }}

Major schools of thought

= Skepticism and fallibilism =

{{main|Skepticism|Falliblism|Epistemic relativism}}

Philosophical skepticism questions the human ability to attain knowledge by challenging the foundations upon which knowledge claims rest. Some skeptics limit their criticism to specific domains of knowledge. For example, religious skeptics say that it is impossible to know about the existence of deities or the truth of other religious doctrines. Similarly, moral skeptics challenge the existence of moral knowledge and metaphysical skeptics say that humans cannot know ultimate reality.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Cohen|1998|loc=§ Article Summary}} | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005|p=838}} | {{harvnb|Moser|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA200 200]}} }} External world skepticism questions knowledge of external facts,{{multiref | {{harvnb|Greco|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA108 108]}} | {{harvnb|McKinsey|2018|loc=Lead section}} }} whereas skepticism about other minds doubts knowledge of the mental states of others.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Gomes|Reed|2018|pp=700–702}} | {{harvnb|Avramides|2023|loc=Lead Section, § 1. The (Traditional) Epistemological Problem}} }}

Global skepticism is the broadest form of skepticism, asserting that there is no knowledge in any domain.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005|p=838}} | {{harvnb|Bergmann|2021|p=57}} | {{harvnb|Moreland|Craig|2003|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=mPEN_EDiZuQC&pg=PA95 95]}} }} In ancient philosophy, this view was embraced by academic skeptics, whereas Pyrrhonian skeptics recommended the suspension of belief to attain tranquility.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hazlett|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=4INnAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA18 18]}} | {{harvnb|Levine|1999|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=umYHtjvOhwIC&pg=PA11 11]}} }} Few epistemologists have explicitly defended global skepticism. The influence of this position stems from attempts by other philosophers to show that their theory overcomes the challenge of skepticism. For example, René Descartes used methodological doubt to find facts that cannot be doubted.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005|p=838}} | {{harvnb|Comesaña|Klein|2024|loc=Lead section}} }}

One consideration in favor of global skepticism is the dream argument. It starts from the observation that, while people are dreaming, they are usually unaware of this. This inability to distinguish between dream and regular experience is used to argue that there is no certain knowledge since a person can never be sure that they are not dreaming.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Windt|2021|loc=§ 1.1 Cartesian Dream Skepticism}} | {{harvnb|Klein|1998|loc=§ 8. The Epistemic Principles and Scepticism}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Knowledge"|ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge"|loc=§ 4. Sceptical Doubts About Knowing}} }}{{efn|The brain in a vat is a similar thought experiment assuming that a person does not have a body but is merely a brain receiving electrical stimuli indistinguishable from the stimuli a brain in a body would receive. This argument also leads to the conclusion of global skepticism based on the claim that it is not possible to distinguish stimuli representing the actual world from simulated stimuli.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hookway|2005|p=838}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 6.1 General Skepticism and Selective Skepticism}} }}}} Some critics assert that global skepticism is self-refuting because denying the existence of knowledge is itself a knowledge claim. Another objection says that the abstract reasoning leading to skepticism is not convincing enough to overrule common sense.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 6.2 Responses to the Closure Argument}} | {{harvnb|Reed|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=geSrCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 75]}} }}

Fallibilism is another response to skepticism.{{harvnb|Cohen|1998|loc=§ 1. The Philosophical Problem of Scepticism, § 2. Responses to Scepticism}} Fallibilists agree with skeptics that absolute certainty is impossible. They reject the assumption that knowledge requires absolute certainty, leading them to the conclusion that fallible knowledge exists.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|ref=Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|loc=Lead section, § 9. Implications of Fallibilism: Knowing Fallibly?}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|1998|loc=§ Article Summary}} }} They emphasize the need to keep an open and inquisitive mind, acknowledging that doubt can never be fully excluded, even for well-established knowledge claims like thoroughly tested scientific theories.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|1998|loc=§ Article Summary}} | {{harvnb|Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|ref=Hetherington, "Fallibilism"|loc=§ 9. Implications of Fallibilism: Knowing Fallibly?}} }}

Epistemic relativism is related to skepticism but differs in that it does not question the existence of knowledge in general. Instead, epistemic relativists only reject the notion of universal epistemic standards or absolute principles that apply equally to everyone. This means that what a person knows depends on subjective criteria or social conventions used to assess epistemic status.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Carter|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=RzslDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA292 292]}} | {{harvnb|Luper|2004|pp=271–272}} }}

= Empiricism and rationalism =

{{main|Empiricism|Rationalism}}

{{multiple image

|perrow=2

|total_width=350

|image1=John Locke.jpg

|alt1=Oil painting of a man with gray hair wearing a brown attire

|image2=Allan Ramsay - David Hume, 1711 - 1776. Historian and philosopher - Google Art Project.jpg

|alt2=Oil painting showing a man from the front against a dark background, dressed in a red coat with gold embroidery, his left arm resting on a surface

|footer=John Locke and David Hume shaped the philosophy of empiricism.{{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=17–18, 22–23}}

}}

The debate between empiricism and rationalism centers on the origins of human knowledge. Empiricism emphasizes that sense experience is the primary source of all knowledge. Some empiricists illustrate this view by describing the mind as a blank slate that only develops ideas about the external world through the sense data received from the sensory organs. According to them, the mind can attain various additional insights by comparing impressions, combining them, generalizing to form more abstract ideas, and deducing new conclusions from them. Empiricists say that all these mental operations depend on sensory material and do not function on their own.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lacey|2005|p=242}} | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=Lead section, § 1.2 Empiricism}} }}

Even though rationalists usually accept sense experience as one source of knowledge,{{efn|Some forms of extreme rationalism, found in ancient Greek philosophy, see reason as the sole source of knowledge.{{harvnb|Lacey|2005a|p=783}}}} they argue that certain forms of knowledge are directly accessed through reason without sense experience,{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lacey|2005a|p=783}} | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=Lead section, § 1. Introduction}} }} like knowledge of mathematical and logical truths.{{harvnb|Tieszen|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=2fgQ_fuCcKAC&pg=PA175 175]}} Some forms of rationalism state that the mind possesses inborn ideas, accessible without sensory assistance. Others assert that there is an additional cognitive faculty, sometimes called rational intuition, through which people acquire nonempirical knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lacey|2005a|p=783}} | {{harvnb|Markie|Folescu|2023|loc=Lead section, § 1. Introduction}} | {{harvnb|Hales|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sINRmT4rZ5wC&pg=PA29 29]}} }} Some rationalists limit their discussion to the origin of concepts, saying that the mind relies on inborn categories to understand the world and organize experience.

= Foundationalism and coherentism =

{{main|Foundationalism|Coherentism}}

File:Foundationalism, coherentism, infinitism2.svg

Foundationalists and coherentists disagree about the structure of knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Audi|1988|pp=407–408}} | {{harvnb|Stairs|2017|pp=155–156}} | {{harvnb|Margolis|2007|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=BeyuCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA214 214]}} | {{harvnb|Fei|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Ot6uEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA79 79]}} }}{{efn|Both can be understood as responses to the regress problem.{{harvnb|Bradley|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=qKXDCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA170 170]}} In ancient philosophy, the underlying problem was discussed as Agrippa's trilemma. The trilemma distinguises three ways of providing reasons for a statement: finding a justification that needs no further reason, circular reasoning by repeating a justification stated earlier, or providing an infinite justification chain.{{harvnb|Klein|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA484 484–485]}}}} Foundationalism distinguishes between basic and non-basic beliefs. A belief is basic if it is justified directly, meaning that its validity does not depend on the support of other beliefs.{{efn|The theory of classical foundationalism has a stronger requirement by saying that basic beliefs are self-evident or indubitable.{{harvnb|Blaauw|Pritchard|2005|p=64}}}} A belief is non-basic if it is justified by another belief.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Stairs|2017|pp=155–156}} | {{harvnb|Margolis|2007|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=BeyuCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA214 214]}} }} For example, the belief that it rained last night is a non-basic belief if it is inferred from the observation that the street is wet.{{harvnb|Stairs|2017|p=155}} According to foundationalism, basic beliefs are the foundation on which all other knowledge is built while non-basic beliefs act as the superstructure resting on this foundation.

Coherentists reject the distinction between basic and non-basic beliefs, saying that the justification of any belief depends on other beliefs. They assert that a belief must align with other beliefs to amount to knowledge. This occurs when beliefs are consistent and support each other. According to coherentism, justification is a holistic aspect determined by the whole system of beliefs, which resembles an interconnected web.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Stairs|2017|pp=156–157}} | {{harvnb|O'Brien|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TOQcebWMstwC&pg=PA77 77]}} | {{harvnb|Slote|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=dCASEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA24 24]}} }}

Foundherentism is an intermediary position combining elements of both foundationalism and coherentism. It accepts the distinction between basic and non-basic beliefs while asserting that the justification of non-basic beliefs depends on coherence with other beliefs.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ruppert|Schlüter|Seide|2016|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=nF2mCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA59 59]}} | {{harvnb|Tramel|2008|pp=215–216}} }}

Infinitism presents a less common alternative perspective on the structure of knowledge. It agrees with coherentism that there are no basic beliefs while rejecting the view that beliefs can support each other in a circular manner. Instead, it argues that beliefs form infinite justification chains, in which each link of the chain supports the belief following it and is supported by the belief preceding it.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bradley|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=qKXDCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA170 170–171]}} | {{harvnb|Stairs|2017|pp=155–156}} }}

= Internalism and externalism =

{{main|Internalism and externalism#Epistemology|l1=Internalism and externalism (epistemology)}}

File:Alvin Goldman 1966.jpg was an influential defender of externalism.{{sfn|BonJour|2016}}]]

The disagreement between internalism and externalism is about the sources of justification.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=159–160}} | {{harvnb|Fumerton|2011|loc=Lead section}} }}{{efn|The internalist-externalist debate in epistemology is different from the internalism-externalism debate in philosophy of mind, which asks whether mental states depend only on the individual or also on their environment.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bernecker|2013|loc=Note 1}} | {{harvnb|Wilson|2023}} }}}} Internalists say that justification depends only on factors within the individual, such as perceptual experience, memories, and other beliefs. This view emphasizes the importance of the cognitive perspective of the individual in the form of their mental states. It is commonly associated with the idea that the relevant factors are accessible, meaning that the individual can become aware of their reasons for holding a justified belief through introspection and reflection.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Poston|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=159–160}} }}

Evidentialism is an influential internalist view, asserting that justification depends on the possession of evidence.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=99, 298}} | {{harvnb|Carter|Littlejohn|2021|loc=§ 9.3.3 An Evidentialist Argument}} | {{harvnb|Mittag|loc=Lead section}} }} In this context, evidence for a belief is any information in the individual's mind that supports the belief. For example, the perceptual experience of rain is evidence for the belief that it is raining. Evidentialists suggest various other forms of evidence, including memories, intuitions, and other beliefs.{{harvnb|Mittag|loc=§ 2b. Evidence}} According to evidentialism, a belief is justified if the individual's evidence supports it and they hold the belief on the basis of this evidence.{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=99, 298}}

Externalism, by contrast, asserts that at least some relevant factors of knowledge are external to the individual. For instance, when considering the belief that a cup of coffee stands on the table, externalists are not primarily interested in the subjective perceptual experience that led to this belief. Instead, they focus on objective factors, like the quality of the person's eyesight, their ability to differentiate coffee from other beverages, and the circumstances under which they observed the cup.{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=160}} A key motivation of many forms of externalism is that justification makes it more likely that a belief is true. Based on this view, justification is external to the extent that some factors contributing to this likelihood are not part of the believer's cognitive perspective.

Reliabilism is an externalist theory asserting that a reliable connection between belief and truth is required for justification.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=83, 301}} | {{harvnb|Olsson|2016}} }} Some reliabilists explain this in terms of reliable processes. According to this view, a belief is justified if it is produced by a reliable process, like perception. A belief-formation process is deemed reliable if most of the beliefs it generates are true. An alternative view focuses on beliefs rather than belief-formation processes, saying that a belief is justified if it is a reliable indicator of the fact it presents. This means that the belief tracks the fact: the person believes it because it is true but would not believe it otherwise.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=84}} | {{harvnb|Lyons|2016|pp=160–162}} | {{harvnb|Olsson|2016}} }}

Virtue epistemology, another type of externalism, asserts that a belief is justified if it manifests intellectual virtues. Intellectual virtues are capacities or traits that perform cognitive functions and help people form true beliefs. Suggested examples include faculties, like vision, memory, and introspection, and character traits, like open-mindedness.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=175–176}} | {{harvnb|Baehr, "Virtue Epistemology"|ref=Baehr, "Virtue Epistemology"|loc=Lead section, § 1. Introduction to Virtue Epistemology}} }}

Branches and approaches

Some branches of epistemology are characterized by their research methods. Formal epistemology employs formal tools from logic and mathematics to investigate the nature of knowledge.{{harvnb|Douven|Schupbach|2014|loc=Lead section}}{{efn|It is closely related to computational epistemology, which examines the interrelation between knowledge and computational processes.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Segura|2009|pp=557–558}} | {{harvnb|Hendricks|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Bjnje5u2q9cC&pg=PA115 115]}} }}}} For example, Bayesian epistemology represents beliefs as degrees of certainty and uses probability theory to formally define norms of rationality governing how certain people should be.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Titelbaum|2022|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=AiFnEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA3 3, 31–32]}} | {{harvnb|Cozic|2018|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=RCxhDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA68 Confirmation and Induction]}} }} Experimental epistemologists base their research on empirical evidence about common knowledge practices.{{harvnb|Beebe|2017|loc=Lead section}} Applied epistemology focuses on the practical application of epistemological principles to diverse real-world problems, like the reliability of knowledge claims on the internet, how to assess sexual assault allegations, and how racism may lead to epistemic injustice.{{harvnb|Lackey|2021|pp=3, 8–9, 13}}{{efn|Epistemic injustice happens, for example, when valid knowledge claims are dismissed or misrepresented.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Fricker|2007|pp=1–2}} | {{harvnb|Crichton|Carel|Kidd|2017|pp=65–66}} }}}} Metaepistemologists study the nature, goals, and research methods of epistemology. As a metatheory, it does not directly advocate for specific epistemological theories but examines their fundamental concepts and background assumptions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Gerken|2018|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|McHugh|Way|Whiting|2019|pp=1–2}} }}{{efn|Nonetheless, metaepistemological insights can have various indirect effects on disputes in epistemology.{{harvnb|Gerken|2018|loc=Lead section}}}}

Particularism and generalism disagree about the right method of conducting epistemological research. Particularists start their inquiry by looking at specific cases. For example, to find a definition of knowledge, they rely on their intuitions about concrete instances of knowledge and particular thought experiments. They use these observations as methodological constraints that any theory of general principles needs to follow. Generalists proceed in the opposite direction. They prioritize general epistemic principles, saying that it is not possible to accurately identify and describe specific cases without a grasp of these principles.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Greco|2021|loc=§ 1. Methodology in Epistemology: Particularism and Generalism}} | {{harvnb|Lemos|2005|pp=488–489}} | {{harvnb|Dancy|2010|pp=532–533}} }} Other methods in contemporary epistemology aim to extract philosophical insights from ordinary language or look at the role of knowledge in making assertions and guiding actions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Greco|2021|loc=§ 2. Methodology in Epistemology: Beyond Particularism}} | {{harvnb|Gardiner|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=xn2ECgAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 31, 33–35]}} }}

Phenomenological epistemology emphasizes the importance of first-person experience. It distinguishes between the natural and the phenomenological attitudes. The natural attitude focuses on objects belonging to common sense and natural science. The phenomenological attitude focuses on the experience of objects and aims to provide a presuppositionless description of how objects appear to the observer.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pietersma|2000|pp=3–4}} | {{harvnb|Howarth|1998|loc=§ Article Summary}} }}

Naturalized epistemology is closely associated with the natural sciences, relying on their methods and theories to examine knowledge. Arguing that epistemological theories should rest on empirical observation, it is critical of a priori reasoning.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=183–184, 188–189, 300}} | {{harvnb|Wrenn|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Rysiew|2021|loc=§ 2. 'Epistemology Naturalized'}} }} Evolutionary epistemology is a naturalistic approach that understands cognition as a product of evolution, examining knowledge and the cognitive faculties responsible for it through the lens of natural selection.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bradie|Harms|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Gontier|loc=Lead section}} }} Social epistemology focuses on the social dimension of knowledge. While traditional epistemology is mainly interested in the knowledge possessed by individuals, social epistemology covers knowledge acquisition, transmission, and evaluation within groups, with specific emphasis on how people rely on each other when seeking knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Tanesini|2017|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|O’Connor|Goldberg|Goldman|2024|loc=Lead section, § 1. What Is Social Epistemology?}} }}

Pragmatist epistemology is a form of fallibilism that emphasizes the close relation between knowing and acting. It sees the pursuit of knowledge as an ongoing process guided by common sense and experience while always open to revision. This approach reinterprets some core epistemological notions, for example, by conceptualizing beliefs as habits that shape actions rather than representations that mirror the world.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Legg|Hookway|2021|loc=Lead section, § 4. Pragmatist Epistemology}} | {{harvnb|Kelly|Cordeiro|2020|p=1}} }} Motivated by pragmatic considerations, epistemic conservatism is a view about belief revision. It prioritizes pre-existing beliefs, asserting that a person should only change their beliefs if they have a good reason to. One argument for epistemic conservatism rests on the recognition that the cognitive resources of humans are limited, making it impractical to constantly reexamine every belief.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Foley|1983|p=165}} | {{harvnb|Vahid|loc=Lead section, § 1. Doxastic Conservatism: The Debate, § 2. Varieties of Doxastic Conservatism}} }}

File:Elizabeth Anderson, philosopher (cropped).jpg combines the perspectives of feminist, social, and naturalized epistemology.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Clough|McHugh|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=NBcHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA177 177]}} | {{harvnb|Grasswick|2018|loc=Lead section}} }}|left]]

Postmodern epistemology critiques the conditions of knowledge in advanced societies. This concerns in particular the metanarrative of a constant progress of scientific knowledge leading to a universal and foundational understanding of reality.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sharpe|2018|pp=318–319}} | {{harvnb|Best|Kellner|1991|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=vZBKEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 165]}} }}{{efn|Influential theorists include Jean-François Lyotard and Michel Foucault.{{harvnb|Sharpe|2018|pp=318–320, 328}}}} Similarly, feminist epistemology adopts a critical perspective, focusing on the effect of gender on knowledge. Among other topics, it explores how preconceptions about gender influence who has access to knowledge, how knowledge is produced, and which types of knowledge are valued in society.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Anderson|1995|p=50}} | {{harvnb|Anderson|2024|loc=Lead section}} }} Some postmodern and feminist thinkers adopt a constructivist approach, arguing that the way people view the world is not a simple reflection of external reality but a social construction. This view emphasizes the creative role of interpretation while undermining objectivity since social constructions can vary across societies.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Chiari|Nuzzo|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=CrqNAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 21]}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=215–216, 301}} | {{harvnb|Warren|2002|p=83}} }} Another critical approach, found in decolonial scholarship, opposes the global influence of Western knowledge systems. It seeks to undermine Western hegemony and decolonize knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Lee|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ZtArDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT67 67]}} | {{harvnb|Dreyer|2017|pp=1–7}} }}

The decolonial outlook is also present in African epistemology. Grounded in African ontology, it emphasizes the interconnectedness of reality as a continuum between knowing subject and known object. It understands knowledge as a holistic phenomenon that includes sensory, emotional, intuitive, and rational aspects, extending beyond the limits of the physical domain.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Chimakonam|Ogbonnaya|2021|pp=175–176, 179–182}} | {{harvnb|Jimoh|2017|pp=121–122}} }}

Another epistemological tradition is found in ancient Indian philosophy. Its diverse schools of thought examine different sources of knowledge, called {{lang|sa-Latn|pramāṇa}}. Perception, inference, and testimony are sources discussed by most schools. Other sources only considered by some schools are non-perception, which leads to knowledge of absences, and presumption.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Phillips|1998|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Phillips|Vaidya|2024|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Bhatt|Mehrotra|2017|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=D4kwEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 12–13]}} }}{{efn|While the discussion of different sources of knowledge is also found in other traditions, Indian epistemologists typically put special emphasis on the relation between knowledge and spiritual progress, understanding the acquisition of knowledge as part of the soteriological process.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Forsthoefel|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=WN_LEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA164 164]}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 5. Sources of Knowledge and Justification}} }}}} Buddhist epistemology focuses on immediate experience, understood as the presentation of unique particulars without secondary cognitive processes, like thought and desire.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Phillips|1998|loc=§ 1. Buddhist Pragmatism and Coherentism}} | {{harvnb|Siderits|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=YzhCEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA332 332]}} }} Nyāya epistemology is a causal theory of knowledge, understanding sources of knowledge as reliable processes that cause episodes of truthful awareness. It sees perception as the primary source of knowledge and emphasizes its importance for successful action.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Phillips|1998|loc=§ 2. Nyāya Reliabilism}} | {{harvnb|Dasti|loc=Lead section, § 1.f.i. A Causal Theory of Knowledge}} }} Mīmāṃsā epistemology considers the holy scriptures known as the Vedas as a key source of knowledge, addressing the problem of their right interpretation.{{harvnb|Phillips|1998|loc=§ 2. Mīmāṃsā Self-certificationalism}} Jain epistemology states that reality is many-sided, meaning that no single viewpoint can capture the entirety of truth.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Webb|loc=§ 2. Epistemology and Logic}} | {{harvnb|Sethia|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=QYdlKv8wBiYC&pg=PA93 93]}} }}

Historical epistemology examines how the understanding of knowledge and related concepts has changed over time. It asks whether the main issues in epistemology are perennial and to what extent past epistemological theories are relevant to contemporary debates. It is particularly concerned with scientific knowledge and practices associated with it.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ávila|Almeida|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sFTaEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA235 235]}} | {{harvnb|Vermeir|2013|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=hKqCD5U_ba8C&pg=PA65 65–66]}} | {{harvnb|Sturm|2011|pp=303–304, 306, 308}} }} It contrasts with the history of epistemology, which presents, reconstructs, and evaluates epistemological theories of philosophers in the past.{{harvnb|Sturm|2011|pp=303–304, 308–309}}{{efn|The precise characterization of the contrast is disputed.{{harvnb|Sturm|2011|p=304}}}}

= Knowledge in particular domains =

Some branches of epistemology focus on knowledge within specific academic disciplines. The epistemology of science examines how scientific knowledge is generated and what problems arise in the process of validating, justifying, and interpreting scientific claims. A key issue concerns the problem of how individual observations can support universal scientific laws. Other topics include the nature of scientific evidence and the aims of science.{{multiref | {{harvnb|McCain|Kampourakis|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=wlAPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PR13 xiii–xiv]}} | {{harvnb|Bird|2010|p=[https://www.jstor.org/stable/40801354 5]}} | {{harvnb|Merritt|2020|pp=[https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/philosophical-approach-to-mond/epistemology-of-science/065BF49E6DE64BA37364BA90542815D0 1–2]}} }} The epistemology of mathematics studies the origin of mathematical knowledge. In exploring how mathematical theories are justified, it investigates the role of proofs and whether there are empirical sources of mathematical knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Murawski|2004|pp=571–572}} | {{harvnb|Sierpinska|Lerman|1996|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-009-1465-0_23 827–828]}} }}

Distinct areas of epistemology are dedicated to specific sources of knowledge. Examples are the epistemology of perception,{{harvnb|Siegel|Silins|Matthen|2014|p=781}} the epistemology of memory,{{harvnb|Conee|1998|loc=Lead section}} and the epistemology of testimony.{{harvnb|Pritchard|2004|p=[https://www.jstor.org/stable/3050633 326]}} In the epistemology of perception, direct and indirect realists debate the connection between the perceiver and the perceived object. Direct realists say that this connection is direct, meaning that there is no difference between the object present in perceptual experience and the physical object causing this experience. According to indirect realism, the connection is indirect, involving mental entities, like ideas or sense data, that mediate between the perceiver and the external world. The contrast between direct and indirect realism is important for explaining the nature of illusions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Brown|1992|p=341}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=268–269, 277–278, 300–301}} }}

Epistemological issues are found in most areas of philosophy. The epistemology of logic examines how people know that an argument is valid. For example, it explores how logicians justify that modus ponens is a correct rule of inference or that all contradictions are false.{{harvnb|Warren|2020|loc=§ 6. The Epistemology of Logic}} Epistemologists of metaphysics investigate whether knowledge of the basic structure of reality is possible and what sources this knowledge could have.{{multiref | {{harvnb|McDaniel|2020|loc=§ 7.2 The Epistemology of Metaphysics}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=§ 5. Is Metaphysics Possible?}} }} Knowledge of moral statements, like the claim that lying is wrong, belongs to the epistemology of ethics. It studies the role of ethical intuitions, coherence among moral beliefs, and the problem of moral disagreement.{{multiref | {{harvnb|DeLapp|loc=Lead section, § 6. Epistemological Issues in Metaethics}} | {{harvnb|Sayre-McCord|2023|loc=§ 5. Moral Epistemology}} }} The ethics of belief is a closely related field exploring the intersection of epistemology and ethics. It examines the norms governing belief formation and asks whether violating them is morally wrong.{{harvnb|Chignell|2018|loc=Lead section}} Religious epistemology studies the role of knowledge and justification for religious doctrines and practices. It evaluates the reliability of evidence from religious experience and holy scriptures while also asking whether the norms of reason should be applied to religious faith.{{multiref | {{harvnb|McNabb|2019|pp=1–3, 22–23}} | {{harvnb|Howard-Snyder|McKaughan|2023|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=M5LTEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 96–97]}} }}

Epistemologists of language explore the nature of linguistic knowledge. One of their topics is the role of tacit knowledge, for example, when native speakers have mastered the rules of grammar but are unable to explicitly articulate them.{{harvnb|Barber|2003|pp=1–3, 10–11, 15}} Epistemologists of modality examine knowledge about what is possible and necessary.{{harvnb|Vaidya|Wallner|2021|pp=1909–1910}} Epistemic problems that arise when two people have diverging opinions on a topic are covered by the epistemology of disagreement.{{harvnb|Croce|2023|loc=Lead section}} Epistemologists of ignorance are interested in epistemic faults and gaps in knowledge.{{harvnb|Maguire|2015|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-9309-4_4 33–34]}}

Related fields

Epistemology and psychology were not defined as distinct fields until the 19th century; earlier investigations about knowledge often do not fit neatly into today's academic categories.{{harvnb|Alston|2006|p=2}} Both contemporary disciplines study beliefs and the mental processes responsible for their formation and change. One key contrast is that psychology describes what beliefs people have and how they acquire them, thereby explaining why someone has a specific belief. The focus of epistemology is on evaluating beliefs, leading to a judgment about whether a belief is justified and rational in a particular case.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kitchener|1992|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=q_MxOPSqRjYC&pg=PA119 119]}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=16}} | {{harvnb|Schmitt|2004|pp=841–842}} }} Epistemology also shares a close connection with cognitive science, which understands mental events as processes that transform information.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schmitt|2004|pp=841–842}} | {{harvnb|Friedenberg|Silverman|Spivey|2022|pp=2–3}} }} Artificial intelligence relies on the insights of epistemology and cognitive science to implement concrete solutions to problems associated with knowledge representation and automatic reasoning.{{harvnb|Wheeler|Pereira|2004|pp=469–470, 472, 491}}

Logic is the study of correct reasoning. For epistemology, it is relevant to inferential knowledge, which arises when a person reasons from one known fact to another.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rosenberg|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=8UgVDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA184 184]}} | {{harvnb|Steup|Neta|2024|loc=§ 4.1 Foundationalism}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2002|p=90}} }} This is the case, for example, when inferring that it rained based on the observation that the streets are wet.{{harvnb|Pomerol|2012|p=190}} Whether an inferential belief amounts to knowledge depends on the form of reasoning used, in particular, that the process does not violate the laws of logic.{{harvnb|Stairs|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Km1QDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA156 156]}} Another overlap between the two fields is found in the epistemic approach to fallacies.{{harvnb|Hansen|2023|loc=§ 3.5 The Epistemic Approach to Fallacies}} Fallacies are faulty arguments based on incorrect reasoning.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hansen|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Chatfield|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=6Xg4DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA194 194]}} }} The epistemic approach to fallacies explains why they are faulty, stating that arguments aim to expand knowledge. According to this view, an argument is a fallacy if it fails to do so. A further intersection is found in epistemic logic, which uses formal logical devices to study epistemological concepts like knowledge and belief.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|2005|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=o7m3amAbDEsC&pg=PA1 1]}} | {{harvnb|Rendsvig|Symons|Wang|2024|loc=Lead section}} }}

Both decision theory and epistemology are interested in the foundations of rational thought and the role of beliefs. Unlike many approaches in epistemology, the main focus of decision theory lies less in the theoretical and more in the practical side, exploring how beliefs are translated into action.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kaplan|2005|pp=434, 443–444}} | {{harvnb|Steele|Stefánsson|2020|loc=Lead section, § 7. Concluding Remarks}} | {{harvnb|Hooker|Leach|McClennen|2012|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=7fntCAAAQBAJ&pg=PR13 xiii–xiv]}} }} Decision theorists examine the reasoning involved in decision-making and the standards of good decisions,{{harvnb|Steele|Stefánsson|2020|loc=Lead section}} identifying beliefs as a central aspect of decision-making. One of their innovations is to distinguish between weaker and stronger beliefs, which helps them consider the effects of uncertainty on decisions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kaplan|2005|pp=434, 443–444}} | {{harvnb|Steele|Stefánsson|2020|loc=§ 7. Concluding Remarks}} }}

Epistemology and education have a shared interest in knowledge, with one difference being that education focuses on the transmission of knowledge, exploring the roles of both learner and teacher.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Chazan|2022|p=15}} | {{harvnb|Leong|2007|loc=[https://www.encyclopedia.com/education/applied-and-social-sciences-magazines/epistemology-and-education § Abstract, § Some Implications for Educators]}} }} Learning theory examines how people acquire knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kelly|2004|pp=183–184}} | {{harvnb|Harasim|2017|p=4}} }} Behavioral learning theories explain the process in terms of behavior changes, for example, by associating a certain response with a particular stimulus.{{harvnb|Harasim|2017|p=11}} Cognitive learning theories study how the cognitive processes that affect knowledge acquisition transform information.{{harvnb|Harasim|2017|pp=11–12}} Pedagogy looks at the transmission of knowledge from the teacher's perspective, exploring the teaching methods they may employ.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Watkins|Mortimore|1999|pp=1–3}} | {{harvnb|Payne|2003|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=abocsyBzTMMC&pg=PA264 264]}} | {{harvnb|Gabriel|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=PreYEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT16 16]}} }} In teacher-centered methods, the teacher serves as the main authority delivering knowledge and guiding the learning process. In student-centered methods, the teacher primarily supports and facilitates the learning process, allowing students to take a more active role.{{harvnb|Emaliana|2017|pp=59–61}} The beliefs students have about knowledge, called personal epistemology, influence their intellectual development and learning success.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hofer|2008|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-1-4020-6596-5_1 3–4]}} | {{harvnb|Hofer|2001|pp=353–354, 369–370}} }}

The anthropology of knowledge examines how knowledge is acquired, stored, retrieved, and communicated. It studies the social and cultural circumstances that affect how knowledge is reproduced and changes, covering the role of institutions like university departments and scientific journals as well as face-to-face discussions and online communications. This field has a broad concept of knowledge, encompassing various forms of understanding and culture, including practical skills. Unlike epistemology, it is not interested in whether a belief is true or justified but in how understanding is reproduced in society.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Allwood|2013|pp=[https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025 69–72]}} | {{harvnb|Barth|2002|pp=1–2}} }} A closely related field, the sociology of knowledge has a similar conception of knowledge. It explores how physical, demographic, economic, and sociocultural factors impact knowledge. This field examines in what sociohistorical contexts knowledge emerges and the effects it has on people, for example, how socioeconomic conditions are related to the dominant ideology in a society.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Coser|2009|loc=[https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-concepts/sociology-knowledge Knowledge, Sociology of]}} | {{harvnb|Tufari|2003|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=4C0KAQAAMAAJ Knowledge, Sociology of]}} | {{harvnb|Scheler|Stikkers|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pFqrO7Lxiw4C&pg=PA23 23]}} }}

History

{{anchor|History of epistemology}}

Early reflections on the nature and sources of knowledge are found in ancient history. In ancient Greek philosophy, Plato (427–347 BCE) studied what knowledge is, examining how it differs from true opinion by being based on good reasons.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=260}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Ancient Philosophy}} }} He proposed that learning is a form of recollection in which the soul remembers what it already knew but had forgotten.{{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Ancient Philosophy}}{{efn|To argue for this point, Plato used the example of a slave boy, who manages to answer a series of geometry questions even though he never studied geometry.}} Plato's student Aristotle (384–322 BCE) was particularly interested in scientific knowledge, exploring the role of sensory experience and the process of making inferences from general principles.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Ancient Philosophy}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=260}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=7}} }} Aristotle's ideas influenced the Hellenistic schools of philosophy, which began to arise in the 4th century BCE and included Epicureanism, Stoicism, and skepticism. The Epicureans had an empiricist outlook, stating that sensations are always accurate and act as the supreme standard of judgments.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|pp=287–288}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=8}} }} The Stoics defended a similar position but confined their trust to lucid and specific sensations, which they regarded as true.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|p=288}} | {{harvnb|Vogt|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=4s-X8wfhemsC&pg=PA44 44]}} }} The skeptics questioned that knowledge is possible, recommending instead suspension of judgment to attain a state of tranquility.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=8}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Ancient Philosophy}} }} Emerging in the 3rd century CE and inspired by Plato's philosophy,{{harvnb|Adkins|Adkins|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=zGY1Sqjwf8kC&pg=PA393 393]}} Neoplatonism distinguished knowledge from true belief, arguing that knowledge is infallible and limited to the realm of immaterial forms.{{harvnb|Gerson|2014|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=yhcWBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA266 266–267, 277–278]}}

File:Tibet, c. 15th-16th century - Portrait of Dharmakirti - 2010.474 - Cleveland Museum of Art.tif developed a causal theory of knowledge.{{harvnb|Dunne|2006|p=753}}|left]]

The Upanishads, philosophical scriptures composed in ancient India between 700 and 300 BCE, examined how people acquire knowledge, including the role of introspection, comparison, and deduction.{{harvnb|Black|loc=Lead section}} In the 6th century BCE, the school of Ajñana developed a radical skepticism questioning the possibility and usefulness of knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Fountoulakis|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=xGtREAAAQBAJ&pg=PA23 23]}} | {{harvnb|Warder|1998|pp=43–44}} | {{harvnb|Fletcher|Romero|Talbot|Warburton|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=drX4DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA46 46]}} }} By contrast, the school of Nyaya, which emerged in the 2nd century BCE, asserted that knowledge is possible. It provided a systematic treatment of how people acquire knowledge, distinguishing between valid and invalid sources.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Prasad|1987|p=48}} | {{harvnb|Dasti|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Bhatt|1989|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=upIQgJhpmsIC&pg=PA72 72]}} }} When Buddhist philosophers became interested in epistemology, they relied on concepts developed in Nyaya and other traditions.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Prasad|1987|p=6}} | {{harvnb|Dunne|2006|p=753}} }} Buddhist philosopher Dharmakirti (6th or 7th century CE){{harvnb|Bonevac|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=neDwEAAAQBAJ&pg=PR18 xviii]}} analyzed the process of knowing as a series of causally related events.

Ancient Chinese philosophers understood knowledge as an interconnected phenomenon fundamentally linked to ethical behavior and social involvement. Many saw wisdom as the goal of attaining knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rošker|2021|loc=Lead section, § 2.1 Relational Epistemology}} | {{harvnb|Shen|2006|pp=215–216, 219}} }} Mozi (470–391 BCE) proposed a pragmatic approach to knowledge using historical records, sensory evidence, and practical outcomes to validate beliefs.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 2a. The Mozi, Later Mohists and Debaters (bianshi)}} | {{harvnb|Shen|2006|p=216}} }} Mencius ({{circa|372–289 BCE}}) explored analogical reasoning as a source of knowledge and employed this method to criticize Mozi.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 2c. Mencius (Mengzi, c. 372-289 B.C.E.) and Analogical Reasoning}} | {{harvnb|Shen|2006|p=216}} }} Xunzi ({{circa|310–220 BCE|lk=no}}) aimed to combine empirical observation and rational inquiry. He emphasized the importance of clarity and standards of reasoning without excluding the role of feeling and emotion.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 2d. Xunzi (310-220 B.C.E.): Dispelling Obsessions}} | {{harvnb|Shen|2006|p=216}} }}

The relation between reason and faith was a central topic in the medieval period.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=10–11}} | {{harvnb|Koterski|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=0Ejsz-WHGh4C&pg=PA9 9–10]}} }} In Arabic–Persian philosophy, al-Farabi ({{circa|870–950|lk=no}}) and Averroes (1126–1198) discussed how philosophy and theology interact, debating which one is a better vehicle to truth.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=11}} | {{harvnb|Schoenbaum|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=YeYyBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA181 181]}} }} Al-Ghazali ({{circa|1056–1111|lk=no}}) criticized many core teachings of previous Islamic philosophers, saying that they relied on unproven assumptions that did not amount to knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Griffel|2020|loc=Lead section, § 3. Al-Ghazâlî's 'Refutations' of Falsafa and Ismâ'îlism}} | {{harvnb|Vassilopoulou|Clark|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=bI59DAAAQBAJ&pg=PA303 303]}} }} Similarly in Western philosophy, Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109) proposed that theological teaching and philosophical inquiry are in harmony and complement each other.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=11}} | {{harvnb|Holopainen|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=x5FiMR3kd_8C&pg=PA75 75]}} }} Formulating a more critical approach, Peter Abelard (1079–1142) argued against unquestioned theological authorities and said that all things are open to rational doubt.{{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=11}} Influenced by Aristotle, Thomas Aquinas (1225–1274) developed an empiricist theory, stating that "nothing is in the intellect unless it first appeared in the senses".{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=11}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|pp=289–290}} }} According to an early form of direct realism proposed by William of Ockham ({{circa|1285–1349|lk=no}}), perception of mind-independent objects happens directly without intermediaries.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kaye|loc=Lead section, § 4a. Direct Realist Empiricism}} | {{harvnb|Antognazza|2024|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=MzATEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA86 86]}} }} Meanwhile, in 14th-century India, Gaṅgeśa developed a reliabilist theory of knowledge and considered the problems of testimony and fallacies.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Phillips|2024|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Prasad|1987|pp=2, 8, 200–202}} }} In China, Wang Yangming (1472–1529) explored the unity of knowledge and action, holding that moral knowledge is inborn and can be attained by overcoming self-interest.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 2g. Wang Yangming on liangzhi: Direct, Clear, Universal Knowledge, § 3h. Wang Yangming: Moral Willing as Knowing}} | {{harvnb|Shen|2006|pp=219–222}} }}

File:Frans Hals - Portret van René Descartes.jpg used methodological doubt to seek certain foundations for philosophy.{{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=14–15}}|left]]

The course of modern philosophy was shaped by René Descartes (1596–1650), who stated that philosophy must begin from a position of indubitable knowledge of first principles. Inspired by skepticism, he aimed to find absolutely certain knowledge by encountering truths that cannot be doubted. He thought that this is the case for the assertion "I think, therefore I am", from which he constructed the rest of his philosophical system.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=14–15}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|p=291}} }} Descartes, together with Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716), belonged to the school of rationalism, which asserts that the mind possesses innate ideas independent of experience.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=261}} | {{harvnb|Evans|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Oo9xDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA298 298]}} }} John Locke (1632–1704) rejected this view in favor of an empiricism according to which the mind is a blank slate. This means that all ideas depend on experience, either as "ideas of sense", which are directly presented through the senses, or as "ideas of reflection", which the mind creates by reflecting on its own activities.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=17–18}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|pp=298–299}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=261}} | {{harvnb|Uzgalis|2024|loc=§ 2. The Limits of Human Understanding}}}} David Hume (1711–1776) used this idea to explore the limits of what people can know. He said that knowledge of facts is never certain, adding that knowledge of relations between ideas, like mathematical truths, can be certain but contains no information about the world.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Coventry|Merrill|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=X950DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA161 161]}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Modern Philosophy: From Hume to Peirce}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=22–23}} }} Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) sought a middle ground between rationalism and empiricism by identifying a type of knowledge overlooked by Hume. For Kant, this knowledge pertains to principles that underlie and structure all experience, such as spatial and temporal relations and fundamental categories of understanding.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=27–30}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Modern Philosophy: From Hume to Peirce}} | {{harvnb|Thorpe|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TTBuBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 5]}} }}

In the 19th century and influenced by Kant's philosophy, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) rejected empiricism by arguing that sensory impressions alone cannot amount to knowledge since all knowledge is actively structured by the knowing subject.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Modern Philosophy: From Hume to Peirce}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=262}} }} John Stuart Mill (1806–1873), by contrast, defended a wide-sweeping form of empiricism and explained knowledge of general truths through inductive reasoning.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=262}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|p=312}} }} Charles Peirce (1839–1914) thought that all knowledge is fallible, emphasizing that knowledge seekers should remain open to revising their beliefs in light of new evidence. He used this idea to argue against Cartesian foundationalism, which seeks absolutely certain truths.{{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Modern Philosophy: From Hume to Peirce}}

In the 20th century, fallibilism was further explored by J. L. Austin (1911–1960) and Karl Popper (1902–1994).{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Twentieth Century}} | {{harvnb|Kvasz|Zeleňák|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=R3aywtFIKKsC&pg=PA71 71]}} }} In continental philosophy, Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) applied the skeptical idea of suspending judgment to the study of experience. By not judging whether an experience is accurate, he tried to describe its internal structure instead.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rockmore|2011|pp=131–132}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=44}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|p=312}} }} Influenced by earlier empiricists, logical positivists, like A. J. Ayer (1910–1989), said that all knowledge is either empirical or analytic, rejecting any form of metaphysical knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=262}} | {{harvnb|Van Inwagen|Sullivan|Bernstein|2023|loc=§ 5. Is Metaphysics Possible?}} }} Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) developed an empiricist sense-datum theory, distinguishing between direct knowledge by acquaintance of sense data and indirect knowledge by description, which is inferred from knowledge by acquaintance.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Twentieth Century}} | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|p=315}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|pp=48–49}} }} Common sense had a central place in G. E. Moore's (1873–1958) epistemology. He used trivial observations, like the fact that he has two hands, to argue against abstract philosophical theories that deviate from common sense.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Baldwin|2010|loc=§ 6. Common Sense and Certainty}} | {{harvnb|Wolenski|2004|p=49}} }} Ordinary language philosophy, as practiced by the late Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951), is a similar approach that tries to extract epistemological insights from how ordinary language is used.{{harvnb|Hamlyn|2006|pp=317–318}}

Edmund Gettier (1927–2021) conceived counterexamples against the idea that knowledge is justified true belief. These counterexamples prompted many philosophers to suggest alternative definitions of knowledge.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hamlyn|2005|p=262}} | {{harvnb|Beilby|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=omdQDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA74 74]}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Twentieth Century}} }} Developed by philosophers such as Alvin Goldman (1938–2024), reliabilism emerged as one of the alternatives, asserting that knowledge requires reliable sources and shifting the focus away from justification.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Goldman|Beddor|2021|loc=Lead section, § 1. A Paradigm Shift in Analytic Epistemology}} | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Twentieth Century, § Recent Issues}} }} Virtue epistemologists, such as Ernest Sosa (1940–present) and Linda Zagzebski (1946–present), analyse belief formation in terms of the intellectual virtues or cognitive competencies involved in the process.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Goldman|Beddor|2021|loc=§ 4.1 Virtue Reliabilism}} | {{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|p=175}} | {{harvnb|Battaly|2018|pp=1–2}} }} Naturalized epistemology, as conceived by Willard Van Orman Quine (1908–2000), employs concepts and ideas from the natural sciences to formulate its theories.{{harvnb|Crumley II|2009|pp=183–184, 188–189}} Other developments in late 20th-century epistemology were the emergence of social, feminist, and historical epistemology.{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pappas|1998|loc=§ Recent Issues}} | {{harvnb|Vagelli|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=hT33DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 96]}} }}

See also

{{Portal|Philosophy}}

{{for outline}}

  • {{annotated link|Epistemological pluralism}}
  • {{annotated link|Knowledge falsification}}
  • {{annotated link|Logology (science)}}
  • {{annotated link|Reformed epistemology}}
  • {{annotated link|Theory of Knowledge (IB Course)}}

References

=Notes=

{{Notelist}}

=Citations=

{{Reflist|30em}}

= Bibliography =

{{Refbegin|30em}}

  • {{cite book |last1=Adkins |first1=Lesley |last2=Adkins |first2=Roy A. |title=Handbook to Life in Ancient Rome |publisher=Infobase Publishing |isbn=978-0-8160-7482-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zGY1Sqjwf8kC |language=en |date=2014 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Allwood |first1=Carl Martin |author-link=Carl Martin Allwood |title=The Encyclopedia of Cross-Cultural Psychology |date=2013 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-33989-3 |pages=69–72 |chapter-url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025 |language=en |chapter=Anthropology of Knowledge |doi=10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025 |access-date=26 September 2022 |archive-date=26 September 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220926085332/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781118339893.wbeccp025 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Alston |first1=William Payne |author1-link=William Alston |title=Beyond Justification: Dimensions of Epistemic Evaluation |publisher=Cornell University Press |isbn=978-0-8014-4291-9 |date=2006 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Anderson |first1=Elizabeth |author1-link=Elizabeth S. Anderson |title=Feminist Epistemology: An Interpretation and a Defense |journal=Hypatia |volume=10 |issue=3 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/3810237 |issn=0887-5367 |date=1995 |pages=50–84 |doi=10.1111/j.1527-2001.1995.tb00737.x |jstor=3810237 |access-date=3 August 2024 |archive-date=2 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240802113229/https://www.jstor.org/stable/3810237 |url-status=live |url-access=subscription }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Anderson |first1=Elizabeth |title=Feminist Epistemology and Philosophy of Science |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 August 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=14 October 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20191014000453/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Antognazza |first1=Maria Rosa |author-link=Maria Rosa Antognazza |editor1-last=Logins |editor1-first=Arturs |editor2-last=Vollet |editor2-first=Jacques-Henri |title=Putting Knowledge to Work |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-288237-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=MzATEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA86 |chapter=Knowledge as Presence and Presentation: Highlights from the History of Knowledge-First Epistemology |date=2024 |access-date=19 July 2024 |pages=71–92 |doi=10.1093/9780191976766.003.0003}}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Audi |first1=Robert |author-link=Robert Audi |title=Foundationalism, Coherentism, and Epistemological Dogmatism |journal=Philosophical Perspectives |volume=2 |doi=10.2307/2214083 |date=1988 |pages=407–442 |jstor=2214083 |issn=1520-8583 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Audi |first1=Robert |title=The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |pages=71–94 |chapter-url=https://philpapers.org/rec/AUDTSO-3 |chapter=The Sources of Knowledge |year=2002 |access-date=12 June 2022 |archive-date=12 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220612112116/https://philpapers.org/rec/AUDTSO-3 |url-status=live |isbn=978-0-19-513005-8 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195301700.003.0003}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Audi |first1=Robert |title=Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-28108-9 |edition=2 |date=2003 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Audi |first1=Robert |editor1-last=Lackey |editor1-first=Jennifer |editor2-last=Sosa |editor2-first=Ernest |title=The Epistemology of Testimony |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-153473-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-YPTEeIhOXYC&pg=PA38 |language=en |chapter=Testimony, Credulity, and Veracity |date=2006 |access-date=15 August 2024 |pages=25–49 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199276011.003.0002}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Ávila |first1=Gabriel da Costa |last2=Almeida |first2=Tiago Santos |editor1-last=Condé |editor1-first=Mauro L. |editor2-last=Salomon |editor2-first=Marlon |title=Handbook for the Historiography of Science |publisher=Springer Nature |isbn=978-3-031-27510-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sFTaEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA235 |language=en |chapter=Lorraine Daston's Historical Epistemology: Style, Program, and School |date=2023 |access-date=30 July 2024 |pages=229–254 |doi=10.1007/978-3-031-27510-4_11}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Avramides |first1=Anita |author1-link=Anita Avramides |title=Other Minds |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/other-minds/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=7 May 2024 |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Ayers |first1=Michael |author1-link=Michael R. Ayers |title=Knowing and Seeing: Groundwork for a New Empiricism |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-257012-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Qt-RDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 |language=en |date=2019 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Baehr |first1=Jason S. |title=Virtue Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/virtue-epistemology/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=2 August 2024 |ref=Baehr, "Virtue Epistemology" |archive-date=1 April 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230401155028/https://iep.utm.edu/virtue-epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Baehr |first1=Jason S. |title=A Priori and A Posteriori |url=https://iep.utm.edu/apriori/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 September 2022 |archive-date=7 August 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210807213522/https://iep.utm.edu/apriori/ |url-status=live |ref=Baehr, "A Priori and A Posteriori" }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Baldwin |first1=Tom |author-link=Thomas Baldwin (philosopher) |title=George Edward Moore |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=17 July 2024 |date=2010 |archive-date=15 March 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230315182300/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Barber |first1=Alex |editor1-last=Barber |editor1-first=Alex |title=Epistemology of Language |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-925057-8 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2003 |pages=1–46 |doi=10.1093/oso/9780199250578.003.0001}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Barnett |first1=Ronald |author-link=Ronald Barnett |title=The Idea Of Higher Education |date=1990 |publisher=Open University Press |isbn=978-0-335-09420-2 |page=40 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eTjlAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA40 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Barseghyan |first1=Hakob |title=The Laws of Scientific Change |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-319-17596-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hxRoCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 |language=en |date=2015 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Barth |first1=Fredrik |author-link=Fredrik Barth |title=An Anthropology of Knowledge |journal=Current Anthropology |date=2002 |volume=43 |issue=1 |pages=1–18 |doi=10.1086/324131 |hdl=1956/4191 |language=en |issn=0011-3204 |hdl-access=free }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Battaly |first1=Heather |editor1-last=Battaly |editor1-first=Heather |title=The Routledge Handbook of Virtue Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-49528-4 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2018 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Baumann |first1=Peter |title=Epistemic Contrastivism, Knowledge and Practical Reasoning |journal=Erkenntnis |volume=81 |issue=1 |doi=10.1007/s10670-015-9728-z |date=2016 |pages=59–68 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/BAUECK |issn=1572-8420 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Beebe |first1=James |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=Experimental Epistemology |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/experimental-epistemology/v-1 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=30 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P067-1 |date=2017 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=30 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240730082844/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/experimental-epistemology/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Beilby |first1=James |title=Epistemology as Theology: An Evaluation of Alvin Plantinga's Religious Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-351-93932-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=omdQDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA74 |language=en |date=2017 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Benton |first1=Matthew |title=The Epistemology of Interpersonal Relations |journal=Noûs |volume=early view |issue= |doi=10.1111/nous.12499 |date=2024 |pages=92–111 |url=https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12499 |access-date=29 April 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822122339/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/nous.12499 |url-status=live |issn=1468-0068 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bergmann |first1=Michael |title=Radical Skepticism and Epistemic Intuition |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-265357-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=T7EzEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA57 |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last=Bernecker |first=Sven |chapter=Triangular Externalism |date=2013-09-03 |chapter-url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781118328408.ch25 |title=A Companion to Donald Davidson |pages=443–455 |editor-last=Lepore |editor-first=Ernie |access-date=2023-10-03 |edition=1 |publisher=Wiley |language=en |doi=10.1002/9781118328408.ch25 |isbn=978-0-470-67370-6 |editor2-last=Ludwig |editor2-first=Kirk |archive-date=9 May 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240509104056/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781118328408.ch25 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Best |first1=Steven |last2=Kellner |first2=Douglas |title=Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-349-21718-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vZBKEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 |language=en |date=1991 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bhatt |first1=Govardhan P. |title=The Basic Ways of Knowing: An In-depth Study of Kumārila's Contribution to Indian Epistemology |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass Publishers |isbn=978-81-208-0580-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=upIQgJhpmsIC&pg=PA72 |language=en |date=1989 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bhatt |first1=S. R. |last2=Mehrotra |first2=Anu |title=Buddhist Epistemology |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass Publishers |isbn=978-81-208-4114-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=D4kwEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2017 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Bird |first1=Alexander |author-link=Alexander Bird |title=The Epistemology of Science—A Bird's-eye View |journal=Synthese |volume=175 |doi=10.1007/s11229-010-9740-4 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/40801354 |issn=0039-7857 |date=2010 |pages=5–16 |jstor=40801354 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=27 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240727035537/https://www.jstor.org/stable/40801354 |url-status=live |url-access=subscription }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Blaauw |first1=Martijn |last2=Pritchard |first2=Duncan |author2-link=Duncan Pritchard |title=Epistemology A–Z |publisher=Edinburgh University Press |isbn=978-0-7486-2213-9 |date=2005 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Black |first1=Brian |title=Upanisads |url=https://iep.utm.edu/upanisad/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=14 July 2024 |archive-date=14 May 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240514105010/https://iep.utm.edu/upanisad/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bonevac |first1=Daniel |author-link=Daniel Bonevac |title=Historical Dictionary of Ethics |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=978-1-5381-7572-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=neDwEAAAQBAJ&pg=PR18 |language=en |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=BonJour |first1=Laurence |author-link=Laurence BonJour |editor1-last=McLaughlin |editor1-first=Brian P. |editor2-last=Kornblith |editor2-first=Hilary |title=Goldman and His Critics |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-60917-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2jcZDQAAQBAJ&pg=PT37 |language=en |chapter=2. Goldman Against Internalism |date=2016 |access-date=22 August 2024 |pages=22–42 |doi=10.1002/9781118609378.ch2}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Braddon-Mitchell |first1=David |last2=Jackson |first2=Frank |author2-link=Frank Cameron Jackson |chapter=Belief |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/belief/v-2 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-V006-2 |date=2011 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=21 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822122221/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/belief/v-2 |url-status=live |publisher=Routledge }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Bradie |first1=Michael |last2=Harms |first2=William |title=Evolutionary Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-evolutionary/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 July 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=9 December 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221209021728/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-evolutionary/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bradley |first1=Darren |title=A Critical Introduction to Formal Epistemology |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-78093-764-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qKXDCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA170 |language=en |date=2015 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Brenner |first1=William H. |title=Logic and Philosophy: An Integrated Introduction |date=1993 |publisher=University of Notre Dame Press |isbn=978-0-268-15898-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DFoFDgAAQBAJ&pg=PT16 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Broncano-Berrocal |first1=Fernando |last2=Carter |first2=J. Adam |chapter=Epistemic Luck |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemic-luck/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P064-1 |date=2017 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=19 August 2024 |archive-date=16 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240816091509/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemic-luck/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Brown |first1=Harold I. |title=Direct Realism, Indirect Realism, and Epistemology |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |volume=52 |issue=2 |doi=10.2307/2107939 |date=1992 |pages=341–363 |jstor=2107939 |issn=1933-1592 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Brown |first1=Derek H. |editor1-last=Costreie |editor1-first=Sorin |title=Early Analytic Philosophy - New Perspectives on the Tradition |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-319-24214-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gMdyCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 |language=en |chapter=A Study in Deflated Acquaintance Knowledge: Sense-Datum Theory and Perceptual Constancy |date=2016 |access-date=19 August 2024 |pages=99–126 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Brown |first1=Jessica |last2=Gerken |first2=Mikkel |editor1-last=Brown |editor1-first=Jessica |editor2-last=Gerken |editor2-first=Mikkel |title=Knowledge Ascriptions |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-969370-2 |language=en |chapter=1. Introduction - Knowledge Ascriptions: Their Semantics, Cognitive Bases, and Social Functions |date=2012 |pages=1–30 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199693702.003.0001}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Bunnin |first1=Nicholas |last2=Yu |first2=Jiyuan |author2-link=Jiyuan Yu |title=The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-0-470-99721-5 |language=en |date=2008 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Campbell |first1=Richmond |title=Moral Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=12 July 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822122725/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Carter |first1=J. Adam |editor1-last=Ichikawa |editor1-first=Jonathan Jenkins |title=The Routledge Handbook of Epistemic Contextualism |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-317-59469-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RzslDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA292 |language=en |chapter=Epistemological Implications of Relativism |date=2017 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=292–302 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Carter |first1=J. Adam |last2=Littlejohn |first2=Clayton |title=This Is Epistemology: An Introduction |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-119-68034-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=n_ArEAAAQBAJ |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Chatfield |first1=Tom |author-link=Tom Chatfield |title=Critical Thinking: Your Guide to Effective Argument, Successful Analysis and Independent Study |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-1-5264-1877-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6Xg4DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA194 |language=en |date=2017 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Chazan |first1=Barry |chapter=What Is "Education"? |title=Principles and Pedagogies in Jewish Education |doi=10.1007/978-3-030-83925-3_3 |date=2022 |pages=13–21 |isbn=978-3-030-83924-6 |doi-access=free |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Chiari |first1=Gabriele |last2=Nuzzo |first2=Maria Laura |title=Constructivist Psychotherapy: A Narrative Hermeneutic Approach |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-23991-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CrqNAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 |language=en |date=2009 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Chignell |first1=Andrew |title=The Ethics of Belief |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-belief/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 July 2024 |date=2018 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822122752/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-belief/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Chimakonam |first1=Jonathan O. |last2=Ogbonnaya |first2=L. Uchenna |title=African Metaphysics, Epistemology and a New Logic: A Decolonial Approach to Philosophy |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |isbn=978-3-030-72445-0 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-030-72445-0_8 |language=en |chapter=Toward an African Theory of Knowledge |date=2021 |doi=10.1007/978-3-030-72445-0_8 |pages=175–194 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Choo |first1=Chun Wei |title=The Inquiring Organization: How Organizations Acquire Knowledge and Seek Information |chapter=5. Epistemic Virtues and Vices |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199782031.003.0005 |isbn=978-0-19-045959-8 |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=2016 |pages=91–114 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Clough |first1=Sharyn |last2=McHugh |first2=Nancy Arden |author1-link=Sharyn Clough |editor1-last=Crasnow |editor1-first=Sharon |editor2-last=Intemann |editor2-first=Kristen |title=The Routledge Handbook of Feminist Philosophy of Science |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-429-01821-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NBcHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA177 |language=en |chapter='Where Are All of the Pragmatist Feminist Philosophers of Science?' |date=2020 |access-date=22 August 2024 |pages=170–184 |doi=10.1111/j.1527-2001.1991.tb01390.x}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Cockram |first1=Nathan |last2=Morton |first2=Adam |author2-link=Adam Morton |title=Contrastivism |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0346.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2 August 2024 |language=en |doi=10.1093/obo/9780195396577-0346 |date=2017 |archive-date=1 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201104111/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0346.xml |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Cohen |first1=Stewart |chapter=Scepticism |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/scepticism/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=31 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P045-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=31 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240731114908/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/scepticism/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Comesaña |first1=Juan |last2=Comesaña |first2=Manuel |title=Skepticism: The Basics |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-000-56823-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LaFhEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT44 |language=en |date=2022 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Comesaña |first1=Juan |last2=Klein |first2=Peter |title=Skepticism |author2-link=Peter D. Klein |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=31 July 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=23 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200823021826/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Conee |first1=Earl |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=Memory, Epistemology of |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/memory-epistemology-of/v-1 |publisher=Routledge |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P032-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=30 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240730082843/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/memory-epistemology-of/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Coser |first1=Lewis A. |author-link=Lewis A. Coser |title=International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences |publisher=Gale |isbn=978-0-02-928751-4 |chapter-url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-concepts/sociology-knowledge |language=en |chapter=Knowledge, Sociology of |orig-year=1968 |date=2009 |pages=8143–8148 |access-date=7 March 2023 |archive-date=7 March 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230307092450/https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-concepts/sociology-knowledge |url-status=live |doi=10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/01907-0}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Coventry |first1=Angela |last2=Merrill |first2=Kenneth R. |title=Historical Dictionary of Hume's Philosophy |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=978-1-5381-1916-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=X950DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA161 |language=en |date=2018 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Cozic |first1=Mikaël |editor1-last=Barberousse |editor1-first=Anouk |editor2-last=Bonnay |editor2-first=Denis |editor3-last=Cozic |editor3-first=Mikael |title=The Philosophy of Science: A Companion |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-069065-6 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RCxhDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA68 |language=en |chapter=Confirmation and Induction |date=2018 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=53–94 |doi=10.1093/oso/9780190690649.003.0002}}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Crichton |first1=Paul |last2=Carel |first2=Havi |last3=Kidd |first3=Ian James |author2-link=Havi Carel |title=Epistemic Injustice in Psychiatry |journal=BJPsych Bulletin |volume=41 |issue=2 |doi=10.1192/pb.bp.115.050682 |date=2017 |pages=65–70 |pmid=28400962 |pmc=5376720 |issn=2056-4708 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Croce |first1=Michel |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=The Epistemology of Disagreement |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/the-epistemology-of-disagreement/v-1 |publisher=Routledge |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P081R1-1 |date=2023 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/CROTEO-32 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Crumley II |first1=Jack S. |title=An Introduction to Epistemology |edition=2 |publisher=Broadview Press |isbn=978-1-77048-156-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=62gYgpeVT28C |language=en |date=2009 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Dancy |first1=Jonathan |author-link=Jonathan Dancy |editor1-last=Dancy |editor1-first=Jonathan |editor2-last=Sosa |editor2-first=Ernest |editor3-last=Steup |editor3-first=Matthias |title=A Companion to Epistemology |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-4443-1509-7 |language=en |chapter=Moral Epistemology |date=2010 |pages=532–536 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Dasti |first1=Matthew R. |title=Nyaya |url=https://iep.utm.edu/nyaya/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=14 July 2024 |archive-date=4 October 2012 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20121004042359/http://www.iep.utm.edu/nyaya/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Degenhardt |first1=M. A. B. |title=Education and the Value of Knowledge |date=2019 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-000-62799-2 |pages=1–6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FuCsDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en }}
  • {{cite web |last1=DeLapp |first1=Kevin M. |title=Metaethics |url=https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=19 December 2023 |archive-date=January 23, 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240123102700/https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=DiFate |first1=Victor |title=Evidence |url=https://iep.utm.edu/evidence/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=20 August 2024 |archive-date=25 June 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210625124049/https://iep.utm.edu/evidence/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Dika |first1=Tarek |title=Descartes's Method: The Formation of the Subject of Science |date=2023 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-286986-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-9itEAAAQBAJ |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Douven |first1=Igor |author-link=Igor Douven |last2=Schupbach |first2=Jonah N. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Topics in Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-993531-4 |chapter=Formal Epistemology |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199935314.013.19 |date=2014 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Dowden |first1=Bradley |last2=Swartz |first2=Norman |title=Truth |url=https://iep.utm.edu/truth/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=13 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123258/https://iep.utm.edu/truth/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Dretske |first1=Fred |author-link=Fred Dretske |chapter=Belief |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=85 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Dreyer |first1=Jaco S. |title=Practical Theology and the Call for the Decolonisation of Higher Education in South Africa: Reflections and Proposals |journal=HTS Teologiese Studies / Theological Studies |date=2017 |volume=73 |issue=4 |pages=1–7 |doi=10.4102/hts.v73i4.4805 |doi-access=free |issn=2072-8050 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Dunne |first1=John D. |author-link=John D. Dunne |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-865781-3 |edition=2 |volume=1 |date=2006 |chapter=Buddhist Epistemology |pages=753–758 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Emaliana |first1=Ive |title=Teacher-Centered or Student-Centered Learning Approach To Promote Learning? |journal=Jurnal Sosial Humaniora |date=2017 |volume=10 |issue=2 |page=59 |doi=10.12962/j24433527.v10i2.2161 |s2cid=148796695 |doi-access=free |issn=1979-5521 }}
  • {{cite book |last=Engel |first=Pascal |author-link=Pascal Engel |chapter=Epistemic Norms |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |edition=0 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |access-date=10 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123252/https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/edit/10.4324/9780203839065/routledge-companion-epistemology-sven-bernecker-duncan-pritchard |url-status=live |pages=47–57 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Evans |first1=C. Stephen |author-link=C. Stephen Evans |title=A History of Western Philosophy: From the Pre-Socratics to Postmodernism |publisher=InterVarsity Press |isbn=978-0-8308-7369-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Oo9xDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA298 |language=en |date=2018 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fei |first1=Duoyi |title=Beyond the Brain: How the Mind and the Body Shape Each Other |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-19-9558-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ot6uEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA79 |language=en |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fletcher |first1=Robert |last2=Romero |first2=Paola |last3=Talbot |first3=Marianne |last4=Warburton |first4=Nigel |last5=Whiston |first5=Amna |author4-link=Nigel Warburton |title=Philosophy: A Visual Encyclopedia |publisher=Dorling Kindersley Limited |isbn=978-0-241-50422-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=drX4DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA46 |language=en |date=2020 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Foley |first1=Richard |title=Epistemic Conservatism |journal=Philosophical Studies |volume=43 |issue=2 |doi=10.1007/bf00372381 |date=1983 |pages=165–182 |issn=0031-8116 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Foley |first1=Richard |chapter=Justification, Epistemic |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/justification-epistemic/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=13 August 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P030-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=13 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240813161101/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/justification-epistemic/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last=Foley |first=Richard |chapter=Epistemic Rationality |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |edition=0 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |access-date=10 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123252/https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/edit/10.4324/9780203839065/routledge-companion-epistemology-sven-bernecker-duncan-pritchard |url-status=live |pages=37–46 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Forsthoefel |first1=Thomas A. |editor1-last=Fuqua |editor1-first=Jonathan |editor2-last=Greco |editor2-first=John |editor3-last=McNabb |editor3-first=Tyler |title=The Cambridge Handbook of Religious Epistemology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-316-51771-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WN_LEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA164 |language=en |chapter=Hindu Religious Epistemology |date=2023 |pages=163–177 |doi=10.1017/9781009047180.014}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fountoulakis |first1=Konstantinos N. |title=Psychiatry: From Its Historical and Philosophical Roots to the Modern Face |publisher=Springer Nature |isbn=978-3-030-86541-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xGtREAAAQBAJ&pg=PA23 |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fricker |first1=Miranda |author-link=Miranda Fricker |title=Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-823790-7 |date=2007 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Friedenberg |first1=Jay |last2=Silverman |first2=Gordon |last3=Spivey |first3=Michael |title=Cognitive Science: An Introduction to the Study of Mind |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-1-5443-8015-5 |edition=4 |date=2022 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fumerton |first1=Richard A. |author-link=Richard A. Fumerton |title=Epistemology |publisher=Blackwell |isbn=978-1-4051-2566-6 |date=2006 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Fumerton |first1=Richard A. |chapter=Skepticism and Epistemic Externalism |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |access-date=10 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123252/https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/edit/10.4324/9780203839065/routledge-companion-epistemology-sven-bernecker-duncan-pritchard |url-status=live |pages=488–499 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gabriel |first1=Cle-Anne |title=Why Teach with Cases?: Reflections on Philosophy and Practice |date=2022 |publisher=Emerald Group Publishing |isbn=978-1-80382-399-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PreYEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT16 |language=en }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Gardiner |first1=J. M. |title=Episodic Memory and Autonoetic Consciousness: A First-person Approach |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences |date=2001 |volume=356 |issue=1413 |pages=1351–1361 |doi=10.1098/rstb.2001.0955 |pmid=11571027 |pmc=1088519 |issn=0962-8436 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gardiner |first1=Georgi |editor1-last=Henderson |editor1-first=David K. |editor2-last=Greco |editor2-first=John |title=Epistemic Evaluation: Purposeful Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-106256-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xn2ECgAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 |language=en |chapter=Teleologies and the Methodology of Epistemology |date=2015 |access-date=19 August 2024 |pages=31–45 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199642632.003.0002}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gerken |first1=Mikkel |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=Metaepistemology |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/metaepistemology/v-1 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=30 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/0123456789-P076-1 |date=2018 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=7 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240807031310/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/metaepistemology/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gerson |first1=Lloyd |author-link=Lloyd Gerson |editor1-last=Remes |editor1-first=Pauliina |editor2-last=Slaveva-Griffin |editor2-first=Svetla |title=The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-315-74418-6 |chapter=17. Neoplatonic Epistemology |date=2014 |pages=266–279 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yhcWBAAAQBAJ }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Glanzberg |first1=Michael |author-link=Michael Glanzberg |title=Truth |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=13 August 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=20 January 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220120210351/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/truth/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Goldman |first1=Alvin I. |author-link=Alvin I. Goldman |title=Discrimination and Perceptual Knowledge |journal=The Journal of Philosophy |date=1976 |volume=73 |issue=20 |pages=771–791 |doi=10.2307/2025679 |jstor=2025679 |issn=0022-362X }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Goldman |first1=Alvin I. |last2=Beddor |first2=Bob |title=Reliabilist Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reliabilism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=17 July 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123304/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reliabilism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Goldman |first1=Alvin |last2=Bender |first2=John |chapter=Justification, Epistemic |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=465 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Goldman |first1=Alvin I. |last2=McGrath |first2=Matthew |title=Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-998112-0 |date=2015 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gomes |first1=Anil |last2=Reed |first2=Baron |editor1-last=Machuca |editor1-first=Diego |title=Skepticism: From Antiquity to the Present |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-4725-1436-3 |url=https://philarchive.org/archive/GOMSAO-2 |language=en |chapter=Scepticism about Other Minds |date=2018 |pages=700–713 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Gontier |first1=Nathalie |title=Evolutionary Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/evo-epis/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=29 July 2024 |archive-date=18 July 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190718224205/https://www.iep.utm.edu/evo-epis/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Gordon |first1=Emma C. |title=Understanding in Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/understa/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=20 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123920/https://iep.utm.edu/understa/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Grasswick |first1=Heidi |title=Feminist Social Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminist-social-epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=22 August 2024 |date=2018 |archive-date=3 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220603210358/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminist-social-epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Greco |first1=John |editor1-last=Moser |editor1-first=Paul K. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-513005-8 |language=en |chapter=Virtues in Epistemology |date=2005 |pages=287–315 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195301700.003.0010}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Greco |first1=John |editor1-last=Greco |editor1-first=John |title=The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-990985-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA108 |language=en |chapter=5. Skepticism about the External World |date=2011 |pages=108–128 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0006}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Greco |first1=John |chapter=Epistemology |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/overview/epistemology/v-3/sections/the-value-of-knowledge-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=17 August 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P059-3 |date=2021 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=16 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240816164952/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/overview/epistemology/v-3/sections/the-value-of-knowledge-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Green |first1=Christopher R. |title=Epistemology of Testimony |url=https://iep.utm.edu/ep-testi/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=8 June 2022 |archive-date=7 March 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220307123956/https://iep.utm.edu/ep-testi/ |url-status=live |date=2022 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Griffel |first1=Frank |author-link=Frank Griffel |title=Al-Ghazali |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/al-ghazali/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 July 2024 |date=2020 |archive-date=28 May 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230528070053/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/al-ghazali/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last=Grimm |first=Stephen R. |chapter=Understanding |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |edition=0 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |access-date=10 August 2024 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822123252/https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/edit/10.4324/9780203839065/routledge-companion-epistemology-sven-bernecker-duncan-pritchard |url-status=live |pages=84–94 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Gross |first1=Matthias |last2=McGoey |first2=Linsey |author1-link=Matthias Gross |author2-link=Linsey McGoey |editor1-last=Gross |editor1-first=Matthias |editor2-last=McGoey |editor2-first=Linsey |title=Routledge International Handbook of Ignorance Studies |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-96467-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=D75hCQAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2015 |access-date=19 August 2024 |pages=1–14 |doi=10.4324/9781003100607}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Haas |first1=Jens |last2=Vogt |first2=Katja Maria |editor1-last=Gross |editor1-first=Matthias |editor2-last=McGoey |editor2-first=Linsey |title=Routledge International Handbook of Ignorance Studies |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-96467-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=D75hCQAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Ignorance and Investigation |date=2015 |access-date=19 August 2024 |pages=17–25 |doi=10.4324/9781003100607-4}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hales |first1=Steven D. |title=Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-26313-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sINRmT4rZ5wC&pg=PA29 |language=en |date=2009 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hamlyn |first1=D. W. |chapter=Epistemology, History of |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=260–262 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hamlyn |first1=D. W. |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-865783-7 |edition=2 |volume=3 |date=2006 |chapter=Epistemology, History of |pages=281–319 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Hansen |first1=Hans |title=Fallacies |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=24 July 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=29 March 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210329182946/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Harasim |first1=Linda M. |title=Learning Theory and Online Technologies |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-138-85999-9 |edition=2 |date=2017 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Harman |first1=Gilbert |author-link=Gilbert Harman |title=The International Encyclopedia of Ethics |publisher=Wiley |isbn=978-1-4051-8641-4 |edition=1 |chapter-url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee181 |language=en |chapter=Rationality |date=2013 |doi=10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee181 |access-date=21 August 2024 |archive-date=16 December 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231216021731/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee181 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |publisher=HarperCollins |title=Knowledge |url=https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=knowledge |access-date=25 October 2022 |author=HarperCollins |date=2022a |website=The American Heritage Dictionary |archive-date=29 November 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221129072236/https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=knowledge |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |title=Knowledge Base |url=https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=knowledge+base |publisher=HarperCollins |access-date=25 October 2022 |author=HarperCollins |date=2022b |website=The American Heritage Dictionary |archive-date=19 March 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220319181514/https://ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=knowledge+base |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Hasan |first1=Ali |last2=Fumerton |first2=Richard |title=Knowledge by Acquaintance vs. Description |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-acquaindescrip/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 February 2025 |date=2024 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hazlett |first1=Allan |author-link=Allan Hazlett |title=A Critical Introduction to Skepticism |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-4411-4407-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4INnAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA18 |language=en |date=2014 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Heinzelmann |first1=Nora |title=Rationality Is Not Coherence |journal=The Philosophical Quarterly |volume=74 |issue=1 |doi=10.1093/pq/pqac083 |date=2023 |pages=312–332 |issn=1467-9213 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hendricks |first1=Vincent F. |author-link=Vincent F. Hendricks |title=Mainstream and Formal Epistemology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-85789-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Bjnje5u2q9cC&pg=PA115 |language=en |date=2006 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Hetherington |first1=Stephen |title=Knowledge |url=https://iep.utm.edu/knowledg/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=18 May 2022 |archive-date=2 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220602105750/https://iep.utm.edu/knowledg/ |url-status=live |ref=Hetherington, "Knowledge" }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Hetherington |first1=Stephen |title=Fallibilism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/fallibil/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=31 July 2024 |ref=Hetherington, "Fallibilism" |archive-date=18 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200818125146/https://iep.utm.edu/fallibil/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Hofer |first1=Barbara K. |title=Personal Epistemology Research: Implications for Learning and Teaching |journal=Educational Psychology Review |volume=13 |issue=4 |doi=10.1023/A:1011965830686 |date=2001 |pages=353–383 |issn=1040-726X }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hofer |first1=Barbara K. |title=Knowing, Knowledge and Beliefs: Epistemological Studies Across Diverse Cultures |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-6596-5 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-1-4020-6596-5_1 |language=en |chapter=Personal Epistemology and Culture |date=2008 |pages=3–22 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-6596-5_1 |access-date=24 July 2024 |archive-date=27 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240727111416/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-1-4020-6596-5_1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Holopainen |first1=Toivo |editor1-last=Lagerlund |editor1-first=Henrik |title=Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy: Philosophy Between 500 and 1500 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-9728-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=x5FiMR3kd_8C&pg=PA75 |language=en |chapter=Anselm of Canterbury |date=2010 |access-date=19 July 2024 |pages=75–81 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hooker |first1=C. A. |last2=Leach |first2=J. J. |last3=McClennen |first3=E. F. |title=Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory: Volume I Theoretical Foundations |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-009-9789-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7fntCAAAQBAJ&pg=PR13 |language=en |date=2012 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hookway |first1=C. J. |chapter=Scepticism |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=838–840 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hookway |first1=C. J. |chapter=Certainty |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005a |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=134 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Hookway |first1=C. J. |chapter=Doubt |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005b |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=220 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Howard-Snyder |first1=Daniel |last2=McKaughan |first2=Daniel J. |editor1-last=Fuqua |editor1-first=Jonathan |editor2-last=Greco |editor2-first=John |editor3-last=McNabb |editor3-first=Tyler |title=The Cambridge Handbook of Religious Epistemology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-009-05145-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=M5LTEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 |language=en |chapter=The Problem of Faith and Reason |date=2023 |access-date=30 July 2024 |pages=96–114 |doi=10.1017/9781009047180.009}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Howarth |first1=Jane |chapter=Phenomenology, Epistemic Issues in |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/phenomenology-epistemic-issues-in/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=3 August 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P038-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=3 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240803085554/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/phenomenology-epistemic-issues-in/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Ichikawa |first1=Jonathan Jenkins |last2=Steup |first2=Matthias |title=The Analysis of Knowledge |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 March 2023 |date=2018 |archive-date=2 May 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220502031402/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-analysis/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Jenicek |first1=Milos |title=How to Think in Medicine: Reasoning, Decision Making, and Communication in Health Sciences and Professions |date=2018 |publisher=CRC Press |isbn=978-1-351-68402-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kWC1DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Jimoh |first1=Anselm Kole |title=Themes, Issues and Problems in African Philosophy |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |isbn=978-3-319-40796-8 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-3-319-40796-8_8 |language=en |chapter=An African Theory of Knowledge |date=2017 |pages=121–136 |doi=10.1007/978-3-319-40796-8_8 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Juhl |first1=Cory |last2=Loomis |first2=Eric |title=Analyticity |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-27841-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8kiPAgAAQBAJ&pg=PR9 |language=en |date=2009 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kaplan |first1=Mark |editor1-last=Moser |editor1-first=Paul K. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-513005-8 |language=en |chapter=Decision Theory and Epistemology |date=2005 |pages=434–462 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195301700.003.0016}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Kaye |first1=Sharon |title=Ockham (Occam), William of |url=https://iep.utm.edu/ockham/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=16 July 2024 |archive-date=23 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240723081225/https://iep.utm.edu/ockham/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kekes |first1=John |author-link=John Kekes |chapter=Wisdom |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=959 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kelly |first1=Kevin |editor1-last=Niiniluoto |editor1-first=I. |editor2-last=Sintonen |editor2-first=Matti |editor3-last=Wolenski |editor3-first=Jan |title=Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-1986-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6gvlBwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Learning Theory and Epistemology |date=2004 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=183–204 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-1986-9_5}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Kelly |first1=Thomas |title=Evidence |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/evidence/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 August 2024 |date=2016 |archive-date=8 September 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210908185254/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/evidence/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Kelly |first1=Leanne M |last2=Cordeiro |first2=Maya |title=Three Principles of Pragmatism for Research on Organizational Processes |journal=Methodological Innovations |volume=13 |issue=2 |doi=10.1177/2059799120937242 |date=2020 |hdl=10536/DRO/DU:30142042 |hdl-access=free |issn=2059-7991 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kern |first1=Andrea |title=Sources of Knowledge: On the Concept of a Rational Capacity for Knowledge |date=2017 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-41611-6 |pages=8–10, 133 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eyh5DQAAQBAJ&pg=PA8 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Khatoon |first1=Naima |author-link=Naima Khatoon |title=General Psychology |publisher=Pearson Education India |isbn=978-81-317-5999-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ha1KBZm9CXQC&pg=PA104 |language=en |date=2012 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Kiesewetter |first1=Benjamin |title=Rationality as Reasons-Responsiveness |journal=Australasian Philosophical Review |volume=4 |issue=4 |doi=10.1080/24740500.2021.1964239 |date=2020 |pages=332–342 |issn=2474-0519 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kitchener |first1=Richard |editor1-last=Duschl |editor1-first=Richard A. |editor2-last=Hamilton |editor2-first=Richard J. |title=Philosophy of Science, Cognitive Psychology, and Educational Theory and Practice |publisher=State University of New York Press |isbn=978-1-4384-0171-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=q_MxOPSqRjYC&pg=PA119 |language=en |chapter=Piaget's Genetic Epistemology: Epistemological Implications for Science Education |date=1992 |access-date=24 July 2024 |pages=116–146 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Klauer |first1=Bernd |last2=Manstetten |first2=Reiner |last3=Petersen |first3=Thomas |last4=Schiller |first4=Johannes |title=Sustainability and the Art of Long-Term Thinking |date=2016 |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-134-98618-7 |pages=105–106 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YjglDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA105 |language=en }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Klausen |first1=Søren Harnow |title=Group Knowledge: A Real-world Approach |journal=Synthese |date=2015 |volume=192 |issue=3 |pages=813–839 |doi=10.1007/s11229-014-0589-9 |s2cid=207246817 |url=https://portal.findresearcher.sdu.dk/da/publications/bbee5873-28f2-46d5-94b6-49ef5b18a38b |access-date=13 November 2022 |archive-date=1 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201125116/https://portal.findresearcher.sdu.dk/da/publications/group-knowledge-a-real-world-approach |url-status=live |issn=0039-7857 }}
  • {{cite book |last=Klein |first=Peter D. |date=1998 |chapter=Knowledge, Concept of |editor1-last=Craig |editor1-first=Edward |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/knowledge-concept-of/v-1 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P031-1 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=13 June 2022 |archive-date=13 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220613025031/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/knowledge-concept-of/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Klein |first1=Peter D. |editor1-last=Greco |editor1-first=John |title=The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-990985-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA484 |language=en |chapter=Contemporary Responses to Agrippa's Trilemma |date=2011 |pages=484–503 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0023}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Koterski |first1=Joseph W. |title=An Introduction to Medieval Philosophy: Basic Concepts |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-4443-6067-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0Ejsz-WHGh4C&pg=PA9 |language=en |date=2011 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Kraft |first1=Tim |title=Scepticism, Infallibilism, Fallibilism |journal=Discipline Filosofiche |date=2012 |volume=22 |issue=2 |pages=49–70 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/KRASIF |access-date=12 June 2022 |archive-date=2 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220602215107/https://philpapers.org/rec/KRASIF |url-status=live |issn=2279-7343 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kvanvig |first1=Jonathan L. |author-link=Jonathan L. Kvanvig |editor1-last=Bernecker |editor1-first=Sven |editor2-last=Pritchard |editor2-first=Duncan |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88200-5 |language=en |chapter=Epistemic Justification |date=2011 |pages=25–36 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Kvasz |first1=Ladislav |last2=Zeleňák |first2=Eugen |editor1-last=Parusniková |editor1-first=Zuzana |editor2-last=Cohen |editor2-first=Robert S. |title=Rethinking Popper |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-9338-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R3aywtFIKKsC&pg=PA71 |language=en |chapter=A Problem for Popper's Fallibilism |date=2009 |access-date=19 July 2024 |pages=71–80 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-9338-8_6}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lacey |first1=Alan |chapter=Empiricism |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=242–245 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lacey |first1=Alan |chapter=Rationalism |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005a |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=783–785 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lackey |first1=Jennifer |author-link=Jennifer Lackey |title=The Epistemology of Groups |year=2021 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-965660-8 |url=https://academic.oup.com/book/31841/chapter-abstract/267480629?redirectedFrom=fulltext |language=en |access-date=25 October 2022 |archive-date=25 October 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221025083743/https://academic.oup.com/book/31841/chapter-abstract/267480629?redirectedFrom=fulltext |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lee |first1=Jerry Won |title=The Politics of Translingualism: After Englishes |date=2017 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-315-31051-0 |page=67 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZtArDwAAQBAJ&pg=PT67 |language=en }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Legg |first1=Catherine |last2=Hookway |first2=Christopher |author2-link=Christopher Hookway |title=Pragmatism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 August 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=8 October 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20201008130434/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lemos |first1=Noah |editor1-last=Moser |editor1-first=Paul K. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-513005-8 |language=en |chapter=Epistemology and Ethics |date=2005 |pages=479–512 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195301700.003.0018}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Leonard |first1=Nick |title=Epistemological Problems of Testimony |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/testimony-episprob/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=8 June 2022 |date=2021 |archive-date=10 July 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220710155155/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/testimony-episprob/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Leong |first1=Wong Yew |editor1-last=Tan |editor1-first=Charlene |title=Philosophical Reflections for Educators |publisher=Cengage Learning Asia |isbn=978-981-4239-76-9 |chapter-url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/education/applied-and-social-sciences-magazines/epistemology-and-education |chapter=Epistemology And Education |date=2007 |access-date=24 July 2024 |archive-date=23 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240723162545/https://www.encyclopedia.com/education/applied-and-social-sciences-magazines/epistemology-and-education |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Levine |first1=Alan |editor1-last=Levine |editor1-first=Alan |title=Early Modern Skepticism and the Origins of Toleration |publisher=Lexington Books |isbn=978-0-7391-0024-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=umYHtjvOhwIC&pg=PA11 |language=en |chapter=1. Introduction |date=1999 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=1–19 |doi=10.5771/9780739154458-1}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lilley |first1=Simon |last2=Lightfoot |first2=Geoffrey |last3=Amaral |first3=Paulo |title=Representing Organization: Knowledge, Management, and the Information Age |date=2004 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-877541-6 |pages=162–163 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=HT8VDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA162 |language=en }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Littlejohn |first1=Ronnie |title=Chinese Philosophy: Overview of Topics |url=https://iep.utm.edu/chinese-philosophy-overview-of-topics/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=2 September 2024 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lowe |first1=E. J. |author-link=E. J. Lowe (philosopher) |chapter=Truth |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=926–927 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Luper |first1=Steven |title=Epistemic Relativism |journal=Philosophical Issues |volume=14 |issue=1 |doi=10.1111/j.1533-6077.2004.00031.x |date=2004 |pages=271–295 |issn=1758-2237 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lynch |first1=Michael P. |author-link=Michael P. Lynch |editor1-last=Bernecker |editor1-first=Sven |editor2-last=Pritchard |editor2-first=Duncan |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88200-5 |language=en |chapter=Truth |date=2011 |pages=3–13 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Lyons |first1=Jack C. |editor1-last=McLaughlin |editor1-first=Brian P. |editor2-last=Kornblith |editor2-first=Hilary |title=Goldman and His Critics |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-60917-0 |language=en |chapter=Goldman on Evidence and Reliability |date=2016 |pages=149–177 |doi=10.1002/9781118609378.ch7|url=https://philarchive.org/rec/LYOGOE }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Magee |first1=Bryan |author1-link=Bryan Magee |last2=Popper |first2=Karl R. |author2-link=Karl Popper |date=1971 |chapter=Conversation with Karl Popper |editor-last=Magee |editor-first=Bryan |title=Modern British Philosophy |publisher=St. Martin's Press |pages=[https://archive.org/details/modernbritishphi0000mage/page/74 74–75] |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/modernbritishphi0000mage/page/66 |chapter-url-access=registration |isbn=978-0-19-283047-0 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Maguire |first1=Kate |title=Margaret Mead: Contributions to Contemporary Education |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-017-9309-4 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-9309-4_4 |language=en |chapter=The Epistemology of Ignorance |series=SpringerBriefs in Education |date=2015 |pages=33–48 |doi=10.1007/978-94-017-9309-4_4 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=29 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240729210427/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-9309-4_4 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Margolis |first1=Joseph |author-link=Joseph Margolis |title=Pragmatism Without Foundations: Reconciling Realism and Relativism |edition=2 |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-4411-6728-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=BeyuCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA214 |language=en |date=2007 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Markie |first1=Peter |last2=Folescu |first2=M. |title=Rationalism Vs. Empiricism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 February 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=9 August 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190809193416/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rationalism-empiricism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Martin |first1=M. G. F. |chapter=Perception |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/perception/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=26 March 2024 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-V023-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=26 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240326091535/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/perception/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McCain |first1=Kevin |last2=Kampourakis |first2=Kostas |editor1-last=McCain |editor1-first=Kevin |editor2-last=Kampourakis |editor2-first=Kostas |title=What Is Scientific Knowledge?: An Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology of Science |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-351-33661-1 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wlAPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PR13 |language=en |chapter=Preface |date=2019 |access-date=30 July 2024 |pages=xiii–xiv }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McCormick |first1=Miriam Schleifer |title=Believing Against the Evidence: Agency and the Ethics of Belief |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-68268-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3BAhBQAAQBAJ&pg=PA42 |language=en |date=2014 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McDaniel |first1=Kris |title=This Is Metaphysics: An Introduction |date=2020 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-40077-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3tDaDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA217 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last=McGrew |first=Timothy |author-link=Timothy McGrew |chapter=Evidence |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |edition=0 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |pages=58–67 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McHugh |first1=Conor |last2=Way |first2=Jonathan |last3=Whiting |first3=Daniel |editor1-last=McHugh |editor1-first=Conor |editor2-last=Way |editor2-first=Jonathan |editor3-last=Whiting |editor3-first=Daniel |title=Metaepistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-880536-6 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2019 |pages=1–8 |doi=10.1093/oso/9780198805366.003.0001}}
  • {{cite web |last1=McKinsey |first1=Michael |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/skepticism-content-externalism/ |title=Skepticism and Content Externalism |access-date=15 February 2025 |date=2018 |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McNabb |first1=Tyler Dalton |title=Religious Epistemology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-108-45753-8 |date=2019 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=McPherson |first1=Tristram |title=Epistemology and Methodology in Ethics |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-108-71340-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6I7fDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 |language=en |date=2020 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Meirmans |first1=Stephanie |last2=Butlin |first2=Roger K. |last3=Charmantier |first3=Anne |last4=Engelstädter |first4=Jan |last5=Groot |first5=Astrid T. |last6=King |first6=Kayla C. |last7=Kokko |first7=Hanna |last8=Reid |first8=Jane M. |last9=Neiman |first9=Maurine |author6-link=Kayla C. King |author7-link=Hanna Kokko |title=Science Policies: How Should Science Funding Be Allocated? An Evolutionary Biologists' Perspective |journal=Journal of Evolutionary Biology |date=2019 |volume=32 |issue=8 |pages=754–768 |doi=10.1111/jeb.13497 |pmid=31215105 |pmc=6771946 |hdl=2164/12705 |hdl-access=free |issn=1420-9101 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Mele |first1=Alfred R. |last2=Rawling |first2=Piers |author1-link=Alfred R. Mele |editor1-last=Mele |editor1-first=Alfred R. |editor2-last=Rawling |editor2-first=Piers |title=The Oxford Handbook of Rationality |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-803324-0 |language=en |chapter=Introduction: Aspects of Rationality |date=2004 |pages=3–16 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195145397.003.0001}}
  • {{cite web |author1=Merriam-Webster |title=Definition of Gnoseology |url=https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/gnoseology |website=Merriam-Webster Dictionary |publisher=Merriam-Webster |access-date=12 July 2024 |language=en |date=2024 |archive-date=22 June 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240622232146/https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/gnoseology |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Merriënboer |first1=Jeroen J. G. van |title=Training Complex Cognitive Skills: A Four-Component Instructional Design Model for Technical Training |date=1997 |publisher=Educational Technology |isbn=978-0-87778-298-8 |page=32 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=o0I3IXLfXuAC&pg=PA32 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Merritt |first1=David |title=A Philosophical Approach to MOND: Assessing the Milgromian Research Program in Cosmology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-108-66568-1 |chapter-url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/philosophical-approach-to-mond/epistemology-of-science/065BF49E6DE64BA37364BA90542815D0 |language=en |chapter=1. The Epistemology of Science |date=2020 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=25 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240725165938/https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/philosophical-approach-to-mond/epistemology-of-science/065BF49E6DE64BA37364BA90542815D0 |url-status=live |pages=1–19 |doi=10.1017/9781108610926.002}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Mi |first1=Chienkuo |editor1-last=Mi |editor1-first=Chienkuo |editor2-last=Chen |editor2-first=Ruey-lin |title=Naturalized Epistemology and Philosophy of Science |publisher=Rodopi |isbn=978-90-420-2198-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wDx1SG8tS5oC&pg=PA113 |language=en |chapter=What Is Naturalized Epistemology? The Quinean Project |date=2007 |pages=105–128 |doi=10.1163/9789401204361_008}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Michaelian |first1=Kourken |last2=Sutton |first2=John |title=Memory |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Epis |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 October 2021 |date=2017 |archive-date=5 October 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211005180825/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/memory/#Epis |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Mittag |first1=Daniel M. |title=Evidentialism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/evidentialism/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=1 August 2024 |archive-date=18 October 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231018080408/http://iep.utm.edu/evidentialism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Montmarquet |first1=James A. |title=Epistemic Virtue |journal=Mind |volume=96 |issue=384 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/2253844 |issn=0026-4423 |date=1987 |pages=482–497 |doi=10.1093/mind/XCVI.384.482 |jstor=2253844 |url-access=subscription }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Moreland |first1=J. P. |last2=Craig |first2=William Lane |author1-link=J. P. Moreland |author2-link=William Lane Craig |title=Philosophical Foundations for a Christian Worldview |publisher=InterVarsity Press |isbn=978-0-8308-2694-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mPEN_EDiZuQC&pg=PA95 |language=en |date=2003 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Morrison |first1=Robert |title=The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning |date=2005 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-82417-0 |page=371 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=znbkHaC8QeMC&pg=PA371 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Moser |first1=Paul K. |editor-last1=Moser |editor-first1=Paul K. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-020818-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5NJjAwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2005 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=3–24 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195301700.003.0001}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Moser |first1=Paul K. |editor1-last=Greco |editor1-first=John |title=The Oxford Handbook of Skepticism |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-990985-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1ETRCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA200 |language=en |chapter=Religious Skepticism |date=2011 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=200–224 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195183214.003.0010}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Moser |first1=Paul K. |title=A Posteriori |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/a-posteriori/v-1 |website=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=18 September 2022 |language=en |date=2016 |archive-date=20 September 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220920170718/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/a-posteriori/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Moss |first1=Jessica |title=Plato's Epistemology: Being and Seeming |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-263735-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Dq8SEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Murawski |first1=Roman |editor1-last=Niiniluoto |editor1-first=I. |editor2-last=Sintonen |editor2-first=Matti |editor3-last=Wolenski |editor3-first=Jan |title=Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-1986-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6gvlBwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Mathematical Knowledge |date=2004 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=571–606 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-1986-9_16}}
  • {{cite book |last1=O'Brien |first1=Dan |title=An Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge |publisher=Polity |isbn=978-0-7456-3316-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TOQcebWMstwC&pg=PA77 |language=en |date=2006 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Olsson |first1=Erik J |title=The Value of Knowledge: The Value of Knowledge |journal=Philosophy Compass |date=2011 |volume=6 |issue=12 |pages=874–883 |doi=10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00425.x |s2cid=143034920 |issn=1747-9991 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Olsson |first1=Erik J. |title=Reliabilism |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0309.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=2 August 2024 |language=en |date=2016 |archive-date=7 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240807005748/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0309.xml |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |author1=Oxford University Press |title=Epistemology |url=https://www.oed.com/dictionary/epistemology_n |website=Oxford English Dictionary |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=13 July 2024 |date=2024 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=O’Connor |first1=Cailin |last2=Goldberg |first2=Sanford |last3=Goldman |first3=Alvin I. |author2-link=Sanford Goldberg |title=Social Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-social/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 July 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=3 May 1998 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/19980503004746/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-social/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=O′Donohue |first1=William |last2=Kitchener |first2=Richard F. |editor1-last=O′Donohue |editor1-first=William |editor2-last=Kitchener |editor2-first=Richard F. |title=The Philosophy of Psychology |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-0-85702-612-5 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=T7uYSFSxxVkC&pg=PA2 |language=en |chapter=Introduction to Section 1 |date=1996 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=1–3 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Palmquist |first1=Stephen |author-link=Stephen Palmquist |title=Cultivating Personhood: Kant and Asian Philosophy |date=2010 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-022623-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NOKjGp7NHtUC&pg=PA800 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pappas |first1=George S. |author-link=George S. Pappas |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=Epistemology, History of |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemology-history-of/v-1 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=15 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P018-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=15 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240715122529/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemology-history-of/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Pappas |first1=George S. |title=Internalist Vs. Externalist Conceptions of Epistemic Justification |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justep-intext/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=1 August 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=5 August 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190805140348/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justep-intext/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Pavese |first1=Carlotta |title=Knowledge How |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-how/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=12 December 2023 |date=2022 |archive-date=25 November 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231125132818/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-how/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Payne |first1=William Harold |author-link=William Harold Payne |editor1-last=Salvatori |editor1-first=Mariolina Rizzi |title=Pedagogy: Disturbing History, 1820–1930 |date=2003 |publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press |isbn=978-0-8229-7246-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=abocsyBzTMMC&pg=PA264 |language=en |chapter=Contributions to the Science of Education and The Education of Teachers |access-date=24 July 2024 |pages=261–271 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Phillips |first1=Stephen |chapter=Epistemology, Indian Schools of |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemology-indian-schools-of/v-1/sections/mimamsa-self-certificationalism |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=2 August 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-F042-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=2 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240802164157/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/epistemology-indian-schools-of/v-1/sections/mimamsa-self-certificationalism |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Phillips |first1=Stephen |title=Gaṅgeśa |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/gangesa/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=3 September 2024 |date=2024 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Phillips |first1=Stephen |last2=Vaidya |first2=Anand |title=Epistemology in Classical Indian Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-india/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 August 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=4 December 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221204064203/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-india/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pietersma |first1=Henry |title=Phenomenological Epistemology |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-513190-1 |date=2000 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Plato |title=Five Dialogues |date=2002 |publisher=Hackett Publishing |pages=[https://archive.org/details/fivedialogueseut00plat/page/89 89–90, 97b–98a] |isbn=978-0-87220-633-5 |url=https://archive.org/details/fivedialogueseut00plat/page/89 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pomerol |first1=Jean-Charles |title=Decision Making and Action |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-58806-2 |language=en |date=2012 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Popper |first1=Karl |title=The Two Fundamental Problems of the Theory of Knowledge |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-62683-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pXd9AwAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 |language=en |chapter=2. Deductivism and Inductivism |date=2014 |access-date=19 August 2024 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Poston |first1=Ted |title=Internalism and Externalism in Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/int-ext/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=1 August 2024 |archive-date=31 March 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230331074000/https://iep.utm.edu/int-ext/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Powell |first1=Timothy |title=The Value of Knowledge: The Economics of Enterprise Knowledge and Intelligence |date=2020 |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-059304-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GYdnEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA132 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pradhan |first1=Ramesh Chandra |title=Mind, Meaning and World: A Transcendental Perspective |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-13-7228-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DR-VDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 |language=en |date=2019 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Prasad |first1=Jwala |title=History of Indian Epistemology |publisher=Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers |isbn=978-81-215-0072-2 |date=1987 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Pritchard |first1=Duncan |title=The Epistemology of Testimony |journal=Philosophical Issues |volume=14 |doi=10.1111/j.1533-6077.2004.00033.x |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/3050633 |date=2004 |pages=326–348 |jstor=3050633 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=30 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240730082844/https://www.jstor.org/stable/3050633 |url-status=live |issn=1533-6077 |url-access=subscription }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pritchard |first1=Duncan |title=Epistemic Luck |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-153566-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DGVcCIDbUQ8C&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2005 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Pritchard |first1=Duncan |title=What Is This Thing Called Knowledge? |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-134-57367-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sfUhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2013 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Pritchard |first1=Duncan |last2=Turri |first2=John |last3=Carter |first3=J. Adam |title=The Value of Knowledge |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-value/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=17 August 2024 |date=2022 |archive-date=10 July 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220710164703/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/knowledge-value/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Reed |first1=Baron |editor1-last=Matthen |editor1-first=Mohan |title=The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-960047-2 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=geSrCQAAQBAJ&pg=PA75 |language=en |chapter=Skepticism and Perception |date=2015 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=66–80 |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199600472.013.038}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Reif |first1=Frederick |title=Applying Cognitive Science to Education: Thinking and Learning in Scientific and Other Complex Domains |date=2008 |publisher=MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-18263-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8V7RZT-IHlUC&pg=PA33 |language=en }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Rendsvig |first1=Rasmus |last2=Symons |first2=John |last3=Wang |first3=Yanjing |title=Epistemic Logic |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-epistemic/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=22 August 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=30 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240330140711/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-epistemic/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rescher |first1=Nicholas |author-link=Nicholas Rescher |chapter=Fallibilism |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/fallibilism/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=31 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-P019-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=11 May 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240511154855/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/fallibilism/v-1 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rescher |first1=Nicholas |title=Epistemic Logic: A Survey of the Logic of Knowledge |publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press |isbn=978-0-8229-7092-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=o7m3amAbDEsC&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2005 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rescher |first1=Nicholas |title=Unknowability: An Inquiry into the Limits of Knowledge |date=2009 |publisher=Lexington Books |isbn=978-0-7391-3615-7 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rescher |first1=Nicholas |title=Ignorance: On the Wider Implications of Deficient Knowledge |date=2009a |publisher=University of Pittsburgh Press |isbn=978-0-8229-6014-0 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rockmore |first1=Tom |author-link=Tom Rockmore |title=Kant and Phenomenology |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-72340-2 |chapter=Husserl's Phenomenological Epistemology |date=2011 |pages=100–138 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Rodríguez |first1=Ángel García |title=Fake Barns and Our Epistemological Theorizing |journal=Crítica: Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía |date=2018 |volume=50 |issue=148 |pages=29–54 |doi=10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2018.02 |jstor=26767766 |s2cid=171635198 |issn=0011-1503 |doi-access=free }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Rosenberg |first1=Jay |author-link=Jay Rosenberg |title=Thinking About Knowing |publisher=Clarendon Press |isbn=978-0-19-925133-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8UgVDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA184 |language=en |date=2002 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Rošker |first1=Jana |title=Epistemology in Chinese Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 September 2024 |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Ruppert |first1=Nikolai |last2=Schlüter |first2=Riske |last3=Seide |first3=Ansgar |editor1-last=Göhner |editor1-first=Julia F. |editor2-last=Jung |editor2-first=Eva-Maria |title=Susan Haack: Reintegrating Philosophy |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-319-24969-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=nF2mCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA59 |language=en |chapter=Problems at the Basis of Susan Haack's Foundherentism |date=2016 |access-date=3 August 2024 |pages=59–70 |doi=10.1007/978-3-319-24969-8_3}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Russell |first1=Bruce |title=A Priori Justification and Knowledge |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/apriori/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2022 |date=2020 |archive-date=12 August 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210812143105/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/apriori/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Russell |first1=Gillian |title=Analytic/Synthetic Distinction |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0044.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=16 August 2024 |language=en |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Rysiew |first1=Patrick |title=Naturalism in Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-naturalized/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=2 August 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=17 August 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220817114504/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-naturalized/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Rysiew |first1=Patrick |title=Epistemic Contextualism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/contextualism-epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=16 February 2025 |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Sayre-McCord |first1=Geoff |title=Metaethics |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaethics/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=19 December 2023 |date=2023 |archive-date=July 12, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230712062506/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaethics/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Scheler |first1=Max |last2=Stikkers |first2=Kenneth W. |author-link=Max Scheler |title=Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge (Routledge Revivals) |date=2012 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-415-62334-6 |page=23 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pFqrO7Lxiw4C&pg=PA23 |language=en }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Schmitt |first1=Frederick F. |editor1-last=Niiniluoto |editor1-first=I. |editor2-last=Sintonen |editor2-first=Matti |editor3-last=Wolenski |editor3-first=Jan |title=Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-1986-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6gvlBwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Epistemology and Cognitive Science |date=2004 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=841–918 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-1986-9_24}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Schoenbaum |first1=Thomas J. |title=Keeping the Faith: Religious Belief in an Age of Science |publisher=McFarland & Company |isbn=978-1-4766-1074-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YeYyBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA181 |language=en |date=2015 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Schwitzgebel |first1=Eric |author-link=Eric Schwitzgebel |editor1-last=Bernecker |editor1-first=Sven |editor2-last=Pritchard |editor2-first=Duncan |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88200-5 |language=en |chapter=Belief |date=2011 |pages=14–24 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Schwitzgebel |first1=Eric |title=Belief |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=13 August 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=15 November 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20191115080001/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Scott |first1=Julie F. |editor1-last=Marsh |editor1-first=Ian |title=Theory and Practice in Sociology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-0-13-026553-1 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=G8aOAwAAQBAJ&pg=PT30 |chapter=The Nature of Social Research and Social Knowledge |date=2002 |access-date=13 July 2024 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Segura |first1=Jordi Vallverdú i |title=Computational Epistemology and e-Science: A New Way of Thinking |journal=Minds and Machines |volume=19 |issue=4 |doi=10.1007/s11023-009-9168-0 |date=2009 |pages=557–567 |issn=0924-6495 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Sethia |first1=Tara |title=Ahiṃsā, Anekānta and Jainism |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass Publishers |isbn=978-81-208-2036-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QYdlKv8wBiYC&pg=PA93 |language=en |date=2004 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Sharpe |first1=Matthew |editor1-last=Coady |editor1-first=David |editor2-last=Chase |editor2-first=James |title=The Routledge Handbook of Applied Epistemology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-39314-6 |language=en |chapter=The Demise of Grand Narratives? Postmodernism, Power-knowledge, and Applied Epistemology |date=2018 |pages=318–331 |doi=10.4324/9781315679099-24}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Shen |first1=Vincent |author-link=Vincent Shen |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |volume=2 |date=2006 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-865782-0 |edition=2 |chapter=Chinese Philosophy: Metaphysics and Epistemology |chapter-url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/chinese-philosophy-metaphysics-and-epistemology }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Siderits |first1=Mark |title=Buddhism As Philosophy |publisher=Hackett Publishing |isbn=978-1-62466-983-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YzhCEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA332 |language=en |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Siegel |first1=Susanna |last2=Silins |first2=Nicholas |last3=Matthen |first3=Mohan |author1-link=Susanna Siegel |chapter=The Epistemology of Perception |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199600472.013.040 |title=The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Perception |editor-last1=Matthen |editor-first1=Mohan |date=2014 |publisher=Oxford University Press |pages=781–811 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Sierpinska |first1=Anna |last2=Lerman |first2=Stephen |title=International Handbook of Mathematics Education: Part 1 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-009-1465-0 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-009-1465-0_23 |language=en |chapter=Epistemologies of Mathematics and of Mathematics Education |date=1996 |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-1465-0_23 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=22 November 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231122145402/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-009-1465-0_23 |url-status=live |pages=827–876 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Silva |first1=Paul |last2=Oliveira |first2=Luis R.G. |chapter=Introduction |title=Propositional and Doxastic Justification |doi=10.4324/9781003008101-1 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=99FkEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT10 |isbn=978-1-003-00810-1 |date=2022 |access-date=15 August 2024 |publisher=Routledge }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Slote |first1=Michael |editor1-last=Zhang |editor1-first=Baosheng |editor2-last=Tong |editor2-first=Shijun |editor3-last=Cao |editor3-first=Jing |editor4-last=Fan |editor4-first=Chuanming |title=Facts and Evidence: A Dialogue Between Philosophy and Law |publisher=China University of Political Science and Law Press |isbn=978-981-15-9639-1 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=dCASEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA24 |language=en |chapter=Ying/Yang Epistemology |date=2021 |pages=23–34 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Smith |first1=Emmanuel |title=Doxastic Justification and Testimonial Beliefs |journal=Episteme |doi=10.1017/epi.2023.49 |date=2023 |pages=1–14 |issn=1750-0117 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Stairs |first1=Allen |title=A Thinker's Guide to the Philosophy of Religion |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-351-21981-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Km1QDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA156 |language=en |date=2017 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Stanley |first1=Jason |last2=Willlamson |first2=Timothy |author1-link=Jason Stanley |title=Knowing How |journal=The Journal of Philosophy |date=2001 |volume=98 |issue=8 |pages=411–444 |doi=10.2307/2678403 |jstor=2678403 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/WILKHV |access-date=12 June 2022 |archive-date=2 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220602215122/https://philpapers.org/rec/WILKHV |url-status=live |issn=0022-362X |url-access=subscription }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Steele |first1=Katie |last2=Stefánsson |first2=H. Orri |title=Decision Theory |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 July 2024 |date=2020 |archive-date=22 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240822130544/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Stehr |first1=Nico |last2=Adolf |first2=Marian T. |title=The Price of Knowledge |author1-link=Nico Stehr |journal=Social Epistemology |date=2016 |volume=30 |issue=5–6 |pages=483–512 |doi=10.1080/02691728.2016.1172366 |issn=1464-5297 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Steup |first1=Matthias |last2=Neta |first2=Ram |title=Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=12 July 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=21 July 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200721023728/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Stoltz |first1=Jonathan |title=Illuminating the Mind: An Introduction to Buddhist Epistemology |date=2021 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-090756-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pTkqEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA120 |language=en }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Stroll |first1=Avrum |title=Epistemology |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology |website=Encyclopædia Britannica |access-date=20 May 2022 |language=en |archive-date=10 July 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190710175341/https://www.britannica.com/topic/epistemology |url-status=live |date=2023 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Sturm |first1=Thomas |title=Historical Epistemology or History of Epistemology? The Case of the Relation Between Perception and Judgment: Dedicated to Günther Patzig on His 85th Birthday |journal=Erkenntnis |volume=75 |issue=3 |doi=10.1007/s10670-011-9338-3 |date=2011 |issn=1572-8420 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Sudduth |first1=Michael |title=Defeaters in Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/defeaters-in-epistemology/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 May 2022 |archive-date=2 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220602105748/https://iep.utm.edu/defeaters-in-epistemology/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Tanesini |first1=Alessandra |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |chapter=Social Epistemology |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/social-epistemology/v-2 |publisher=Routledge |access-date=29 July 2024 |doi=10.4324/0123456789-P046-2 |date=2017 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=29 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240329170812/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/social-epistemology/v-2 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Thorpe |first1=Lucas |title=The Kant Dictionary |publisher=Bloomsbury |isbn=978-1-4411-2248-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TTBuBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 |language=en |date=2014 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Tieszen |first1=Richard L. |title=Phenomenology, Logic, and the Philosophy of Mathematics |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-83782-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2fgQ_fuCcKAC&pg=PA175 |language=en |date=2005 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Titelbaum |first1=Michael G. |title=Fundamentals of Bayesian Epistemology 1: Introducing Credences |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-870760-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AiFnEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA3 |language=en |date=2022 }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Tramel |first1=Peter |title=Haack's Foundherentism Is a Foundationalism |journal=Synthese |volume=160 |issue=2 |doi=10.1007/s11229-006-9108-y |date=2008 |pages=215–228 |issn=0039-7857 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Truncellito |first1=David A. |title=Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/epistemo/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=12 July 2024 |archive-date=13 January 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220113223803/https://iep.utm.edu/epistemo/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Tufari |first1=P. |title=New Catholic Encyclopedia |date=2003 |publisher=Thomson/Gale |isbn=978-0-7876-4008-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4C0KAQAAMAAJ |language=en |chapter=Knowledge, Sociology of |access-date=7 March 2023 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Turri |first1=John |last2=Alfano |first2=Mark |last3=Greco |first3=John |author2-link=Mark Alfano |title=Virtue Epistemology |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-virtue/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 January 2025 |date=2021 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Uzgalis |first1=William |title=John Locke |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=15 February 2025 |date=2024 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Vagelli |first1=Matteo |editor1-last=Herring |editor1-first=Emily |editor2-last=Jones |editor2-first=Kevin |editor3-last=Kiprijanov |editor3-first=Konstantin |editor4-last=Sellers |editor4-first=Laura |title=The Past, Present, and Future of Integrated History and Philosophy of Science |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-351-21481-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hT33DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 |language=en |chapter=Historical Epistemology and the 'Marriage' Between History and Philosophy of Science |date=2019 |access-date=19 July 2024 |pages=96–112 |doi=10.4324/9781351214827-7}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Vahid |first1=Hamid |title=Doxastic Conservatism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/doxastic-conservatism/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=2 August 2024 |archive-date=2 August 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240802164156/https://iep.utm.edu/doxastic-conservatism/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Vaidya |first1=Anand Jayprakash |last2=Wallner |first2=Michael |title=The Epistemology of Modality and the Problem of Modal Epistemic Friction |journal=Synthese |volume=198 |issue=S8 |doi=10.1007/s11229-018-1860-2 |date=2021 |pages=1909–1935 |pmid=34720230 |pmc=8549955 |issn=0039-7857 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Van Inwagen |first1=Peter |last2=Sullivan |first2=Meghan |last3=Bernstein |first3=Sara |author1-link=Peter Van Inwagen |title=Metaphysics |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaphysics/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=17 March 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=16 September 2018 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180916103726/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaphysics/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Vassilopoulou |first1=P. |last2=Clark |first2=S. |title=Late Antique Epistemology: Other Ways to Truth |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-0-230-24077-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=bI59DAAAQBAJ&pg=PA303 |language=en |date=2009 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Vermeir |first1=Koen |editor1-last=Laerke |editor1-first=Mogens |editor2-last=Smith |editor2-first=Justin E. H. |editor3-last=Schliesser |editor3-first=Eric |title=Philosophy and Its History: Aims and Methods in the Study of Early Modern Philosophy |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-985714-2 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hKqCD5U_ba8C&pg=PA65 |language=en |chapter=Philosophy and Genealogy: Ways of Writing History of Philosophy |date=2013 |access-date=30 July 2024 |pages=50–70 |doi=10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199857142.003.0004}}
  • {{cite book |last1=Vogt |first1=Katja Maria |editor1-last=Machuca |editor1-first=Diego E. |title=Pyrrhonism in Ancient, Modern, and Contemporary Philosophy |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-007-1991-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4s-X8wfhemsC&pg=PA44 |language=en |chapter=The Aims of Skeptical Investigation |date=2011 |access-date=19 July 2024 |pages=33–50 |doi=10.1007/978-94-007-1991-0_3}}
  • {{cite journal |last=Walton |first=Douglas N. |author-link=Douglas N. Walton |date=2005 |title=Pragmatic and Idealized Models of Knowledge and Ignorance |journal=American Philosophical Quarterly |volume=42 |issue=1 |pages=59–69 [59, 64] |jstor=20010182 |issn=2152-1123 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Warder |first1=Anthony Kennedy |author-link=Anthony Kennedy Warder |title=A Course in Indian Philosophy |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass Publishers |isbn=978-81-208-1482-0 |edition=2 |date=1998 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Warren |first1=Bill |title=Philosophical Dimensions of Personal Construct Psychology |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-134-70325-8 |language=en |date=2002 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Warren |first1=Jared |title=Shadows of Syntax: Revitalizing Logical and Mathematical Conventionalism |date=2020 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-008615-2 |url=https://global.oup.com/academic/product/shadows-of-syntax-9780190086152 |access-date=30 July 2024 |archive-date=28 May 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240528232725/https://global.oup.com/academic/product/shadows-of-syntax-9780190086152 |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Watkins |first1=Chris |last2=Mortimore |first2=Peter |title=Understanding Pedagogy and Its Impact on Learning |date=1999 |publisher=Sage |doi=10.4135/9781446219454 |isbn=978-1-85396-453-4 |chapter-url=https://sk.sagepub.com/books/understanding-pedagogy-and-its-impact-on-learning/n1.xml |chapter=Pedagogy: What Do We Know? |access-date=24 July 2024 |archive-date=12 July 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220712120304/https://sk.sagepub.com/books/understanding-pedagogy-and-its-impact-on-learning/n1.xml |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Webb |first1=Mark Owen |title=Jain Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/jain/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=2 August 2024 |archive-date=28 May 2010 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100528030933/https://iep.utm.edu/jain/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite journal |last1=Wheeler |first1=Gregory R. |last2=Pereira |first2=Luís Moniz |title=Epistemology and Artificial Intelligence |journal=Journal of Applied Logic |volume=2 |issue=4 |doi=10.1016/j.jal.2004.07.007 |date=2004 |pages=469–493 |issn=1570-8683 }}
  • {{cite book |last=Whitcomb |first=Dennis |chapter=Wisdom |chapter-url=https://www.taylorfrancis.com/books/9781136882012 |title=The Routledge Companion to Epistemology |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-136-88201-2 |editor-last=Bernecker |editor-first=Sven |edition=0 |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780203839065 |editor-last2=Pritchard |editor-first2=Duncan |pages=95–106 }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Wilson |first1=Fred |title=The External World and Our Knowledge of It: Hume's Critical Realism, an Exposition and a Defence |publisher=University of Toronto Press |isbn=978-0-8020-9764-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=b8n609PDSrsC&pg=PA314 |language=en |date=2008 }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Wilson |first1=Robert A. |title=Externalism and Internalism in the Philosophy of Mind |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0352.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |access-date=11 August 2024 |language=en |date=2023 |archive-date=10 April 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230410004809/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0352.xml |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite web |last1=Windt |first1=Jennifer M. |title=Dreams and Dreaming |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dreams-dreaming/#CartDreaSkep |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=12 December 2023 |date=2021 |archive-date=1 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201125124/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dreams-dreaming/#CartDreaSkep |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Wolenski |first1=Jan |author-link=Jan Wolenski |editor1-last=Niiniluoto |editor1-first=I. |editor2-last=Sintonen |editor2-first=Matti |editor3-last=Wolenski |editor3-first=Jan |title=Handbook of Epistemology |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-1986-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6gvlBwAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=History of Epistemology |date=2004 |access-date=13 July 2024 |pages=3–56 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-1986-9_1}}
  • {{cite web |last1=Wrenn |first1=Chase B. |title=Naturalistic Epistemology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/nat-epis/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=2 August 2024 |archive-date=16 July 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240716142002/https://iep.utm.edu/nat-epis/ |url-status=live }}
  • {{cite book |last1=Zagzebski |first1=Linda |author1-link=Linda Zagzebski |date=1999 |chapter=What Is Knowledge? |editor1-last=Greco |editor1-first=John |editor2-last=Sosa |editor2-first=Ernest |title=The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology |publisher=Blackwell |pages=92–116 |chapter-url=https://philpapers.org/rec/ZAGWIK |isbn=978-0-631-20290-5 |doi=10.1002/9781405164863.ch3 |s2cid=158886670 |access-date=12 June 2022 |archive-date=2 June 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220602215147/https://philpapers.org/rec/ZAGWIK |url-status=live }}

{{Refend}}