Peano axioms#First-order theory of arithmetic
{{short description|Axioms for the natural numbers}}
In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms ({{IPAc-en|p|i|ˈ|ɑː|n|oʊ}},[http://www.dictionary.com/browse/peano "Peano"]. Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary. {{IPA|it|peˈaːno|}}), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly unchanged in a number of metamathematical investigations, including research into fundamental questions of whether number theory is consistent and complete.
The axiomatization of arithmetic provided by Peano axioms is commonly called Peano arithmetic.
The importance of formalizing arithmetic was not well appreciated until the work of Hermann Grassmann, who showed in the 1860s that many facts in arithmetic could be derived from more basic facts about the successor operation and induction.{{sfn|Grassmann|1861}}{{sfn|Wang|1957|loc="It is rather well-known, through Peano's own acknowledgement, that Peano […] made extensive use of Grassmann's work in his development of the axioms. It is not so well-known that Grassmann had essentially the characterization of the set of all integers, now customary in texts of modern algebra, that it forms an ordered integral domain in wihich each set of positive elements has a least member. […] [Grassmann's book] was probably the first serious and rather successful attempt to put numbers on a more or less axiomatic basis."|pages=145, 147}} In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided an axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic.{{sfn|Peirce|1881}}{{sfn|Shields|1997}} In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a simplified version of them as a collection of axioms in his book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method ({{langx|la|Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita}}).
The nine Peano axioms contain three types of statements. The first axiom asserts the existence of at least one member of the set of natural numbers. The next four are general statements about equality; in modern treatments these are often not taken as part of the Peano axioms, but rather as axioms of the "underlying logic".{{sfn|Van Heijenoort|1967|page=94}} The next three axioms are first-order statements about natural numbers expressing the fundamental properties of the successor operation. The ninth, final, axiom is a second-order statement of the principle of mathematical induction over the natural numbers, which makes this formulation close to second-order arithmetic. A weaker first-order system is obtained by explicitly adding the addition and multiplication operation symbols and replacing the second-order induction axiom with a first-order axiom schema. The term Peano arithmetic is sometimes used for specifically naming this restricted system.
Historical second-order formulation
{{improve references|date=May 2024}}
When Peano formulated his axioms, the language of mathematical logic was in its infancy. The system of logical notation he created to present the axioms did not prove to be popular, although it was the genesis of the modern notation for set membership (∈, which comes from Peano's ε). Peano maintained a clear distinction between mathematical and logical symbols, which was not yet common in mathematics; such a separation had first been introduced in the Begriffsschrift by Gottlob Frege, published in 1879.{{sfn|Van Heijenoort|1967|page=2}} Peano was unaware of Frege's work and independently recreated his logical apparatus based on the work of Boole and Schröder.{{sfn|Van Heijenoort|1967|page=83}}
The Peano axioms define the arithmetical properties of natural numbers, usually represented as a set N or The non-logical symbols for the axioms consist of a constant symbol 0 and a unary function symbol S.
The first axiom states that the constant 0 is a natural number:
{{ordered list|start=1
| 1= 0 is a natural number.
}}
Peano's original formulation of the axioms used 1 instead of 0 as the "first" natural number,{{sfn|Peano|1889|page=1}} while the axioms in Formulario mathematico include zero.{{sfn|Peano|1908|page=27}}
The next four axioms describe the equality relation. Since they are logically valid in first-order logic with equality, they are not considered to be part of "the Peano axioms" in modern treatments.{{sfn|Van Heijenoort|1967|page=83}}
{{ordered list|start=2
| 2= For every natural number x, {{nowrap|1=x = x}}. That is, equality is reflexive.
| 3= For all natural numbers x and y, if {{nowrap|1=x = y}}, then {{nowrap|1=y = x}}. That is, equality is symmetric.
| 4= For all natural numbers x, y and z, if x = y and y = z, then {{nowrap|1=x = z}}. That is, equality is transitive.
| 5= For all a and b, if b is a natural number and {{nowrap|1=a = b}}, then a is also a natural number. That is, the natural numbers are closed under equality.
}}
The remaining axioms define the arithmetical properties of the natural numbers. The naturals are assumed to be closed under a single-valued "successor" function S.
{{ordered list
| start = 6|
| 6 = For every natural number n, S(n) is a natural number. That is, the natural numbers are closed under S.
| 7 = For all natural numbers m and n, if {{nowrap|1=S(m) = S(n)}}, then {{nowrap|1=m = n}}. That is, S is an injection.
| 8 = For every natural number n, {{nowrap|1=S(n) = 0}} is false. That is, there is no natural number whose successor is 0.
}}
File:Domino effect visualizing exclusion of junk term by induction axiom.jpgGerardo con Diaz, [http://www.math.harvard.edu/archive/23a_fall_05/Handouts/induction.pdf Mathematical Induction] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130502163438/http://www.math.harvard.edu/archive/23a_fall_05/Handouts/induction.pdf |date=2 May 2013 }}, Harvard University However, axioms 1–8 are {{em|also}} satisfied by the set of all dominoes—whether light or dark—taken together.The non-contiguous set satisfies axiom 1 as it has a 0 element, 2–5 as it doesn't affect equality relations, 6 as all pieces have a successor, axiom 7 as no two dominos topple, or are toppled by, the same piece, and axiom 8 as every domino bar the first light domino is toppled by another domino. The 9th axiom (induction) limits N to the chain of light pieces ("no junk") as only light dominoes will fall when the nearest is toppled.
{{sfn|Meseguer|Goguen|1986|loc=sections 2.3 (p. 464) and 4.1 (p. 471)}}]]
Axioms 1, 6, 7, 8 define a unary representation of the intuitive notion of natural numbers: the number 1 can be defined as S(0), 2 as S(S(0)), etc. However, considering the notion of natural numbers as being defined by these axioms, axioms 1, 6, 7, 8 do not imply that the successor function generates all the natural numbers different from 0.
The intuitive notion that each natural number can be obtained by applying successor sufficiently many times to zero requires an additional axiom, which is sometimes called the axiom of induction.
{{ordered list|start=9
| 9=If K is a set such that:
- 0 is in K, and
- for every natural number n, n being in K implies that S(n) is in K,
then K contains every natural number.
}}
The induction axiom is sometimes stated in the following form:
{{ordered list|start=9
| 9=If φ is a unary predicate such that:
- φ(0) is true, and
- for every natural number n, φ(n) being true implies that φ(S(n)) is true,
then φ(n) is true for every natural number n.
}}
In Peano's original formulation, the induction axiom is a second-order axiom. It is now common to replace this second-order principle with a weaker first-order induction scheme. There are important differences between the second-order and first-order formulations, as discussed in the section {{section link||Peano arithmetic as first-order theory}} below.
= Defining arithmetic operations and relations =
If we use the second-order induction axiom, it is possible to define addition, multiplication, and total (linear) ordering on N directly using the axioms. However, {{Citation needed span|text=with first-order induction, this is not possible|date=January 2022}} and addition and multiplication are often added as axioms. The respective functions and relations are constructed in set theory or second-order logic, and can be shown to be unique using the Peano axioms.
== Addition ==
Addition is a function that maps two natural numbers (two elements of N) to another one. It is defined recursively as:
:
a + 0 &= a , & \textrm{(1)}\\
a + S (b) &= S (a + b). & \textrm{(2)}
\end{align}
For example:
:
a + 1 &= a + S(0) & \mbox{by definition} \\
&= S(a + 0) & \mbox{using (2)} \\
&= S(a), & \mbox{using (1)} \\
\\
a + 2 &= a + S(1) & \mbox{by definition} \\
&= S(a + 1) & \mbox{using (2)} \\
&= S(S(a)) & \mbox{using } a + 1 = S(a) \\
\\
a + 3 &= a + S(2) & \mbox{by definition} \\
&= S(a + 2) & \mbox{using (2)} \\
&= S(S(S(a))) & \mbox{using } a + 2 = S(S(a)) \\
\text{etc.} & \\
\end{align}
To prove commutativity of addition, first prove and , each by induction on . Using both results, then prove by induction on .
The structure {{nowrap|(N, +)}} is a commutative monoid with identity element 0. {{nowrap|(N, +)}} is also a cancellative magma, and thus embeddable in a group. The smallest group embedding N is the integers.{{cn|date=May 2024}}
== Multiplication ==
Similarly, multiplication is a function mapping two natural numbers to another one. Given addition, it is defined recursively as:
:
a \cdot 0 &= 0, \\
a \cdot S (b) &= a + (a \cdot b).
\end{align}
It is easy to see that is the multiplicative right identity:
:
To show that is also the multiplicative left identity requires the induction axiom due to the way multiplication is defined:
- is the left identity of 0: .
- If is the left identity of (that is ), then is also the left identity of : , using commutativity of addition.
Therefore, by the induction axiom is the multiplicative left identity of all natural numbers. Moreover, it can be shownFor formal proofs, see e.g. :File:Inductive proofs of properties of add, mult from recursive definitions.pdf. that multiplication is commutative and distributes over addition:
: .
Thus, is a commutative semiring.
== Inequalities ==
The usual total order relation ≤ on natural numbers can be defined as follows, assuming 0 is a natural number:
: For all {{nowrap|a, b ∈ N}}, {{nowrap|a ≤ b}} if and only if there exists some {{nowrap|c ∈ N}} such that {{nowrap|1=a + c = b}}.
This relation is stable under addition and multiplication: for , if {{nowrap|a ≤ b}}, then:
- a + c ≤ b + c, and
- a · c ≤ b · c.
Thus, the structure {{nowrap|(N, +, ·, 1, 0, ≤)}} is an ordered semiring; because there is no natural number between 0 and 1, it is a discrete ordered semiring.
The axiom of induction is sometimes stated in the following form that uses a stronger hypothesis, making use of the order relation "≤":
: For any predicate φ, if
:* φ(0) is true, and
:* for every {{nowrap|n ∈ N}}, if φ(k) is true for every {{nowrap|k ∈ N}} such that {{nowrap|k ≤ n}}, then φ(S(n)) is true,
:* then for every {{nowrap|n ∈ N}}, φ(n) is true.
This form of the induction axiom, called strong induction, is a consequence of the standard formulation, but is often better suited for reasoning about the ≤ order. For example, to show that the naturals are well-ordered—every nonempty subset of N has a least element—one can reason as follows. Let a nonempty {{nowrap|X ⊆ N}} be given and assume X has no least element.
- Because 0 is the least element of N, it must be that {{nowrap|0 ∉ X}}.
- For any {{nowrap|n ∈ N}}, suppose for every {{nowrap|k ≤ n}}, {{nowrap|k ∉ X}}. Then {{nowrap|S(n) ∉ X}}, for otherwise it would be the least element of X.
Thus, by the strong induction principle, for every {{nowrap|n ∈ N}}, {{nowrap|n ∉ X}}. Thus, {{nowrap|1=X ∩ N = ∅}}, which contradicts X being a nonempty subset of N. Thus X has a least element.
= Models =
A model of the Peano axioms is a triple {{nowrap|(N, 0, S)}}, where N is a (necessarily infinite) set, {{nowrap|0 ∈ N}} and {{nowrap|S: N → N}} satisfies the axioms above. Dedekind proved in his 1888 book, The Nature and Meaning of Numbers ({{langx|de|Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?}}, i.e., "What are the numbers and what are they good for?") that any two models of the Peano axioms (including the second-order induction axiom) are isomorphic. In particular, given two models {{nowrap|(NA, 0A, SA)}} and {{nowrap|(NB, 0B, SB)}} of the Peano axioms, there is a unique homomorphism {{nowrap|f : NA → NB}} satisfying
:
f(0_A) &= 0_B \\
f(S_A (n)) &= S_B (f (n))
\end{align}
and it is a bijection. This means that the second-order Peano axioms are categorical. (This is not the case with any first-order reformulation of the Peano axioms, below.)
== Set-theoretic models ==
{{Main|Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers}}
The Peano axioms can be derived from set theoretic constructions of the natural numbers and axioms of set theory such as ZF.{{harvnb|Suppes|1960}}, {{harvnb|Hatcher|2014}} The standard construction of the naturals, due to John von Neumann, starts from a definition of 0 as the empty set, ∅, and an operator s on sets defined as:
:
The set of natural numbers N is defined as the intersection of all sets closed under s that contain the empty set. Each natural number is equal (as a set) to the set of natural numbers less than it:
:
0 &= \emptyset \\
1 &= s(0) = s(\emptyset) = \emptyset \cup \{ \emptyset \} = \{ \emptyset \} = \{ 0 \} \\
2 &= s(1) = s(\{ 0 \}) = \{ 0 \} \cup \{ \{ 0 \} \} = \{ 0 , \{ 0 \} \} = \{ 0, 1 \} \\
3 &= s(2) = s(\{ 0, 1 \}) = \{ 0, 1 \} \cup \{ \{ 0, 1 \} \} = \{ 0, 1, \{ 0, 1 \} \} = \{ 0, 1, 2 \}
\end{align}
and so on. The set N together with 0 and the successor function {{nowrap|s : N → N}} satisfies the Peano axioms.
Peano arithmetic is equiconsistent with several weak systems of set theory.{{sfn|Tarski|Givant|1987|loc=Section 7.6}} One such system is ZFC with the axiom of infinity replaced by its negation. Another such system consists of general set theory (extensionality, existence of the empty set, and the axiom of adjunction), augmented by an axiom schema stating that a property that holds for the empty set and holds of an adjunction whenever it holds of the adjunct must hold for all sets.
== Interpretation in category theory ==
The Peano axioms can also be understood using category theory. Let C be a category with terminal object 1C, and define the category of pointed unary systems, US1(C) as follows:
- The objects of US1(C) are triples {{nowrap|(X, 0X, SX)}} where X is an object of C, and {{nowrap|0X : 1C → X}} and {{nowrap|SX : X → X}} are C-morphisms.
- A morphism φ : (X, 0X, SX) → (Y, 0Y, SY) is a C-morphism {{nowrap|φ : X → Y}} with {{nowrap|1=φ 0X = 0Y}} and {{nowrap|1=φ SX = SY φ}}.
Then C is said to satisfy the Dedekind–Peano axioms if US1(C) has an initial object; this initial object is known as a natural number object in C. If {{nowrap|(N, 0, S)}} is this initial object, and {{nowrap|(X, 0X, SX)}} is any other object, then the unique map {{nowrap|u : (N, 0, S) → (X, 0X, SX)}} is such that
:
u (0) &= 0_X, \\
u (S x) &= S_X (u x).
\end{align}
This is precisely the recursive definition of 0X and SX.
= Consistency =
{{Further|Hilbert's second problem|Consistency}}
When the Peano axioms were first proposed, Bertrand Russell and others agreed that these axioms implicitly defined what we mean by a "natural number".{{harvnb|Fritz|1952|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Yl_XAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA137, p. 137]}}
An illustration of 'interpretation' is Russell's own definition of 'cardinal number'. The uninterpreted system in this case is Peano's axioms for the number system, whose three primitive ideas and five axioms, Peano believed, were sufficient to enable one to derive all the properties of the system of natural numbers. Actually, Russell maintains, Peano's axioms define any progression of the form of which the series of the natural numbers is one instance. Henri Poincaré was more cautious, saying they only defined natural numbers if they were consistent; if there is a proof that starts from just these axioms and derives a contradiction such as 0 = 1, then the axioms are inconsistent, and don't define anything.{{harvnb|Gray|2013|loc=[https://archive.org/details/henripoincaresci0000gray/page/133 p. 133]}}
So Poincaré turned to see whether logicism could generate arithmetic, more precisely, the arithmetic of ordinals. Couturat, said Poincaré, had accepted the Peano axioms as a definition of a number. But this will not do. The axioms cannot be shown to be free of contradiction by finding examples of them, and any attempt to show that they were contradiction-free by examining the totality of their implications would require the very principle of mathematical induction Couturat believed they implied. For (in a further passage dropped from S&M) either one assumed the principle in order to prove it, which would only prove that if it is true it is not self-contradictory, which says nothing; or one used the principle in another form than the one stated, in which case one must show that the number of steps in one's reasoning was an integer according to the new definition, but this could not be done (1905c, 834). In 1900, David Hilbert posed the problem of proving their consistency using only finitistic methods as the second of his twenty-three problems.{{sfn|Hilbert|1902}} In 1931, Kurt Gödel proved his second incompleteness theorem, which shows that such a consistency proof cannot be formalized within Peano arithmetic itself, if Peano arithmetic is consistent.{{sfn|Gödel|1931}}
Although it is widely claimed that Gödel's theorem rules out the possibility of a finitistic consistency proof for Peano arithmetic, this depends on exactly what one means by a finitistic proof. Gödel himself pointed out the possibility of giving a finitistic consistency proof of Peano arithmetic or stronger systems by using finitistic methods that are not formalizable in Peano arithmetic, and in 1958, Gödel published a method for proving the consistency of arithmetic using type theory.{{harvnb|Gödel|1958}} In 1936, Gerhard Gentzen gave a proof of the consistency of Peano's axioms, using transfinite induction up to an ordinal called ε0.{{harvnb|Gentzen|1936}} Gentzen explained: "The aim of the present paper is to prove the consistency of elementary number theory or, rather, to reduce the question of consistency to certain fundamental principles". Gentzen's proof is arguably finitistic, since the transfinite ordinal ε0 can be encoded in terms of finite objects (for example, as a Turing machine describing a suitable order on the integers, or more abstractly as consisting of the finite trees, suitably linearly ordered). Whether or not Gentzen's proof meets the requirements Hilbert envisioned is unclear: there is no generally accepted definition of exactly what is meant by a finitistic proof, and Hilbert himself never gave a precise definition.
The vast majority of contemporary mathematicians believe that Peano's axioms are consistent, relying either on intuition or the acceptance of a consistency proof such as Gentzen's proof. A small number of philosophers and mathematicians, some of whom also advocate ultrafinitism, reject Peano's axioms because accepting the axioms amounts to accepting the infinite collection of natural numbers. In particular, addition (including the successor function) and multiplication are assumed to be total. Curiously, there are self-verifying theories that are similar to PA but have subtraction and division instead of addition and multiplication, which are axiomatized in such a way to avoid proving sentences that correspond to the totality of addition and multiplication, but which are still able to prove all true theorems of PA, and yet can be extended to a consistent theory that proves its own consistency (stated as the non-existence of a Hilbert-style proof of "0=1").{{sfn|Willard|2001}}
Peano arithmetic as first-order theory
All of the Peano axioms except the ninth axiom (the induction axiom) are statements in first-order logic.{{sfn|Partee|Ter Meulen|Wall|2012|page=215}} The arithmetical operations of addition and multiplication and the order relation can also be defined using first-order axioms. The axiom of induction above is second-order, since it quantifies over predicates (equivalently, sets of natural numbers rather than natural numbers). As an alternative one can consider a first-order axiom schema of induction. Such a schema includes one axiom per predicate definable in the first-order language of Peano arithmetic, making it weaker than the second-order axiom.{{sfnp|Harsanyi|1983}} The reason that it is weaker is that the number of predicates in first-order language is countable, whereas the number of sets of natural numbers is uncountable. Thus, there exist sets that cannot be described in first-order language (in fact, most sets have this property).
First-order axiomatizations of Peano arithmetic have another technical limitation. In second-order logic, it is possible to define the addition and multiplication operations from the successor operation, but this cannot be done in the more restrictive setting of first-order logic. Therefore, the addition and multiplication operations are directly included in the signature of Peano arithmetic, and axioms are included that relate the three operations to each other.
The following list of axioms (along with the usual axioms of equality), which contains six of the seven axioms of Robinson arithmetic, is sufficient for this purpose:{{sfn|Mendelson|1997|page=155}}
In addition to this list of numerical axioms, Peano arithmetic contains the induction schema, which consists of a recursively enumerable and even decidable set of axioms. For each formula {{nowrap|φ(x, y1, ..., yk)}} in the language of Peano arithmetic, the first-order induction axiom for φ is the sentence
:
where is an abbreviation for y1,...,yk. The first-order induction schema includes every instance of the first-order induction axiom; that is, it includes the induction axiom for every formula φ.
= Equivalent axiomatizations =
The above axiomatization of Peano arithmetic uses a signature that only has symbols for zero as well as the successor, addition, and multiplications operations. There are many other different, but equivalent, axiomatizations. One such alternative{{sfn|Kaye|1991|pages=16–18}} uses an order relation symbol instead of the successor operation and the language of discretely ordered semirings (axioms 1-7 for semirings, 8-10 on order, 11-13 regarding compatibility, and 14-15 for discreteness):
- , i.e., addition is associative.
- , i.e., addition is commutative.
- , i.e., multiplication is associative.
- , i.e., multiplication is commutative.
- , i.e., multiplication distributes over addition.
- , i.e., zero is an identity for addition, and an absorbing element for multiplication (actually superfluous{{NoteTag|"" can be proven from the other axioms (in first-order logic) as follows. Firstly, by distributivity and additive identity. Secondly, by Axiom 15. If then by addition of the same element and commutativity, and hence by substitution, contradicting irreflexivity. Therefore it must be that .}}).
- , i.e., one is an identity for multiplication.
- , i.e., the '<' operator is transitive.
- , i.e., the '<' operator is irreflexive.
- , i.e., the ordering satisfies trichotomy.
- , i.e. the ordering is preserved under addition of the same element.
- , i.e. the ordering is preserved under multiplication by the same positive element.
- , i.e. given any two distinct elements, the larger is the smaller plus another element.
- , i.e. zero and one are distinct and there is no element between them. In other words, 0 is covered by 1, which suggests that these numbers are discrete.
- , i.e. zero is the minimum element.
The theory defined by these axioms is known as PA−. It is also incomplete and one of its important properties is that any structure satisfying this theory has an initial segment (ordered by ) isomorphic to . Elements in that segment are called standard elements, while other elements are called nonstandard elements.
Finally, Peano arithmetic PA is obtained by adding the first-order induction schema.
= Undecidability and incompleteness =
According to Gödel's incompleteness theorems, the theory of PA (if consistent) is incomplete. Consequently, there are sentences of first-order logic (FOL) that are true in the standard model of PA but are not a consequence of the FOL axiomatization. Essential incompleteness already arises for theories with weaker axioms, such as Robinson arithmetic.
Closely related to the above incompleteness result (via Gödel's completeness theorem for FOL) it follows that there is no algorithm for deciding whether a given FOL sentence is a consequence of a first-order axiomatization of Peano arithmetic or not. Hence, PA is an example of an undecidable theory. Undecidability arises already for the existential sentences of PA, due to the negative answer to Hilbert's tenth problem, whose proof implies that all computably enumerable sets are diophantine sets, and thus definable by existentially quantified formulas (with free variables) of PA. Formulas of PA with higher quantifier rank (more quantifier alternations) than existential formulas are more expressive, and define sets in the higher levels of the arithmetical hierarchy.
= Nonstandard models =
{{Main|Non-standard model of arithmetic}}
Although the usual natural numbers satisfy the axioms of PA, there are other models as well (called "non-standard models"); the compactness theorem implies that the existence of nonstandard elements cannot be excluded in first-order logic.{{sfn|Hermes|1973|loc=VI.4.3|ps=, presenting a theorem of Thoralf Skolem}} The upward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem shows that there are nonstandard models of PA of all infinite cardinalities. This is not the case for the original (second-order) Peano axioms, which have only one model, up to isomorphism.{{sfn|Hermes|1973|loc=VI.3.1}} This illustrates one way the first-order system PA is weaker than the second-order Peano axioms.
When interpreted as a proof within a first-order set theory, such as ZFC, Dedekind's categoricity proof for PA shows that each model of set theory has a unique model of the Peano axioms, up to isomorphism, that embeds as an initial segment of all other models of PA contained within that model of set theory. In the standard model of set theory, this smallest model of PA is the standard model of PA; however, in a nonstandard model of set theory, it may be a nonstandard model of PA. This situation cannot be avoided with any first-order formalization of set theory.
It is natural to ask whether a countable nonstandard model can be explicitly constructed. The answer is affirmative as Skolem in 1933 provided an explicit construction of such a nonstandard model. On the other hand, Tennenbaum's theorem, proved in 1959, shows that there is no countable nonstandard model of PA in which either the addition or multiplication operation is computable.{{sfn|Kaye|1991|loc=Section 11.3}} This result shows it is difficult to be completely explicit in describing the addition and multiplication operations of a countable nonstandard model of PA. There is only one possible order type of a countable nonstandard model. Letting ω be the order type of the natural numbers, ζ be the order type of the integers, and η be the order type of the rationals, the order type of any countable nonstandard model of PA is {{nowrap|ω + ζ·η}}, which can be visualized as a copy of the natural numbers followed by a dense linear ordering of copies of the integers.
== Overspill ==
A cut in a nonstandard model M is a nonempty subset C of M so that C is downward closed (x < y and y ∈ C ⇒ x ∈ C) and C is closed under successor. A proper cut is a cut that is a proper subset of M. Each nonstandard model has many proper cuts, including one that corresponds to the standard natural numbers. However, the induction scheme in Peano arithmetic prevents any proper cut from being definable. The overspill lemma, first proved by Abraham Robinson, formalizes this fact.
{{math theorem|name=Overspill lemma{{sfn|Kaye|1991|pages=70ff.}}|math_statement= Let M be a nonstandard model of PA and let C be a proper cut of M. Suppose that is a tuple of elements of M and is a formula in the language of arithmetic so that
: for all b ∈ C.
Then there is a c in M that is greater than every element of C such that
:
}}
See also
Notes
{{NoteFoot}}
References
= Citations =
{{Reflist}}
= Sources =
{{refbegin}}
- {{cite book
|last= Davis
|first= Martin
|author-link= Martin Davis (mathematician)
|year= 1974
|title= Computability. Notes by Barry Jacobs.
|publisher= Courant Institute of Mathematical Sciences, New York University
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Dedekind
|first= Richard
|author-link= Richard Dedekind
|year= 1888
|title= Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?
|trans-title= What are and what should the numbers be?
|publisher= Vieweg
|url= http://digisrv-1.biblio.etc.tu-bs.de:8080/docportal/servlets/MCRFileNodeServlet/DocPortal_derivate_00005731/V.C.125.pdf
|access-date= 4 July 2016
|archive-date= 20 October 2016
|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20161020135148/http://digisrv-1.biblio.etc.tu-bs.de:8080/docportal/servlets/MCRFileNodeServlet/DocPortal_derivate_00005731/V.C.125.pdf
|url-status= dead
}}
- Two English translations:
- {{cite book
|last= Beman
|first= Wooster, Woodruff
|year= 1901
|title= Essays on the Theory of Numbers
|publisher= Dover Publications
|url= http://www.gutenberg.org/files/21016/21016-pdf.pdf
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Ewald
|first= William B.
|year= 1996
|title= From Kant to Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics
|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=Nt_uAAAAMAAJ
|publisher= Oxford University Press
|pages= 787–832
|isbn= 978-0-19-853271-2
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Fritz
|first= Charles A. Jr.
|year= 1952
|title= Bertrand Russell's construction of the external world
|publisher= New York, Humanities Press
|url= https://archive.org/details/bertrandrussells0000frit
|url-access= registration
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Gentzen
|first= Gerhard
|author-link= Gerhard Gentzen
|year= 1936
|title= Die Widerspruchsfreiheit der reinen Zahlentheorie
|journal= Mathematische Annalen
|volume= 112
|pages= 132–213
|doi= 10.1007/bf01565428
|others= Reprinted in English translation in his 1969 Collected works, M. E. Szabo, ed.
|s2cid= 122719892
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Gödel
|first= Kurt
|author-link= Kurt Gödel
|year= 1931
|title= Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, I
|journal= Monatshefte für Mathematik
|volume= 38
|pages= 173–198
|url= http://www.w-k-essler.de/pdfs/goedel.pdf
|doi= 10.1007/bf01700692
|others= See On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems for details on English translations.
|s2cid= 197663120
|access-date= 2013-10-31
|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20180411113347/http://www.w-k-essler.de/pdfs/goedel.pdf
|archive-date= 2018-04-11
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Gödel
|first= Kurt
|year= 1958
|author-link= Kurt Gödel
|title= Über eine bisher noch nicht benützte Erweiterung des finiten Standpunktes
|journal= Dialectica
|volume= 12
|pages= 280–287
|others= Reprinted in English translation in 1990. Gödel's Collected Works, Vol II. Solomon Feferman et al., eds.
|issue= 3–4
|publisher= Oxford University Press
|doi= 10.1111/j.1746-8361.1958.tb01464.x
|doi-access= free
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Grassmann
|first= Hermann Günther
|author-link= Hermann Grassmann
|year= 1861
|title= Lehrbuch der Arithmetik für höhere Lehranstalten
|publisher= Verlag von Theod. Chr. Fr. Enslin
|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=jdQ2AAAAMAAJ
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Gray
|first= Jeremy
|author-link= Jeremy Gray
|year= 2013
|title= Henri Poincaré: A scientific biography
|chapter= The Essayist
|chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=w2Tya9gOKqEC&pg=PA133
|page= 133
|publisher= Princeton University Press
|isbn= 978-0-691-15271-4
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Harsanyi
|first= John C.
|author-link= John C. Harsanyi
|year= 1983
|title= Methodology, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science
|chapter= Mathematics, the Empirical Facts, and Logical Necessity
|editor1-last= Hempel
|editor1-first= Carl G.
|editor2-last= Putnam
|editor2-first= Hilary
|editor3-last= Essler
|editor3-first= Wilhelm K.
|pages= 167–192
|doi= 10.1007/978-94-015-7676-5_8
|isbn= 978-90-481-8389-0
|s2cid= 121297669
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Hatcher
|first= William S.
|date= 2014
|orig-date= 1982
|title= The Logical Foundations of Mathematics
|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=wf3iBQAAQBAJ&pg=PP1
|publisher= Elsevier
|isbn= 978-1-4831-8963-5
}} Derives the Peano axioms (called S) from several axiomatic set theories and from category theory.
- {{cite book
|last= Hermes
|first= Hans
|year= 1973
|issn= 1431-4657
|isbn= 3-540-05819-2
|title= Introduction to Mathematical Logic
|publisher= Springer
|series= Hochschultext
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Hilbert
|first= David
|year= 1902
|title= Mathematische Probleme
|trans-title= Mathematical Problems
|journal= Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society
|volume= 8
|issue= 10
|pages= 437–479
|url= https://www.ams.org/journals/bull/1902-08-10/S0002-9904-1902-00923-3/home.html
|translator-first= Maby
|translator-last= Winton
|doi= 10.1090/s0002-9904-1902-00923-3
|doi-access= free
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Kaye
|first= Richard
|year= 1991
|title= Models of Peano arithmetic
|publisher= Oxford University Press
|isbn= 0-19-853213-X
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Landau
|first= Edmund
|author-link= Edmund Landau
|year= 1965
|title= Grundlagen Der Analysis
|publisher= AMS Chelsea Publishing
|others= Derives the basic number systems from the Peano axioms. English/German vocabulary included.
|isbn= 978-0-8284-0141-8
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Mendelson
|first= Elliott
|author-link= Elliott Mendelson
|date= December 1997
|orig-date=December 1979
|title= Introduction to Mathematical Logic (Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications)
|edition= 4th
|publisher= Springer
|isbn= 978-0-412-80830-2
}}
- {{cite book
|last1= Meseguer
|first1= José
|last2= Goguen
|first2= Joseph A.
|date= Dec 1986
|url= https://courses.engr.illinois.edu/cs576/sp2017/readings/background/initiality-induction-computability.pdf
|contribution= Initiality, induction, and computability
|pages= 459–541
|isbn= 978-0-521-26793-9
|editor= Maurice Nivat and John C. Reynolds
|title= Algebraic Methods in Semantics
|location= Cambridge
|publisher= Cambridge University Press
}}
- {{cite book
|last1= Partee
|first1= Barbara
|last2= Ter Meulen
|first2= Alice
|author2-link= Alice ter Meulen
|last3= Wall
|first3= Robert
|year= 2012
|title= Mathematical Methods in Linguistics
|publisher= Springer
|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=d5xrCQAAQBAJ
|isbn= 978-94-009-2213-6
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Peano
|first= Giuseppe
|author-link= Giuseppe Peano
|year= 1908
|title= Formulario Mathematico
|edition= V
|page= 27
|publisher= Turin, Bocca frères, Ch. Clausen
|url= https://archive.org/details/formulairedemat04peangoog
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Peirce
|first= C. S.
|author-link= Charles Sanders Peirce
|year= 1881
|title= On the Logic of Number
|url= https://archive.org/details/jstor-2369151
|journal= American Journal of Mathematics
|volume= 4
|issue= 1
|pages= 85–95
|doi= 10.2307/2369151
|mr= 1507856
|jstor= 2369151
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Shields
|first= Paul
|year= 1997
|title= Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce
|url= https://archive.org/details/studiesinlogicof00nath
|url-access= registration
|chapter= 3. Peirce's Axiomatization of Arithmetic
|chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=pWjOg-zbtMAC&pg=PA43
|editor1-last= Houser
|editor1-first= Nathan
|editor2-last= Roberts
|editor2-first= Don D.
|editor3-last= Van Evra
|editor3-first= James
|publisher= Indiana University Press
|isbn= 0-253-33020-3
|pages= 43–52
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Suppes
|first= Patrick
|author-link= Patrick Suppes
|year= 1960
|title= Axiomatic Set Theory
|publisher= Dover Publications
|isbn= 0-486-61630-4
|url-access= registration
|url= https://archive.org/details/axiomaticsettheo00supp_0
}} Derives the Peano axioms from ZFC
- {{cite book
|last1= Tarski
|first1= Alfred
|author-link1= Alfred Tarski
|last2= Givant
|first2= Steven
|year= 1987
|title= A Formalization of Set Theory without Variables
|series= AMS Colloquium Publications
|volume= 41
|publisher= American Mathematical Society
|isbn= 978-0-8218-1041-5
|url-access= registration
|url= https://archive.org/details/formalizationofs0000tars
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Van Heijenoort
|first= Jean
|author-link= Jean van Heijenoort
|year= 1967
|title= From Frege to Godel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931
|publisher= Harvard University Press
|isbn= 978-0-674-32449-7
}}
- Contains translations of the following two papers, with valuable commentary:
- {{cite book
|last= Dedekind
|first= Richard
|author-link= Richard Dedekind
|year= 1890
|title= Letter to Keferstein.
|pages= 98–103
|others= On p. 100, he restates and defends his axioms of 1888.
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Peano
|first= Giuseppe
|author-link= Giuseppe Peano
|year= 1889
|title= Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita
|trans-title= The principles of arithmetic, presented by a new method
|pages= 83–97
|url= https://archive.org/details/arithmeticespri00peangoog
|others= An excerpt of the treatise where Peano first presented his axioms, and recursively defined arithmetical operations.
|publisher= Fratres Bocca
}}
- {{cite web
|last= Van Oosten
|first= Jaap
|date= June 1999
|title= Introduction to Peano Arithmetic (Gödel Incompleteness and Nonstandard Models)
|url= https://webspace.science.uu.nl/~ooste110/syllabi/peanomoeder.pdf
|publisher= Utrecht University
|access-date= 2 September 2023
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Wang
|first= Hao
|author-link= Hao Wang (academic)
|date= June 1957
|title= The Axiomatization of Arithmetic
|journal= The Journal of Symbolic Logic
|volume= 22
|issue= 2
|pages= 145–158
|doi= 10.2307/2964176
|publisher= Association for Symbolic Logic
|jstor= 2964176
|s2cid= 26896458
}}
- {{cite journal
|last= Willard
|first= Dan E.
|author-link= Dan Willard
|year= 2001
|doi= 10.2307/2695030
|issue= 2
|journal= The Journal of Symbolic Logic
|mr= 1833464
|pages= 536–596
|title= Self-verifying axiom systems, the incompleteness theorem and related reflection principles
|url= https://www.cs.albany.edu/~dew/m/jsl1.pdf
|volume= 66
|jstor= 2695030
|s2cid= 2822314
|archive-date= 2020-11-09
|access-date= 2018-06-30
|archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20201109033211/http://www.cs.albany.edu/~dew/m/jsl1.pdf
|url-status= dead
}}
{{refend}}
Further reading
- {{cite book
|last= Buss
|first= Samuel R.
|date= 1998
|editor-last= Buss
|editor-first= Samuel R.
|chapter= Chapter II: First-Order Proof Theory of Arithmetic
|title= Handbook of Proof Theory
|publisher= Elsevier Science
|location= New York
|isbn= 978-0-444-89840-1
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Mendelson
|first= Elliott
|author-link= Elliott Mendelson
|date= June 2015
|orig-date= December 1979
|title= Introduction to Mathematical Logic (Discrete Mathematics and Its Applications)
|edition= 6th
|publisher= Chapman and Hall/CRC
|isbn= 978-1-4822-3772-6
}}
- {{cite book
|last= Smullyan
|first= Raymond M.
|author-link= Raymond M. Smullyan
|title= The Gödelian Puzzle Book: Puzzles, Paradoxes and Proofs
|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=xUapAAAAQBAJ
|date= December 2013
|publisher= Dover Publications
|isbn= 978-0-486-49705-1
}}
- {{cite book
|last=Takeuti
|first=Gaisi
|author-link= Gaisi Takeuti
|date=2013
|title=Proof theory
|location=Mineola, New York
|isbn=978-0-486-49073-1
|edition=Second
}}
External links
- {{cite IEP |poincare |title=Henri Poincaré |first=Mauro |last=Murzi}} Includes a discussion of Poincaré's critique of the Peano's axioms.
- {{cite book |first=Karlis |last=Podnieks |chapter=3. First Order Arithmetic |title=What is Mathematics: Gödel's Theorem and Around |date=2015-01-25 |url=https://dspace.lu.lv/dspace/handle/7/5306 |pages=93–121 }}
- {{springer|title=Peano axioms|id=p/p071880}}
- {{MathWorld | urlname=PeanosAxioms | title=Peano's Axioms}}
- {{cite web |url=http://www.math.uwaterloo.ca/~snburris/htdocs/scav/dedek/dedek.html |title=What are numbers, and what is their meaning?: Dedekind |first=Stanley N. |last=Burris |year=2001 |access-date=2007-03-23 |archive-date=2022-10-26 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20221026225838/https://www.math.uwaterloo.ca/~snburris/htdocs/scav/dedek/dedek.html |url-status=dead }} Commentary on Dedekind's work.
{{PlanetMath attribution|urlname=pa|title=PA}}
{{Mathematical logic}}
Category:Formal theories of arithmetic