causality conditions

Causality conditions are classifications of Lorentzian manifolds according to the types of causal structures they admit.

In the study of spacetimes, there exists a hierarchy of causality conditions which are important in proving mathematical theorems about the global structure of such manifolds.

These conditions were collected during the late 1970s.E. Minguzzi and M. Sanchez, The causal hierarchy of spacetimes in H. Baum and D. Alekseevsky (eds.), vol. Recent developments in pseudo-Riemannian geometry, ESI Lect. Math. Phys., (Eur. Math. Soc. Publ. House, Zurich, 2008), pp. 299–358, {{ISBN|978-3-03719-051-7}}, arXiv:gr-qc/0609119

The weaker the causality condition on a spacetime, the more unphysical the spacetime is. Spacetimes with closed timelike curves, for example, present severe interpretational difficulties. See the grandfather paradox.

It is reasonable to believe that any physical spacetime will satisfy the strongest causality condition: global hyperbolicity. For such spacetimes the equations in general relativity can be posed as an initial value problem on a Cauchy surface.

The hierarchy

There is a hierarchy of causality conditions, each one of which is strictly stronger than the previous. This is sometimes called the causal ladder. The conditions, from weakest to strongest, are:

  • Non-totally vicious
  • Chronological
  • Causal
  • Distinguishing
  • Strongly causal
  • Stably causal
  • Causally continuous
  • Causally simple
  • Globally hyperbolic

Given are the definitions of these causality conditions for a Lorentzian manifold (M,g). Where two or more are given they are equivalent.

Notation:

(See causal structure for definitions of \,I^+(x), \,I^-(x) and \,J^+(x), \,J^-(x).)

Non-totally vicious

  • For some points p \in M we have p \not\ll p.

Chronological

Causal

  • There are no closed causal (non-spacelike) curves.
  • If both p \prec q and q \prec p then p = q

Distinguishing

= Past-distinguishing =

  • Two points p, q \in M which share the same chronological past are the same point:

:: I^-(p) = I^-(q) \implies p = q

  • Equivalently, for any neighborhood U of p \in M there exists a neighborhood V \subset U, p \in V such that no past-directed non-spacelike curve from p intersects V more than once.

= Future-distinguishing =

  • Two points p, q \in M which share the same chronological future are the same point:

:: I^+(p) = I^+(q) \implies p = q

  • Equivalently, for any neighborhood U of p \in M there exists a neighborhood V \subset U, p \in V such that no future-directed non-spacelike curve from p intersects V more than once.

Strongly causal

  • For every neighborhood U of p \in M there exists a neighborhood V \subset U, p \in V through which no timelike curve passes more than once.
  • For every neighborhood U of p \in M there exists a neighborhood V \subset U, p \in V that is causally convex in M (and thus in U).
  • The Alexandrov topology agrees with the manifold topology.

Stably causal

For each of the weaker causality conditions defined above, there are some manifolds satisfying the condition which can be made to violate it by arbitrarily small perturbations of the metric. A spacetime is stably causal if it cannot be made to contain closed causal curves by any perturbation smaller than some arbitrary finite magnitude. Stephen Hawking showedS.W. Hawking, [https://www.jstor.org/stable/2416157 The existence of cosmic time functions] Proc. R. Soc. Lond. (1969), A308, 433 that this is equivalent to:

  • There exists a global time function on M. This is a scalar field t on M whose gradient \nabla^a t is everywhere timelike and future-directed. This global time function gives us a stable way to distinguish between future and past for each point of the spacetime (and so we have no causal violations).

Globally hyperbolic

{{Main|Globally hyperbolic manifold}}

Robert Geroch showedR. Geroch, [http://link.aip.org/link/?JMAPAQ/11/437/1 Domain of Dependence] {{webarchive|url=https://archive.today/20130224130421/http://link.aip.org/link/?JMAPAQ/11/437/1 |date=2013-02-24 }} J. Math. Phys. (1970) 11, 437–449 that a spacetime is globally hyperbolic if and only if there exists a Cauchy surface for M. This means that:

  • M is topologically equivalent to \mathbb{R} \times\!\, S for some Cauchy surface S. (Here \mathbb{R} denotes the real line).

See also

References

  • {{cite book | author=S.W. Hawking, G.F.R. Ellis | title=The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time | location=Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1973 | isbn=0-521-20016-4| title-link=The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time }}
  • {{cite book | author = S.W. Hawking, W. Israel | title = General Relativity, an Einstein Centenary Survey| publisher = Cambridge University Press | year =1979 | isbn=0-521-22285-0| title-link = General Relativity, an Einstein Centenary Survey}}

Category:Lorentzian manifolds

Category:Theory of relativity

Category:General relativity

Category:Theoretical physics