Beauty
{{short description|Characteristic that provides pleasure or satisfaction}}
{{other uses}}
{{pp|small=yes}}
{{Use mdy dates|date=June 2012}}
File:Rozeta_Paryż_notre-dame_chalger.jpg style rose window in Notre-Dame de Paris. In Gothic architecture, light was considered "the source and actual essence of all that is beautiful".Stegers, Rudolf (2008). [https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=GSujjKW04A4C Sacred Buildings: A Design Manual] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20241212131245/https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=GSujjKW04A4C |date=December 12, 2024 }}. Berlin: De Gruyter. p. 60. {{ISBN|3764382767}}.]]
Beauty is commonly described as a feature of objects that makes them pleasurable to perceive. Such objects include landscapes, sunsets, humans and works of art. Beauty, art and taste are the main subjects of aesthetics, one of the fields of study within philosophy. As a positive aesthetic value, it is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart.
One difficulty in understanding beauty is that it has both objective and subjective aspects: it is seen as a property of things but also as depending on the emotional response of observers. Because of its subjective side, beauty is said to be "in the eye of the beholder".{{cite web|url=http://www.phrases.org.uk/meanings/59100.html|title=Beauty is in the eye of the beholder|access-date=December 4, 2007|publisher=The Phrase Finder|year=2007|author=Gary Martin| archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20071130023507/http://www.phrases.org.uk/meanings/59100.html| archive-date= November 30, 2007 | url-status= live}} It has been argued that the ability on the side of the subject needed to perceive and judge beauty, sometimes referred to as the "sense of taste", can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run. This suggests the standards of validity of judgments of beauty are intersubjective, i.e. dependent on a group of judges, rather than fully subjective or objective.
Conceptions of beauty aim to capture what is essential to all beautiful things. Classical conceptions define beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole. Hedonist conceptions see a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause disinterested pleasure. Other conceptions include defining beautiful objects in terms of their value, of a loving attitude toward them or of their function.
Overview
Beauty, together with art and taste, is the main subject of aesthetics, one of the major branches of philosophy.{{cite web |title=Aesthetics |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/aesthetics |website=Encyclopedia Britannica |access-date=9 February 2021 |language=en |archive-date=February 28, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220228161617/https://www.britannica.com/topic/aesthetics |url-status=live }} Beauty is usually categorized as an aesthetic property besides other properties, like grace, elegance or the sublime.{{cite book |last1=Levinson |first1=Jerrold |title=The Oxford Handbook of Aesthetics |date=2003 |publisher=Oxford University Press |pages=3–24 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/LEVPAA-3 |chapter=Philosophical Aesthetics: An Overview |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210210170443/https://philpapers.org/rec/LEVPAA-3 |url-status=live }} As a positive aesthetic value, beauty is contrasted with ugliness as its negative counterpart. Beauty is often listed as one of the three fundamental concepts of human understanding besides truth and goodness.{{cite web |title=Beauty and Ugliness |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/beauty-and-ugliness |website=Encyclopedia.com |access-date=9 February 2021 |archive-date=December 24, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211224063952/https://www.encyclopedia.com/history/dictionaries-thesauruses-pictures-and-press-releases/beauty-and-ugliness |url-status=live }}{{cite journal |last1=Kriegel |first1=Uriah |title=The Value of Consciousness |journal=Analysis |date=2019 |volume=79 |issue=3 |pages=503–520 |doi=10.1093/analys/anz045 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITVO-6 |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=January 11, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220111180343/https://philpapers.org/rec/KRITVO-6 |url-status=live |issn=0003-2638}}{{cite web |title=Beauty in Aesthetics |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/religion/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/beauty-aesthetics |website=Encyclopedia.com |access-date=9 February 2021 |archive-date=January 13, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220113093113/https://www.encyclopedia.com/religion/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/beauty-aesthetics |url-status=live }}
Objectivists or realists see beauty as an objective or mind-independent feature of beautiful things, which is denied by subjectivists. The source of this debate is that judgments of beauty seem to be based on subjective grounds, namely our feelings, while claiming universal correctness at the same time. This tension is sometimes referred to as the "antinomy of taste". Adherents of both sides have suggested that a certain faculty, commonly called a sense of taste, is necessary for making reliable judgments about beauty.{{cite book |last1=Zangwill |first1=Nick |editor1-first=Jerrold |editor1-last=Levinson |title=Oxford Handbook to Aesthetics |date=2003 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=https://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199279456-e-18 |chapter=Beauty |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.003.0018 |access-date=February 16, 2021 |archive-date=January 11, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220111214528/https://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199279456.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199279456-e-18 |url-status=live }} David Hume, for example, suggests that this faculty can be trained and that the verdicts of experts coincide in the long run.
Beauty is mainly discussed in relation to concrete objects accessible to sensory perception. It has been suggested that the beauty of a thing supervenes on the sensory features of this thing. It has also been proposed that abstract objects like stories or mathematical proofs can be beautiful. Beauty plays a central role in works of art and nature.
An influential distinction among beautiful things, according to Immanuel Kant, is that between adherent beauty (pulchritudo adhaerens)Translated in Zangwill as dependent beauty and free beauty (pulchritudo vaga). A thing has adherent beauty if its beauty depends on the conception or function of this thing, unlike free or absolute beauty. Examples of adherent beauty include an ox which is beautiful as an ox but not beautiful as a horse{{cite web |last1=Sartwell |first1=Crispin |title=Beauty |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |date=2017 |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 26, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220226100643/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/ |url-status=live }} or a photograph which is beautiful, because it depicts a beautiful building but that lacks beauty generally speaking because of its low quality.{{cite book |last1=De Clercq |first1=Rafael |title=The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics |publisher=Routledge |date=2013 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/GAUTRC-4 |chapter=Beauty |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=January 13, 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220113095319/https://philpapers.org/rec/GAUTRC-4 |url-status=live }}
Objectivism and subjectivism
{{Further information|Objectivity (philosophy)|subjectivity|label1=objectivity}}
Judgments of beauty seem to occupy an intermediary position between objective judgments, e.g. concerning the mass and shape of a grapefruit, and subjective likes, e.g. concerning whether the grapefruit tastes good.{{cite book |last1=Honderich |first1=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |chapter=Aesthetic judgment |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=January 29, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210129082636/https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |url-status=live }} Judgments of beauty differ from the former because they are based on subjective feelings rather than objective perception. But they also differ from the latter because they lay claim on universal correctness. This tension is also reflected in common language. On the one hand, we talk about beauty as an objective feature of the world that is ascribed, for example, to landscapes, paintings or humans.{{cite book |last1=Scruton |first1=Roger |title=Beauty: A Very Short Introduction |year=2011 |publisher=Oxford University Press |page=5 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/SCRBAV |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=March 10, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210310091105/https://philpapers.org/rec/SCRBAV |url-status=live }} The subjective side, on the other hand, is expressed in sayings like "beauty is in the eye of the beholder".
These two positions are often referred to as objectivism (or realism) and subjectivism. Objectivism is the traditional view, while subjectivism developed more recently in western philosophy. Objectivists hold that beauty is a mind-independent feature of things. On this account, the beauty of a landscape is independent of who perceives it or whether it is perceived at all. Disagreements may be explained by an inability to perceive this feature, sometimes referred to as a "lack of taste".{{cite journal |last1=Rogerson |first1=Kenneth F. |title=The Meaning of Universal Validity in Kant's Aesthetics |journal=The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism |date=1982 |volume=40 |issue=3 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/429687 |page=304 |doi=10.2307/429687 |jstor=429687 |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210210141158/https://www.jstor.org/stable/429687 |url-status=live |url-access=subscription }} Subjectivism, on the other hand, denies the mind-independent existence of beauty. Influential for the development of this position was John Locke's distinction between primary qualities, which the object has independent of the observer, and secondary qualities, which constitute powers in the object to produce certain ideas in the observer.{{cite web |last1=Uzgalis |first1=William |title=John Locke |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=9 February 2021 |date=2020 |archive-date=April 24, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210424195227/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/locke/ |url-status=live }} When applied to beauty, there is still a sense in which it depends on the object and its powers. But this account makes the possibility of genuine disagreements about claims of beauty implausible, since the same object may produce very different ideas in distinct observers. The notion of "taste" can still be used to explain why different people disagree about what is beautiful, but there is no objectively right or wrong taste, there are just different tastes.
The problem with both the objectivist and the subjectivist position in their extreme form is that each has to deny some intuitions about beauty. This issue is sometimes discussed under the label "antinomy of taste". It has prompted various philosophers to seek a unified theory that can take all these intuitions into account. One promising route to solve this problem is to move from subjective to intersubjective theories, which hold that the standards of validity of judgments of taste are intersubjective or dependent on a group of judges rather than objective. This approach tries to explain how genuine disagreement about beauty is possible despite the fact that beauty is a mind-dependent property, dependent not on an individual but a group. A closely related theory sees beauty as a secondary or response-dependent property. On one such account, an object is beautiful "if it causes pleasure by virtue of its aesthetic properties". The problem that different people respond differently can be addressed by combining response-dependence theories with so-called ideal-observer theories: it only matters how an ideal observer would respond. There is no general agreement on how "ideal observers" are to be defined, but it is usually assumed that they are experienced judges of beauty with a fully developed sense of taste. This suggests an indirect way of solving the antinomy of taste: instead of looking for necessary and sufficient conditions of beauty itself, one can learn to identify the qualities of good critics and rely on their judgments. This approach only works if unanimity among experts was ensured. But even experienced judges may disagree in their judgments, which threatens to undermine ideal-observer theories.
Conceptions
= Classical =
File:Analysis of Beauty Plate 1 by William Hogarth.jpg, William Hogarth depicts the effect of changing proportions and attempts to define what proportions are beautiful.]]
The "classical conception" (see Classicism) defines beauty in terms of the relation between the beautiful object as a whole and its parts: the parts should stand in the right proportion to each other and thus compose an integrated harmonious whole. On this account, which found its most explicit articulation in the Italian Renaissance, the beauty of a human body, for example, depends, among other things, on the right proportion of the different parts of the body and on the overall symmetry. One problem with this conception is that it is difficult to give a general and detailed description of what is meant by "harmony between parts" and raises the suspicion that defining beauty through harmony results in exchanging one unclear term for another one. Some attempts have been made to dissolve this suspicion by searching for laws of beauty, like the golden ratio.
18th century philosopher Alexander Baumgarten, for example, saw laws of beauty in analogy with laws of nature and believed that they could be discovered through empirical research. As of 2003, these attempts have failed to find a general definition of beauty and several authors take the opposite claim that such laws cannot be formulated, as part of their definition of beauty.
= Hedonism =
{{Main|Hedonism}}
A very common element in many conceptions of beauty is its relation to pleasure.{{cite journal |last1=De Clercq |first1=Rafael |title=Aesthetic Pleasure Explained |journal=Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism |date=2019 |volume=77 |issue=2 |pages=121–132 |doi=10.1111/jaac.12636 |doi-access=free }} Hedonism makes this relation part of the definition of beauty by holding that there is a necessary connection between pleasure and beauty, e.g. that for an object to be beautiful is for it to cause pleasure or that the experience of beauty is always accompanied by pleasure.{{cite journal |last1=Gorodeisky |first1=Keren |title=On Liking Aesthetic Value |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |date=2019 |volume=102 |issue=2 |pages=261–280 |doi=10.1111/phpr.12641 |s2cid=204522523 }} This account is sometimes labeled as "aesthetic hedonism" in order to distinguish it from other forms of hedonism.{{cite journal |last1=Berg |first1=Servaas Van der |title=Aesthetic Hedonism and Its Critics |journal=Philosophy Compass |date=2020 |volume=15 |issue=1 |pages=e12645 |doi=10.1111/phc3.12645 |s2cid=213973255 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/VANAHA |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 11, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210211034801/https://philpapers.org/rec/VANAHA |url-status=live }}{{cite web |last1=Matthen |first1=Mohan |last2=Weinstein |first2=Zachary |title=Aesthetic Hedonism |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0223.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |access-date=10 February 2021 |language=en |archive-date=January 18, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210118012154/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0223.xml |url-status=live }} An influential articulation of this position comes from Thomas Aquinas, who treats beauty as "that which pleases in the very apprehension of it".{{cite book |last1=Honderich |first1=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |chapter=Beauty |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=January 29, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210129082636/https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |url-status=live }} Immanuel Kant explains this pleasure through a harmonious interplay between the faculties of understanding and imagination. A further question for hedonists is how to explain the relation between beauty and pleasure. This problem is akin to the Euthyphro dilemma: is something beautiful because we enjoy it or do we enjoy it because it is beautiful? Identity theorists solve this problem by denying that there is a difference between beauty and pleasure: they identify beauty, or the appearance of it, with the experience of aesthetic pleasure.
Hedonists usually restrict and specify the notion of pleasure in various ways in order to avoid obvious counterexamples. One important distinction in this context is the difference between pure and mixed pleasure. Pure pleasure excludes any form of pain or unpleasant feeling while the experience of mixed pleasure can include unpleasant elements.{{cite web |last1=Spicher |first1=Michael R. |title=Aesthetic Taste |url=https://iep.utm.edu/a-taste/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 14, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210214142548/https://iep.utm.edu/a-taste/ |url-status=live }} But beauty can involve mixed pleasure, for example, in the case of a beautifully tragic story, which is why mixed pleasure is usually allowed in hedonist conceptions of beauty.
Another problem faced by hedonist theories is that we take pleasure from many things that are not beautiful. One way to address this issue is to associate beauty with a special type of pleasure: aesthetic or disinterested pleasure. A pleasure is disinterested if it is indifferent to the existence of the beautiful object or if it did not arise owing to an antecedent desire through means-end reasoning. For example, the joy of looking at a beautiful landscape would still be valuable if it turned out that this experience was an illusion, which would not be true if this joy was due to seeing the landscape as a valuable real estate opportunity. Opponents of hedonism usually concede that many experiences of beauty are pleasurable but deny that this is true for all cases. For example, a cold jaded critic may still be a good judge of beauty because of her years of experience but lack the joy that initially accompanied her work. One way to avoid this objection is to allow responses to beautiful things to lack pleasure while insisting that all beautiful things merit pleasure, that aesthetic pleasure is the only appropriate response to them.
= Others =
G. E. Moore explained beauty in regard to intrinsic value as "that of which the admiring contemplation is good in itself".{{cite book |last1=Craig |first1=Edward |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=1996 |publisher=Routledge |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/BEAREO |chapter=Beauty |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=January 16, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210116111145/https://philpapers.org/rec/BEAREO |url-status=live }} This definition connects beauty to experience while managing to avoid some of the problems usually associated with subjectivist positions since it allows that things may be beautiful even if they are never experienced.
Another subjectivist theory of beauty comes from George Santayana, who suggested that we project pleasure onto the things we call "beautiful". So in a process akin to a category mistake, one treats one's subjective pleasure as an objective property of the beautiful thing. Other conceptions include defining beauty in terms of a loving or longing attitude toward the beautiful object or in terms of its usefulness or function.{{cite journal |last1=Hansson |first1=Sven Ove |title=Aesthetic Functionalism |journal=Contemporary Aesthetics |date=2005 |volume=3 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/HANAF |access-date=February 10, 2021 |archive-date=February 13, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210213052644/https://philpapers.org/rec/HANAF |url-status=live }} In 1871, functionalist Charles Darwin explained beauty as result of accumulative sexual selection in "The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex".
In philosophy
=Greco-Roman tradition=
file:Helene Paris Louvre K6.jpg mentions Helen of Troy (left) as the most beautiful woman.]]The classical Greek noun that best translates to the English-language words "beauty" or "beautiful" was κάλλος, kallos, and the adjective was καλός, kalos. This is also translated as "good" or "of fine quality" and thus has a broader meaning than mere physical or material beauty. Similarly, kallos was used differently from the English word beauty in that it first and foremost applied to humans and bore an erotic connotation.{{cite book|last1=Konstan|first1=David|title=Beauty - The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea|date=2014|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York|isbn=978-0-19-992726-5|pages=30–35}} The Koine Greek word for beautiful was ὡραῖος, hōraios,Matthew 23:27, Acts 3:10, Flavius Josephus, 12.65 an adjective etymologically coming from the word ὥρα, hōra, meaning "hour". In Koine Greek, beauty was thus associated with "being of one's hour".Euripides, Alcestis 515. Thus, a ripe fruit (of its time) was considered beautiful, whereas a young woman trying to appear older or an older woman trying to appear younger would not be considered beautiful. In Attic Greek, hōraios had many meanings, including "youthful" and "ripe old age". Another classical term in use to describe beauty was pulchrum (Latin).{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iIUYQhu3jkgC&pg=PA7|author=G Parsons|title=Aesthetics and Nature|publisher=A&C Black|year=2008|isbn=978-0826496768|accessdate=2015-05-11|page=7|archive-date=February 3, 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045632/https://books.google.com/books?id=iIUYQhu3jkgC&pg=PA7|url-status=live}}
Beauty for ancient thinkers existed both in form, which is the material world as it is, and as embodied in the spirit, which is the world of mental formations. Greek mythology mentions Helen of Troy as the most beautiful woman.P.T. Struck - [http://www.classics.upenn.edu/myth/php/homer/index.php?page=trojan The Trojan War] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211222140837/http://www.classics.upenn.edu/myth/php/homer/index.php?page=trojan |date=December 22, 2021 }} Classics Department of University of Penn [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 1250> )R Highfield - [https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/science/science-news/3345362/Scientists-calculate-the-exact-date-of-the-Trojan-horse-using-eclipse-in-Homer.html Scientists calculate the exact date of the Trojan horse using eclipse in Homer] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211224062642/https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/science/science-news/3345362/Scientists-calculate-the-exact-date-of-the-Trojan-horse-using-eclipse-in-Homer.html |date=December 24, 2021 }} Telegraph Media Group Limited 24 Jun 2008 [Retrieved 2015-05-12]Bronze Age first source [https://books.google.com/books?id=UtMVAwAAQBAJ&dq=Aegean+Area%2C+2000-1100+BC&pg=PA116 C Freeman - Egypt, Greece, and Rome: Civilizations of the Ancient Mediterranean - p.116] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045632/https://books.google.com/books?id=UtMVAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA116&lpg=PA116&dq=Aegean+Area,+2000-1100+BC&source=bl&ots=e8a-F21hqF&sig=yeNN_IeUTGxRQSD-mJTphLYmQeo&hl=en&sa=X&ei=IgpSVczeEcrB7AajjYHoCw&ved=0CEUQ6AEwBg#v=onepage&q=Aegean%20Area%2C%202000-1100%20BC&f=false |date=February 3, 2023 }}, verified at [https://books.google.com/books?id=EbIVASSe9jcC&q=The+Bronze+Age A. F. Harding - European Societies in the Bronze Age - p.1] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045737/https://books.google.com/books?id=EbIVASSe9jcC&printsec=frontcover&dq=The+Bronze+Age&hl=en&sa=X&ei=lQpSVZjtLaev7AahgoGQBw&ved=0CCYQ6AEwAQ#v=onepage&q=The%20Bronze%20Age&f=false |date=February 3, 2023 }} [Retrieved 2015-05-12][http://classictales.educ.cam.ac.uk/stories/warwithtroy/extras/Sources_for_War_with_Troy.pdf Sources for War with Troy] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151208122159/http://classictales.educ.cam.ac.uk/stories/warwithtroy/extras/Sources_for_War_with_Troy.pdf |date=December 8, 2015 }} Cambridge University Classics Department [Retrieved 2015-05-12]( < 750, 850 > )the most beautiful - [https://books.google.com/books?id=j7tj_XxmLwIC&q=The+Cambridge+History+of+Literary+Criticism%3A+Volume+3%2C+The+Renaissance C.Braider - The Cambridge History of Literary Criticism: Volume 3] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045633/https://books.google.com/books?id=j7tj_XxmLwIC&printsec=frontcover&dq=The+Cambridge+History+of+Literary+Criticism:+Volume+3,+The+Renaissance&hl=en&sa=X&ei=_hBSVZ_MBMaX7QbWoIP4Bw&ved=0CCEQ6AEwAA#v=onepage&q=The%20Cambridge%20History%20of%20Literary%20Criticism%3A%20Volume%203%2C%20The%20Renaissance&f=false |date=February 3, 2023 }}, The Renaissance: Zeuxis portrait (p.174) {{ISBN|0521300088}} - Ed. G.A. Kennedy, G.P. Norton & [https://www.britishmuseum.org/explore/young_explorers/childrens_online_tours/the_trojan_war/helen_runs_off_with_paris.aspx The British Museum - Helen runs off with Paris] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151011155338/http://www.britishmuseum.org/explore/young_explorers/childrens_online_tours/the_trojan_war/helen_runs_off_with_paris.aspx |date=October 11, 2015 }} [Retrieved 2015-05-12] Ancient Greek architecture is based on this view of symmetry and proportion.
==Pre-Socratic==
In one fragment of Heraclitus's writings (Fragment 106) he mentions beauty, this reads: "To God all things are beautiful, good, right..."W.W. Clohesy - [http://kuscholarworks.ku.edu/bitstream/handle/1808/9145/auslegung.v13.n02.175-192.pdf?sequence=1 The Strength of the Invisible: Reflections on Heraclitus (p.177)] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170812213308/https://kuscholarworks.ku.edu/bitstream/handle/1808/9145/auslegung.v13.n02.175-192.pdf?sequence=1 |date=August 12, 2017 }} Auslegung Volume XIII {{ISSN|0733-4311}} [Retrieved 2015-05-12] The earliest Western theory of beauty can be found in the works of early Greek philosophers from the pre-Socratic period, such as Pythagoras, who conceived of beauty as useful for a moral education of the soul. He wrote of how people experience pleasure when aware of a certain type of formal situation present in reality, perceivable by sight or through the ear and discovered the underlying mathematical ratios in the harmonic scales in music. The Pythagoreans conceived of the presence of beauty in universal terms, which is, as existing in a cosmological state, they observed beauty in the heavens.{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LS_ji6fh60IC&pg=PA102|title=History of Aesthetics|editor=J. Harrell|editor2=C. Barrett|editor3=D. Petsch|publisher=A&C Black|year=2006|isbn=0826488552|accessdate=2015-05-11|page=102|archive-date=February 3, 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045633/https://books.google.com/books?id=LS_ji6fh60IC&pg=PA102|url-status=live}} They saw a strong connection between mathematics and beauty. In particular, they noted that objects proportioned according to the golden ratio seemed more attractive.{{cite book|last=Seife |first=Charles |year=2000 |title=Zero: The Biography of a Dangerous Idea |publisher=Penguin |isbn=0-14-029647-6 |page=32}}
==Classical period==
The classical concept of beauty is one that exhibits perfect proportion (Wolfflin).{{cite book|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/#ClaCon|author=Sartwell, C|title=Beauty|publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition)|editor=Edward N. Zalta|accessdate=2015-05-11|archive-date=January 18, 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210118204000/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/beauty/#ClaCon|url-status=live}} In this context, the concept belonged often within the discipline of mathematics. An idea of spiritual beauty emerged during the classical period, beauty was something embodying divine goodness, while the demonstration of behaviour which might be classified as beautiful, from an inner state of morality which is aligned to the good.{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Edi7bg9V3aEC&pg=PA118|author=L Cheney|title=Giorgio Vasari's Teachers: Sacred & Profane Art|publisher=Peter Lang|year=2007|isbn=978-0820488134|accessdate=2015-05-11|page=118|archive-date=February 3, 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045645/https://books.google.com/books?id=Edi7bg9V3aEC&pg=PA118|url-status=live}}
The writing of Xenophon shows a conversation between Socrates and Aristippus. Socrates discerned differences in the conception of the beautiful, for example, in inanimate objects, the effectiveness of execution of design was a deciding factor on the perception of beauty in something. By the account of Xenophon, Socrates found beauty congruent with that to which was defined as the morally good, in short, he thought beauty coincident with the good.N Wilson - [https://books.google.com/books?id=8pXhAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 Encyclopedia of Ancient Greece] (p.20) Routledge, 31 Oct 2013 {{ISBN|113678800X}} [Retrieved 2015-05-12]
Beauty is a subject of Plato in his work Symposium.{{cite book|url=https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23046-the-beautiful-shape-of-the-good-platonic-and-pythagorean-themes-in-kant-s-critique-of-the-power-of-judgment/|author=Fistioc, M.C.|others=Review by S Naragon, Manchester College|title=The Beautiful Shape of the Good: Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgment|date=December 5, 2002 |publisher=Routledge, 2002 (University of Notre Dame philosophy reviews)|accessdate=2015-05-11|archive-date=January 22, 2016|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160122042943/http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23046-the-beautiful-shape-of-the-good-platonic-and-pythagorean-themes-in-kant-s-critique-of-the-power-of-judgment/|url-status=live}} In the work, the high priestess Diotima describes how beauty moves out from a core singular appreciation of the body to outer appreciations via loved ones, to the world in its state of culture and society (Wright). In other words, Diotoma gives to Socrates an explanation of how love should begin with erotic attachment, and end with the transcending of the physical to an appreciation of beauty as a thing in itself. The ascent of love begins with one's own body, then secondarily, in appreciating beauty in another's body, thirdly beauty in the soul, which cognates to beauty in the mind in the modern sense, fourthly beauty in institutions, laws and activities, fifthly beauty in knowledge, the sciences, and finally to lastly love beauty itself, which translates to the original Greek language term as auto to kalon.{{cite book|url=http://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/6/0/4/%7B60490E04-DC57-48DA-9334-9E0B40C03C8D%7DUrstad7.pdf|author=K Urstad|title=Loving Socrates:The Individual and the Ladder of Love in Plato's Symposium|publisher=Res Cogitans 2010 no.7, vol. 1|accessdate=2015-05-11|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151010022315/http://static.sdu.dk/mediafiles/6/0/4/%7B60490E04-DC57-48DA-9334-9E0B40C03C8D%7DUrstad7.pdf|archive-date=2015-10-10|url-status=dead}} In the final state, auto to kalon and truth are united as one. There is the sense in the text, concerning love and beauty they both co-exist but are still independent or, in other words, mutually exclusive, since love does not have beauty since it seeks beauty.{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=T9wWJcRD8tYC&pg=PA75|author=A Preus|title=Notes on Greek Philosophy from Thales to Aristotle (parts 198 and 210)|publisher=Global Academic Publishing |year=1996 |isbn=1883058090 | accessdate=2015-05-12}} The work toward the end provides a description of beauty in a negative sense.
Plato also discusses beauty in his work Phaedrus,{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=K53FQyj44UIC&pg=PA112|author1=W. K. C. Guthrie |author2=J. Warren |title=The Greek Philosophers from Thales to Aristotle (p.112)|publisher=Routledge |year=2012|isbn=978-0415522281|accessdate=2015-05-12}} and identifies Alcibiades as beautiful in Parmenides.{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4C0p-lM0dgQC&pg=PA21|author=S Scolnicov|title=Plato's Parmenides |page=21|publisher=University of California Press |year=2003 |isbn=0520925114|accessdate=2015-05-12}} He considered beauty to be the Idea (Form) above all other Ideas.Phaedrus Platonic thought synthesized beauty with the divine.{{cite book|url=http://commons.pacificu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1094&context=eip|author=J.L. Wright|title=Review of The Beautiful Shape of the Good:Platonic and Pythagorean Themes in Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgment by M.C.Fistioc Volume 4 Issue 2 Medical Research Ethics|publisher=Pacific University Library|accessdate=2015-05-11|archive-date=March 4, 2016|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304093334/http://commons.pacificu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1094&context=eip|url-status=dead}}(ed. 4th paragraph - beauty and the divine) Scruton (cited: Konstan) states Plato states of the idea of beauty, of it (the idea), being something inviting desirousness (cf. seducing), and, promotes an intellectual renunciation (cf. denouncing) of desire.{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iVQgBQAAQBAJ|author=D. Konstan |title=Beauty - The Fortunes of an Ancient Greek Idea|publisher=published by Oxford University Press |year=2014 |isbn=978-0199927265 |accessdate=2015-11-24}} For Alexander Nehamas, it is only the locating of desire to which the sense of beauty exists, in the considerations of Plato.F. McGhee - {{usurped|1=[https://web.archive.org/web/20210310091244/http://www.oxonianreview.org/wp/cold-pastoral/ review of text written by David Konstan]}} published by the Oxonian Review March 31, 2015 [Retrieved 2015-11-24](references not sources: [http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2014/2014-06-08.html Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2014.06.08 (Donald Sells)] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141126032057/http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2014/2014-06-08.html |date=November 26, 2014 }} + [http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001/acprof-9780199605507 DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001 ] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200716084141/https://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199605507.001.0001/acprof-9780199605507 |date=July 16, 2020 }})
Aristotle defines beauty in Metaphysics as having order, symmetry and definiteness which the mathematical sciences exhibit to a special degree. He saw a relationship between the beautiful (to kalon) and virtue, arguing that "Virtue aims at the beautiful."Nicomachean Ethics
==Roman==
In De Natura Deorum, Cicero wrote: "the splendour and beauty of creation", in respect to this, and all the facets of reality resulting from creation, he postulated these to be a reason to see the existence of a God as creator.{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zHyQAgAAQBAJ&q=Empedocles+beauty|author=M Garani|title=Empedocles Redivivus: Poetry and Analogy in Lucretius|publisher=Routledge|year=2007|isbn=978-1135859831|accessdate=2015-05-12|archive-date=February 3, 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045739/https://books.google.com/books?id=zHyQAgAAQBAJ&q=Empedocles+beauty|url-status=live}}
=Western Middle Ages=
In the Middle Ages, Catholic philosophers like Thomas Aquinas included beauty among the transcendental attributes of being.Eco, Umberto (1988). The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Univ. Press. p. 98. {{ISBN|0674006755}}. In his Summa Theologica, Aquinas described the three conditions of beauty as: integritas (wholeness), consonantia (harmony and proportion), and claritas (a radiance and clarity that makes the form of a thing apparent to the mind).McNamara, Denis Robert (2009). Catholic Church Architecture and the Spirit of the Liturgy. Hillenbrand Books. pp. 24–28. {{ISBN|1595250271}}.
In the Gothic Architecture of the High and Late Middle Ages, light was considered the most beautiful revelation of God, which was heralded in design.Stegers, Rudolf (2008). [https://books.google.com/books?id=GSujjKW04A4C&dq=%22light+was+thought+to+be+the+source+and+actual+essence+of+all+that+is+beautiful%22&pg=PA60 Sacred Buildings: A Design Manual]. Berlin: De Gruyter. p. 60. {{ISBN|3764382767}}. Examples are the stained glass of Gothic Cathedrals including Notre-Dame de Paris and Chartres Cathedral.Duiker, William J., and Spielvogel, Jackson J. (2019). World History. United States: Cengage Learning. p. 351. {{ISBN|1337401048}}
St. Augustine said of beauty "Beauty is indeed a good gift of God; but that the good may not think it a great good, God dispenses it even to the wicked."{{cite web|url=http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/npnf102.iv.XV.22.html|title=NPNF1-02. St. Augustine's City of God and Christian Doctrine - Christian Classics Ethereal Library|website=CCEL|access-date=May 1, 2018|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170701195246/http://www.ccel.org/ccel/schaff/npnf102.iv.XV.22.html|archive-date=July 1, 2017|df=mdy-all}}
=Renaissance=
Classical philosophy and sculptures of men and women produced according to the Greek philosophers' tenets of ideal human beauty were rediscovered in Renaissance Europe, leading to a re-adoption of what became known as a "classical ideal". In terms of female human beauty, a woman whose appearance conforms to these tenets is still called a "classical beauty" or said to possess a "classical beauty", whilst the foundations laid by Greek and Roman artists have also supplied the standard for male beauty and female beauty in western civilization as seen, for example, in the Winged Victory of Samothrace. During the Gothic era, the classical aesthetical canon of beauty was rejected as sinful. Later, Renaissance and Humanist thinkers rejected this view, and considered beauty to be the product of rational order and harmonious proportions. Renaissance artists and architects (such as Giorgio Vasari in his "Lives of Artists") criticised the Gothic period as irrational and barbarian. This point of view of Gothic art lasted until Romanticism, in the 19th century. Vasari aligned himself to the classical notion and thought of beauty as defined as arising from proportion and order.
=Age of Reason=
File:Sandro_Botticelli_-_La_nascita_di_Venere_-_Google_Art_Project_-_edited.jpg ({{circa}} 1485) by Sandro Botticelli.{{citation |last=Ames-Lewis |first=Francis |date=2000 |title=The Intellectual Life of the Early Renaissance Artist |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FrcsXlpD6NIC&q=Botticelli+Apelles+Birth+of+Venus&pg=PA194 |location=New Haven, Connecticut |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=0-300-09295-4 |page=194}} The goddess Venus (Aphrodite) is the classical personification of beauty.]]
The Age of Reason saw a rise in an interest in beauty as a philosophical subject. For example, Scottish philosopher Francis Hutcheson argued that beauty is "unity in variety and variety in unity".{{cite book|author=Francis Hutcheson|title=An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XF4uAAAAYAAJ|year=1726|publisher=J. Darby|isbn=9780598982698|access-date=June 14, 2020|archive-date=February 3, 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045639/https://books.google.com/books?id=XF4uAAAAYAAJ|url-status=live}} He wrote that beauty was neither purely subjective nor purely objective—it could be understood not as "any Quality suppos'd to be in the Object, which should of itself be beautiful, without relation to any Mind which perceives it: For Beauty, like other Names of sensible Ideas, properly denotes the Perception of some mind; ... however we generally imagine that there is something in the Object just like our Perception."Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin's Press. p. 421. {{ISBN|0312053916}}.
Immanuel Kant believed that there could be no "universal criterion of the beautiful" and that the experience of beauty is subjective, but that an object is judged to be beautiful when it seems to display "purposiveness"; that is, when its form is perceived to have the character of a thing designed according to some principle and fitted for a purpose.Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin's Press. pp. 482–483. {{ISBN|0312053916}}. He distinguished "free beauty" from "merely adherent beauty", explaining that "the first presupposes no concept of what the object ought to be; the second does presuppose such a concept and the perfection of the object in accordance therewith."Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin's Press. p. 517. {{ISBN|0312053916}}. By this definition, free beauty is found in seashells and wordless music; adherent beauty in buildings and the human body.
The Romantic poets, too, became highly concerned with the nature of beauty, with John Keats arguing in Ode on a Grecian Urn that:
: Beauty is truth, truth beauty, —that is all
: Ye know on earth, and all ye need to know.
= Western 19th and 20th century =
In the Romantic period, Edmund Burke postulated a difference between beauty in its classical meaning and the sublime.Doran, Robert (2017). The Theory of the Sublime from Longinus to Kant. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 144. {{ISBN|1107499151}}. The concept of the sublime, as explicated by Burke and Kant, suggested viewing Gothic art and architecture, though not in accordance with the classical standard of beauty, as sublime.Monk, Samuel Holt (1960). The Sublime: A Study of Critical Theories in XVIII-century England. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. pp. 6–9, 141. {{OCLC|943884}}.
The 20th century saw an increasing rejection of beauty by artists and philosophers alike, culminating in postmodernism's anti-aesthetics.{{cite book|author=Hal Foster|title=The Anti-aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture|year=1998|publisher=New Press|isbn=978-1-56584-462-9}} This is despite beauty being a central concern of one of postmodernism's main influences, Friedrich Nietzsche, who argued that the Will to Power was the Will to Beauty.{{cite book|author=Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche|title=The Will To Power|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mM9vDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR31|year=1967|publisher=Random House|isbn=978-0-394-70437-1}}
In the aftermath of postmodernism's rejection of beauty, thinkers have returned to beauty as an important value. American analytic philosopher Guy Sircello proposed his New Theory of Beauty as an effort to reaffirm the status of beauty as an important philosophical concept.Guy Sircello, A New Theory of Beauty. Princeton Essays on the Arts, 1. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1975.Love and Beauty. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989. He rejected the subjectivism of Kant and sought to identify the properties inherent in an object that make it beautiful. He called qualities such as vividness, boldness, and subtlety "properties of qualitative degree" (PQDs) and stated that a PQD makes an object beautiful if it is not—and does not create the appearance of—"a property of deficiency, lack, or defect"; and if the PQD is strongly present in the object.Kennick, William Elmer (1979). Art and Philosophy: Readings in Aesthetics; 2nd ed. New York: St. Martin's Press. pp. 535–537. {{ISBN|0312053916}}.
Elaine Scarry argues that beauty is related to justice.{{cite book|author=Elaine Scarry|title=On Beauty and Being Just|date=4 November 2001|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=0-691-08959-0}}
Beauty is also studied by psychologists and neuroscientists in the field of experimental aesthetics and neuroesthetics respectively. Psychological theories see beauty as a form of pleasure.{{cite journal |last1=Reber |first1=Rolf |last2=Schwarz |first2=Norbert |last3=Winkielman |first3=Piotr |title=Processing Fluency and Aesthetic Pleasure: Is Beauty in the Perceiver's Processing Experience? |journal=Personality and Social Psychology Review |date=November 2004 |volume=8 |issue=4 |pages=364–382 |doi=10.1207/s15327957pspr0804_3 |pmid=15582859 |s2cid=1868463 |hdl=1956/594 |hdl-access=free }}{{cite journal |last1=Armstrong |first1=Thomas |last2=Detweiler-Bedell |first2=Brian |title=Beauty as an Emotion: The Exhilarating Prospect of Mastering a Challenging World |journal=Review of General Psychology |date=December 2008 |volume=12 |issue=4 |pages=305–329 |doi=10.1037/a0012558 |citeseerx=10.1.1.406.1825 |s2cid=8375375 }} Correlational findings support the view that more beautiful objects are also more pleasing.{{cite journal |last1=Vartanian |first1=Oshin |last2=Navarrete |first2=Gorka |last3=Chatterjee |first3=Anjan |last4=Fich |first4=Lars Brorson |last5=Leder |first5=Helmut |last6=Modroño |first6=Cristián |last7=Nadal |first7=Marcos |last8=Rostrup |first8=Nicolai |last9=Skov |first9=Martin |title=Impact of contour on aesthetic judgments and approach-avoidance decisions in architecture |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |date=18 June 2013 |volume=110 |issue=Suppl 2 |pages=10446–10453 |doi=10.1073/pnas.1301227110 |pmid=23754408 |pmc=3690611 |doi-access=free }}{{cite journal |last1=Marin |first1=Manuela M. |last2=Lampatz |first2=Allegra |last3=Wandl |first3=Michaela |last4=Leder |first4=Helmut |title=Berlyne Revisited: Evidence for the Multifaceted Nature of Hedonic Tone in the Appreciation of Paintings and Music |journal=Frontiers in Human Neuroscience |date=4 November 2016 |volume=10 |page=536 |doi=10.3389/fnhum.2016.00536 |pmid=27867350 |pmc=5095118 |doi-access=free }}{{cite journal |last1=Brielmann |first1=Aenne A. |last2=Pelli |first2=Denis G. |title=Beauty Requires Thought |journal=Current Biology |date=May 2017 |volume=27 |issue=10 |pages=1506–1513.e3 |doi=10.1016/j.cub.2017.04.018 |pmid=28502660 |pmc=6778408 |bibcode=2017CBio...27E1506B }} Some studies suggest that higher experienced beauty is associated with activity in the medial orbitofrontal cortex.{{cite journal |last1=Kawabata |first1=Hideaki |last2=Zeki |first2=Semir |title=Neural Correlates of Beauty |journal=Journal of Neurophysiology |date=April 2004 |volume=91 |issue=4 |pages=1699–1705 |doi=10.1152/jn.00696.2003 |pmid=15010496 |s2cid=13828130 }}{{cite journal |last1=Ishizu |first1=Tomohiro |last2=Zeki |first2=Semir |title=Toward A Brain-Based Theory of Beauty |journal=PLOS ONE |date=6 July 2011 |volume=6 |issue=7 |pages=e21852 |doi=10.1371/journal.pone.0021852 |pmid=21755004 |pmc=3130765 |bibcode=2011PLoSO...621852I |doi-access=free }} This approach of localizing the processing of beauty in one brain region has received criticism within the field.{{cite journal |last1=Conway |first1=Bevil R. |last2=Rehding |first2=Alexander |title=Neuroaesthetics and the Trouble with Beauty |journal=PLOS Biology |date=19 March 2013 |volume=11 |issue=3 |pages=e1001504 |doi=10.1371/journal.pbio.1001504 |pmid=23526878 |pmc=3601993 |doi-access=free }}
Philosopher and novelist Umberto Eco wrote On Beauty: A History of a Western Idea (2004){{Cite book|title=On Beauty: A historyof a western idea|last=Eco|first=Umberto|publisher=Secker & Warburg|year=2004|isbn=978-0436205170|location=London}}{{cite web | last=Phillips | first=Mike | title=Review: On Beauty edited by Umberto Eco | website=the Guardian | date=29 January 2005 | url=http://www.theguardian.com/books/2005/jan/29/history.highereducation | access-date=3 June 2023}} and On Ugliness (2007).{{Cite book|title=On Ugliness|last=Eco|first=Umberto|publisher=Harvill Secker|year=2007|isbn=9781846551222|location=London}} The narrator of his novel The Name of the Rose follows Aquinas in declaring: "three things concur in creating beauty: first of all integrity or perfection, and for this reason, we consider ugly all incomplete things; then proper proportion or consonance; and finally clarity and light", before going on to say "the sight of the beautiful implies peace".{{Cite book|title=The Name of the Rose|last=Eco|first=Umberto|publisher=Vintage|year=1980|isbn=9780099466031|location=London|pages=65}}{{cite journal |last1=Fasolini |first1=Diego |title=The Intrusion of Laughter into the Abbey of Umberto Eco's The Name of the Rose: The Christian paradox of Joy Mingling with Sorrow |journal=Romance Notes |date=2006 |volume=46 |issue=2 |pages=119–129 |jstor=43801801 }} Mike Phillips has described Umberto Eco's On Beauty as "incoherent" and criticized him for focusing only on Western European history and devoting none of his book to Eastern European, Asian, or African history. Amy Finnerty described Eco's work On Ugliness favorably.{{cite web | title=Edited by Umberto Eco - Book Review - The New York Times | website=On Ugliness | date=2 December 2007 | url=https://www.nytimes.com/2007/12/02/books/review/Finnerty-t.html | access-date=3 June 2023 | archive-date=June 3, 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230603202148/https://www.nytimes.com/2007/12/02/books/review/Finnerty-t.html | url-status=live }}
=Chinese philosophy=
Chinese philosophy has traditionally not made a separate discipline of the philosophy of beauty.The Chinese Text: Studies in Comparative Literature (1986). Cocos (Keeling) Islands: Chinese University Press. p. 119. {{ISBN|962201318X}}. Confucius identified beauty with goodness, and considered a virtuous personality to be the greatest of beauties: In his philosophy, "a neighborhood with a ren man in it is a beautiful neighborhood."Chang, Chi-yun (2013). Confucianism: A Modern Interpretation (2012 Edition). Singapore: World Scientific Publishing Company. p. 213. {{ISBN|9814439894}} Confucius's student Zeng Shen expressed a similar idea: "few men could see the beauty in some one whom they dislike." Mencius considered "complete truthfulness" to be beauty. Zhu Xi said: "When one has strenuously implemented goodness until it is filled to completion and has accumulated truth, then the beauty will reside within it and will not depend on externals."Tang, Yijie (2015). Confucianism, Buddhism, Daoism, Christianity and Chinese Culture. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. p. 242. {{ISBN|3662455331}}
Human attributes
{{Main|Physical attractiveness| Feminine beauty ideal}}
File:Nofretete Neues Museum.jpg, 14th century BC]]
The word "beauty" is often{{how often|date=November 2022}} used as a countable noun to describe a beautiful woman.{{Cite web|title=Beauty {{!}} Definition of Beauty by Oxford Dictionary on Lexico.com|url=https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/beauty|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200809175019/https://www.lexico.com/en/definition/beauty|url-status=dead|archive-date=August 9, 2020|access-date=2020-08-01|website=Lexico Dictionaries {{!}} English|language=en}}{{Cite web|title=BEAUTY (noun) American English definition and synonyms {{!}} Macmillan Dictionary|url=https://www.macmillandictionary.com/us/dictionary/american/beauty_1|access-date=2020-08-01|website=Macmillan Dictionary|language=en|archive-date=July 9, 2017|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170709064049/http://www.macmillandictionary.com/us/dictionary/american/beauty_1|url-status=live}}
The characterization of a person as "beautiful", whether on an individual basis or by community consensus, is often{{how often|date=November 2022}} based on some combination of inner beauty, which includes psychological factors such as personality, intelligence, grace, politeness, charisma, integrity, congruence and elegance, and outer beauty (i.e. physical attractiveness) which includes physical attributes which are valued on an aesthetic basis.{{citation needed|date=November 2022}}
Standards of beauty have changed over time, based on changing cultural values. Historically, paintings show a wide range of different standards for beauty.[https://books.google.com/books?id=J68vAAAAMAAJ&pg=PA291 Artists' Types of Beauty] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230203045633/https://www.google.com/books/edition/The_Strand_Magazine/J68vAAAAMAAJ?hl=en&gbpv=1&dq=&pg=PA291&printsec=frontcover |date=February 3, 2023 }}", The Strand Magazine. United Kingdom, G. Newnes, 1904. pp. 291–298.{{cite book | last=Chō | first=Kyō | translator-first=Kyoko Iriye | translator-last=Selden | translator-link=Kyoko Iriye Selden | year=2012 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=BQcl4aCkY5MC&q=painting | title=The Search for the Beautiful Woman: A Cultural History of Japanese and Chinese Beauty | location=Lanham | publisher=Rowman & Littlefield | pages=100–102 | isbn=978-1442218956}}.
A strong indicator of physical beauty is "averageness".{{Cite journal |doi = 10.1111/j.1467-9280.1990.tb00079.x|title = Attractive Faces Are Only Average|journal = Psychological Science|volume = 1|issue = 2|pages = 115–121|year = 1990|last1 = Langlois|first1 = Judith H.|last2 = Roggman|first2 = Lori A.|s2cid = 18557871}}{{cite journal |last1=Strauss |first1=Mark S. |title=Abstraction of prototypical information by adults and 10-month-old infants |journal=Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory |date=1979 |volume=5 |issue=6 |pages=618–632 |doi=10.1037/0278-7393.5.6.618 |pmid=528918 }} When images of human faces are averaged together to form a composite image, they become progressively closer to the "ideal" image and are perceived as more attractive. This was first noticed in 1883, when Francis Galton overlaid photographic composite images of the faces of vegetarians and criminals to see if there was a typical facial appearance for each. When doing this, he noticed that the composite images were more attractive as compared to any of the individual images.{{cite journal | last=Galton | first=Francis | title=Composite Portraits, Made by Combining Those of Many Different Persons Into a Single Resultant Figure. | journal=The Journal of the Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland | publisher=JSTOR | volume=8 | year=1879 | pages=132–144 | issn=0959-5295 | doi=10.2307/2841021 | jstor=2841021 | url=https://zenodo.org/record/1449534 | access-date=June 14, 2020 | archive-date=July 26, 2020 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200726162242/https://zenodo.org/record/1449534 | url-status=live }} Researchers have replicated the result under more controlled conditions and found that the computer-generated, mathematical average of a series of faces is rated more favorably than individual faces.{{cite journal | last1=Langlois | first1=Judith H. | last2=Roggman | first2=Lori A. | last3=Musselman | first3=Lisa | s2cid=145147905 | title=What Is Average and What Is Not Average About Attractive Faces? | journal=Psychological Science | publisher=SAGE Publications | volume=5 | issue=4 | year=1994 | issn=0956-7976 | doi=10.1111/j.1467-9280.1994.tb00503.x | pages=214–220}} It is argued that it is evolutionarily advantageous that sexual creatures are attracted to mates who possess predominantly common or average features, because it suggests the absence of genetic or acquired defects.{{cite journal | last=Koeslag | first=Johan H. | title=Koinophilia groups sexual creatures into species, promotes stasis, and stabilizes social behaviour | journal=Journal of Theoretical Biology | publisher=Elsevier BV | volume=144 | issue=1 | year=1990 | issn=0022-5193 | doi=10.1016/s0022-5193(05)80297-8 | pages=15–35| pmid=2200930 | bibcode=1990JThBi.144...15K }}Symons, D. (1979) The Evolution of Human Sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.{{cite news |url=https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/science/science-news/3341719/Why-beauty-is-an-advert-for-good-genes.html |archive-url=https://ghostarchive.org/archive/20220111/https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/science/science-news/3341719/Why-beauty-is-an-advert-for-good-genes.html |archive-date=January 11, 2022 |url-access=subscription |url-status=live |last=Highfield |first=Roger |author-link=Roger Highfield |title=Why beauty is an advert for good genes |newspaper=The Daily Telegraph |access-date=13 February 2012 |date=7 May 2008 }}{{cbignore}}
Since the 1970s there has been increasing evidence that a preference for beautiful faces emerges early in infancy, and is probably innate,{{cite journal | last1=Slater | first1=Alan | last2=Von der Schulenburg | first2=Charlotte | last3=Brown | first3=Elizabeth | last4=Badenoch | first4=Marion | last5=Butterworth | first5=George | last6=Parsons | first6=Sonia | last7=Samuels | first7=Curtis | title=Newborn infants prefer attractive faces | journal=Infant Behavior and Development | publisher=Elsevier BV | volume=21 | issue=2 | year=1998 | issn=0163-6383 | doi=10.1016/s0163-6383(98)90011-x | pages=345–354}}{{cite book | last1=Kramer | first1=Steve | last2=Zebrowitz | first2=Leslie | author2-link=Leslie Zebrowitz | last3=Giovanni | first3=Jean Paul San | last4=Sherak | first4=Barbara | title=Studies in Perception and Action III | chapter=Infants’ Preferences for Attractiveness and Babyfaceness | publisher=Routledge | date=2019-02-21 | isbn=978-1-315-78936-1 | doi=10.4324/9781315789361-103 | pages=389–392| s2cid=197734413 }}{{cite journal | last1=Langlois | first1=Judith H. | last2=Ritter | first2=Jean M. | last3=Roggman | first3=Lori A. | last4=Vaughn | first4=Lesley S. | title=Facial diversity and infant preferences for attractive faces. | journal=Developmental Psychology | publisher=American Psychological Association (APA) | volume=27 | issue=1 | year=1991 | issn=1939-0599 | doi=10.1037/0012-1649.27.1.79 | pages=79–84}}
and that the rules by which attractiveness is established are similar across different genders and cultures.{{cite journal | last1=Apicella | first1=Coren L | last2=Little | first2=Anthony C | last3=Marlowe | first3=Frank W | s2cid=37353815 | title=Facial Averageness and Attractiveness in an Isolated Population of Hunter-Gatherers | journal=Perception | publisher=SAGE Publications | volume=36 | issue=12 | year=2007 | issn=0301-0066 | doi=10.1068/p5601 | pages=1813–1820| pmid=18283931 }}{{cite journal | last=Rhodes | first=Gillian | title=The Evolutionary Psychology of Facial Beauty | journal=Annual Review of Psychology | publisher=Annual Reviews | volume=57 | issue=1 | year=2006 | issn=0066-4308 | doi=10.1146/annurev.psych.57.102904.190208 | pages=199–226| pmid=16318594 }}
A feature of beautiful women which has been explored by researchers is a waist–hip ratio of approximately 0.70. As of 2004, physiologists had shown that women with hourglass figures were more fertile than other women because of higher levels of certain female hormones, a fact that may subconsciously condition males choosing mates.{{Cite news|url=http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/health/3682657.stm|title=Hourglass figure fertility link|date=4 May 2004|work=BBC News|access-date=1 July 2018|archive-date=October 11, 2011|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111011122830/http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/health/3682657.stm|url-status=live}}{{Cite web|url=https://www.newscientist.com/article/dn4953-barbie-shaped-women-more-fertile/|title=Barbie-shaped women more fertile|last=Bhattacharya|first=Shaoni|date=5 May 2004|website=New Scientist|access-date=1 July 2018|archive-date=July 10, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180710102117/https://www.newscientist.com/article/dn4953-barbie-shaped-women-more-fertile/|url-status=live}} In 2008, other commentators have suggested that this preference may not be universal. For instance, in some non-Western cultures in which women have to do work such as finding food, men tend to have preferences for higher waist-hip ratios.{{Cite web|url=https://www.livescience.com/3098-female-figure-hourglass.html|title=Best Female Figure Not an Hourglass|date=December 3, 2008|website=Live Science|access-date=1 July 2018|archive-date=July 10, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180710102010/https://www.livescience.com/3098-female-figure-hourglass.html|url-status=live}}{{Cite news|url=https://www.vox.com/2014/6/22/5832826/did-evolution-really-make-men-prefer-women-with-hourglass-figures|title=Did evolution really make men prefer women with hourglass figures?|last=Locke|first=Susannah|date=June 22, 2014|work=Vox|access-date=1 July 2018|archive-date=July 10, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180710102501/https://www.vox.com/2014/6/22/5832826/did-evolution-really-make-men-prefer-women-with-hourglass-figures|url-status=live}}{{Cite web|url=http://www.sharonlbegley.com/hourglass-figures-we-take-it-all-back|title=Hourglass Figures: We Take It All Back|last=Begley|first=Sharon|website=Sharon Begley|access-date=1 July 2018|archive-date=July 10, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180710102426/http://www.sharonlbegley.com/hourglass-figures-we-take-it-all-back|url-status=live}}
Exposure to the thin ideal in mass media, such as fashion magazines, directly correlates with body dissatisfaction, low self-esteem, and the development of eating disorders among female viewers.{{Cite news|url=https://www.nationaleatingdisorders.org/media-eating-disorders|title=Media & Eating Disorders|date=2017-10-05|work=National Eating Disorders Association|access-date=2018-11-27|language=en|archive-date=December 2, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181202024747/https://www.nationaleatingdisorders.org/media-eating-disorders|url-status=live}}{{Cite web|url=http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/health/769290.stm|title=Model's link to teenage anorexia|date=May 30, 2000|website=BBC News|access-date=October 25, 2009|archive-date=April 13, 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200413234506/http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/health/769290.stm|url-status=live}} Further, the widening gap between individual body sizes and societal ideals continues to breed anxiety among young girls as they grow, highlighting the dangerous nature of beauty standards in society.{{Cite news|url=https://eating-disorders.org.uk/information/the-media-eating-disorders/|title=National Centre for Eating Disorders - The Media & Eating Disorders|last=Jade|first=Deanne|work=National Centre for Eating Disorders|access-date=2018-11-27|language=en-US|archive-date=December 24, 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181224041630/https://eating-disorders.org.uk/information/the-media-eating-disorders/|url-status=live}}
= Western concept=
File:18891109 Arsenic complexion wafers - Helena Independent.png complexion wafers" decried blotches, moles, pimples, freckles, and "all female irregularities".{{cite news |title=A Woman's Face is Her Fortune (advertisement) |url=https://newspaperarchive.com/helena-independent-nov-09-1889-p-9/ |newspaper=The Helena Independent |date=November 9, 2000 |page=7 |archive-date=August 27, 2021 |access-date=October 6, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210827224324/https://newspaperarchive.com/browse/us/mt/helena/helena-independent/ |url-status=live }} Arsenic was known to be poisonous during the Victorian era.{{cite magazine |last1=Little |first1=Becky |title=Arsenic Pills and Lead Foundation: The History of Toxic Makeup |url=https://news.nationalgeographic.com/2016/09/ingredients-lipstick-makeup-cosmetics-science-history/ |magazine=National Geographic |date=2016-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181105180856/https://news.nationalgeographic.com/2016/09/ingredients-lipstick-makeup-cosmetics-science-history/ |archive-date=November 5, 2018 |url-status=dead }}]]
A study using Chinese immigrants and Hispanic, Black and White American citizens found that their ideals of female beauty were not significantly different.{{cite journal | last=Cunningham | first=Michael | first4=Perri B. | last5=Wu | first5=Cheng-Huan | title="Their ideas of beauty are, on the whole, the same as ours": Consistency and variability in the cross-cultural perception of female physical attractiveness. | journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology | volume=68 | issue=2 | date=1995 | issn=1939-1315 | doi=10.1037/0022-3514.68.2.261 | pages=261–279}} Participants in the study rated Asian and Latina women as more attractive than White and Black women, and it was found that Asian and Latina women had more of the attributes that were considered attractive for women.{{harvnb|Cunningham|1995|p=1995|ps=: "All groups of judges made more positive ratings of the Asian and Hispanic targets compared with the Black and White targets. Further analyses indicated that the Asian and Hispanic targets happened to possess significantly larger eye height, eye width, nose width, eyebrow height, smile width, and upper lip width than the White and Black women".}} Exposure to Western media did not influence or improve the Asian men's ratings of White women.{{harvnb|Cunningham|1995|p=271|ps=: "The four-item measure of exposure to Western culture was not reliably associated with giving higher ratings to Whites (r = . 19, n s). The relation of rating Whites to frequency of viewing Western television, for example, was quite low (r=.01)."}}
One study found that East Asian women in the United States are closer to the ideal figure promoted in Western media, and that East Asian women conform to both Western and Eastern influences in the United States.{{cite journal | last1=Barnett | first1=Heather L. | last2=Keel | first2=P. | last3=Conoscenti | first3=Lauren M. | title=Body Type Preferences in Asian and Caucasian College Students | journal=Sex Roles | date=2001 | volume=45 | issue=11/12 | page=875-875| doi=10.1023/A:1015600705749 | s2cid=141429057 }}{{harvnb|Barnett|Keel|Conoscenti|2001|p=875|ps=: "Rieger et al. (2001) argue that traditional values and practices in Asian cultures also idealize thinness. Virtues of fasting that results in emaciation are quoted from the Daoist text Sandong zhunang (Rieger et al., 2001). Thus, while Caucasian and Asian women may be exposed to similar ideals of attractiveness, and Asian women are nearer to weight ideals portrayed by the media, both traditional and western values may contribute to the internalization of extremely thin ideals by Asian females."}} East Asian men were found to be more impacted by Western beauty ideals then East Asian women, in the United States. East Asian men felt as though their bodies were not large enough and therefore deviated from the Western norm.{{harvnb|Barnett|Keel|Conoscenti|2001|p=875|ps=: "Additionally, ethnic facial features may contribute to a general feeling of deviating from the norm, leading Asian or Asian American men to focus on a seemingly mutable quality, body weight. Further, Asian men were more likely than Caucasian men to select an ideal body figure that was similar to the figure they thought most attractive to the opposite sex. This suggests that Asian males may be more invested in achieving a larger body in order to attract a romantic partner. Finally, Asian males may be negatively affected by efforts to acculturate to Western society. A recent study revealed that acculturation is positively related to perfectionism in Asian males but not Asian females (Davis & Katzman, 1999)."}} East Asian men and white Western women were found to have the highest levels of body dissatisfaction in the United States.{{harvnb|Barnett|Keel|Conoscenti|2001|p=875|ps=: " "Specifically, Asian males reported an ideal figure that was larger than their current figure. An interaction between gender and ethnicity revealed that Caucasian females and Asian males reported the largest degree of body dissatisfaction."}} A study of African American and South Asian women found that some had internalized a white beauty ideal that placed light skin and straight hair at the top.{{Cite journal|last1=Harper|first1=Kathryn|last2=Choma|first2=Becky L.|s2cid=150156045|date=2018-10-05|title=Internalised White Ideal, Skin Tone Surveillance, and Hair Surveillance Predict Skin and Hair Dissatisfaction and Skin Bleaching among African American and Indian Women|journal=Sex Roles| volume=80| issue=11–12| pages=735–744| doi=10.1007/s11199-018-0966-9|issn=0360-0025}}
Eurocentric standards for men include tallness, leanness, and muscularity, which have been idolized through American media, such as in Hollywood films and magazine covers.{{cite book | last1=Pompper | first1=D. | last2=Allison | first2=M.C. | title=Rhetoric of Masculinity: Male Body Image, Media, and Gender Role Stress/Conflict | publisher=Lexington Books | year=2022 | isbn=978-1-7936-2689-9 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zt1WEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA82 | access-date=2023-06-03 | pages=82–83}}
In of the United States, African Americans have historically been subjected to beauty ideals that often do not reflect their own appearance, which can lead to issues of low self-esteem. African-American philosopher Cornel West elaborates that, "much of black self-hatred and self-contempt has to do with the refusal of many black Americans to love their own black bodies-especially their black noses, hips, lips, and hair."{{cite book | last=West | first=C. | title=Race Matters, 25th Anniversary: With a New Introduction | publisher=Beacon Press | year=2017 | isbn=978-0-8070-0883-6 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mRVHDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA85 | access-date=1 June 2023 | page=85}} According to Patton (2006), the stereotype of African-American women's inferiority (relative to other races of women) maintains a system of oppression based on race and gender that operates to the detriment of women of all races, and also black men.{{cite journal |last1=Patton |first1=Tracey Owens |title=Hey Girl, Am I More than My Hair?: African American Women and Their Struggles with Beauty, Body Image, and Hair |journal=NWSA Journal |date=July 2006 |volume=18 |issue=2 |pages=45–46 |doi=10.2979/NWS.2006.18.2.24 |doi-broken-date=November 1, 2024 |id={{Project MUSE|199496}} {{ProQuest|233235409}} |jstor=4317206 |quote= "These stereotypes and the culture that sustains them exist to define the social position of black women as subordinate on the basis of gender to all men, regardless of color, and on the basis of race to all other women. These negative images also are indispensable to the maintenance of an interlocking system of oppression based on race and gender that operates to the detriment of all women and all blacks" (Caldwell 2000, 280)."}} In the 1960s, the black is beautiful cultural movement sought to dispel the notion of a Eurocentric concept of beauty.{{Cite web |last=DoCarmo |first=Stephen |title=Notes on the Black Cultural Movement |publisher=Bucks County Community College |url=http://www.bucks.edu/~docarmos/BCMnotes.html |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20050408205800/http://www.bucks.edu/~docarmos/BCMnotes.html |archive-date=April 8, 2005 |access-date=November 27, 2007 |url-status=dead }}
Much criticism has been directed at models of beauty which depend solely upon Western ideals of beauty, as seen, for example, in the Barbie franchise. Criticisms of Barbie are often centered around concerns that children consider Barbie a role model of beauty and will attempt to emulate her. One of the most common criticisms of Barbie is that she promotes an unrealistic idea of body image for a young woman, leading to a risk that girls who attempt to emulate her will become anorexic.{{cite journal |last1=Dittmar |first1=Helga |last2=Halliwell |first2=Emma |last3=Ive |first3=Suzanne |title=Does Barbie make girls want to be thin? The effect of experimental exposure to images of dolls on the body image of 5- to 8-year-old girls |journal=Developmental Psychology |date=March 2006 |volume=42 |issue=2 |pages=283–292 |doi=10.1037/0012-1649.42.2.283 |pmid=16569167 }}
As of 1998, these criticisms of the lack of diversity in such franchises as the Barbie model of beauty in Western culture, had led to a dialogue to create non-exclusive models of Western ideals in body type for young girls who do not match the thinness ideal that Barbie represents.{{cite book | last1=Flett | first1=G.L. | last2=Kocovski | first2=N. | last3=Davison | first3=G.C. | last4=Neale | first4=J.M. | last5=Blankstein | first5=K.R. | title=Abnormal Psychology, Sixth Canadian Edition Loose-Leaf Print Companion | publisher=John Wiley & Sons Canada, Limited | year=2017 | isbn=978-1-119-44409-1 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=e_6lEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA292 | language=cy | access-date=2024-01-11 | page=292}} Mattel responded to these criticisms.
In East Asian cultures, familial pressures and cultural norms shape beauty ideals. A 2017 experimental study concluded that Asian cultural idealization of "fragile" girls was impacting Asian American women's lifestyle, eating, and appearance choices.{{cite journal |last1=Wong |first1=Stephanie N. |last2=Keum |first2=Brian TaeHyuk |last3=Caffarel |first3=Daniel |last4=Srinivasan |first4=Ranjana |last5=Morshedian |first5=Negar |last6=Capodilupo |first6=Christina M. |last7=Brewster |first7=Melanie E. |title=Exploring the conceptualization of body image for Asian American women. |journal=Asian American Journal of Psychology |date=December 2017 |volume=8 |issue=4 |pages=296–307 |doi=10.1037/aap0000077 |s2cid=151560804 }}
Effects on society
Researchers have found that good-looking students get higher grades from their teachers than students with an ordinary appearance.{{cite web|first=Sharon |last=Begley |author-link=Sharon Begley |url=http://www.newsweek.com/id/206597 |title=The Link Between Beauty and Grades |work=Newsweek |date=14 July 2009 |access-date=2010-05-31| archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20100420004627/http://www.newsweek.com/id/206597| archive-date=April 20, 2010| url-status= live}} Some studies using mock criminal trials have shown that physically attractive "defendants" are less likely to be convicted—and if convicted are likely to receive lighter sentences—than less attractive ones (although the opposite effect was observed when the alleged crime was swindling, perhaps because jurors perceived the defendant's attractiveness as facilitating the crime).{{cite book|author1=Amina A Memon|author2=Aldert Vrij|author3=Ray Bull|title=Psychology and Law: Truthfulness, Accuracy and Credibility|date=31 October 2003|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|isbn=978-0-470-86835-5|pages=46–47}} Studies among teens and young adults, such as those of psychiatrist and self-help author Eva Ritvo show that skin conditions have a profound effect on social behavior and opportunity.{{cite press release |url=http://multivu.prnewswire.com/mnr/galderma/38432 |title=Image survey reveals "perception is reality" when it comes to teenagers |publisher=multivu.prnewswire.com |url-status=live |archive-url=https://archive.today/20120710073856/http://multivu.prnewswire.com/mnr/galderma/38432 |archive-date=July 10, 2012 |df=mdy-all }}
How much money a person earns may also be influenced by physical beauty. One study found that people low in physical attractiveness earn 5 to 10 percent less than ordinary-looking people, who in turn earn 3 to 8 percent less than those who are considered good-looking.{{cite news |last=Lorenz |first=K. |year=2005 |url=http://www.cnn.com/2005/US/Careers/07/08/looks/ |title=Do pretty people earn more? |work=CNN News |publisher=Time Warner |agency=Cable News Network |access-date=January 31, 2007 |archive-date=October 12, 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151012073953/http://www.cnn.com/2005/US/Careers/07/08/looks/ |url-status=live }} In the market for loans, the least attractive people are less likely to get approvals, although they are less likely to default. In the marriage market, women's looks are at a premium, but men's looks do not matter much.{{Cite web |last=Hamermesh |first=Daniel |author-link=Dubner |last2=Stephen J. |date=30 January 2014 |title=Reasons to not be ugly: full transcript |url=http://freakonomics.com/2014/01/30/reasons-to-not-be-ugly-full-transcript/ |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140301230021/http://freakonomics.com/2014/01/30/reasons-to-not-be-ugly-full-transcript/ |archive-date=March 1, 2014 |access-date=2014-03-04 |website=Freakonomics |df=mdy-all}} The impact of physical attractiveness on earnings varies across races, with the largest beauty wage gap among black women and black men.{{cite journal |last1=Monk |first1=Ellis P. |last2=Esposito |first2=Michael H. |last3=Lee |first3=Hedwig |title=Beholding Inequality: Race, Gender, and Returns to Physical Attractiveness in the United States |journal=American Journal of Sociology |date=1 July 2021 |volume=127 |issue=1 |pages=194–241 |doi=10.1086/715141 |s2cid=235473652 }}
Conversely, being very unattractive increases the individual's propensity for criminal activity for a number of crimes ranging from burglary to theft to selling illicit drugs.
Discrimination against others based on their appearance is known as lookism.{{cite book|author=Leo Gough|title=C. Northcote Parkinson's Parkinson's Law: A modern-day interpretation of a management classic|date=29 June 2011|publisher=Infinite Ideas|isbn=978-1-908189-71-4|page=36}}
See also
Notes
{{reflist|group=note}}
References
{{Reflist|35}}
Further reading
- {{cite book |title=The Evolution of Beauty: How Darwin's Forgotten Theory of Mate Choice Shapes the Animal World - and Us |author=Richard O. Prum |publisher=Anchor |year=2018 |isbn=978-0345804570}}
- Liebelt, C. (2022), [https://doi.org/10.1002/fea2.12076 Beauty: What Makes Us Dream, What Haunts Us]. Feminist Anthropology.
External links
{{Commons category|Beauty}}
{{Wikiquote|Beauty}}
{{Wiktionary|beauty|pretty}}
- {{cite SEP |url-id=beauty |title=Beauty |last=Sartwell |first=Crispin}}
- {{InPho|idea|1998}}
- [http://www.bbc.co.uk/radio4/history/inourtime/inourtime_20050519.shtml BBC Radio 4's In Our Time programme on Beauty] (requires RealAudio)
- [https://web.archive.org/web/20050305091132/http://etext.lib.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/dhi.cgi?id=dv1-28 Dictionary of the History of Ideas:] Theories of Beauty to the Mid-Nineteenth Century
- [http://www.uni-regensburg.de/Fakultaeten/phil_Fak_II/Psychologie/Psy_II/beautycheck/english/prototypen/prototypen.htm beautycheck.de/english] Regensburg University – Characteristics of beautiful faces
- [http://www.terraingallery.org/IsBeauty.html Eli Siegel's "Is Beauty the Making One of Opposites?"]
- [http://libmma.contentdm.oclc.org/cdm/ref/collection/p15324coll10/id/53033 Art and love in Renaissance Italy ], Issued in connection with an exhibition held Nov. 11, 2008-Feb. 16, 2009, Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York (see Belle: Picturing Beautiful Women; pages 246–254).
- [https://books.google.com/books?id=pFEII68kmVsC&dq=Thales+philosophy+on++beauty&pg=PA356 Plato - Symposium] in S. Marc Cohen, Patricia Curd, C. D. C. Reeve (ed.)
{{Aesthetics}}
{{Humanities}}
{{Authority control}}
Category:Concepts in aesthetics