Classical liberalism#Evolution of core beliefs
{{short description|Ideology supporting both civil and economic liberties}}
{{about|the branch of liberalism that advocates civil liberties with an emphasis on economic freedom|the liberal economic system organized on individual lines|Economic liberalism|the branch of liberalism that endorses a regulated market economy and the expansion of civil and political rights|Social liberalism}}
{{EngvarB|date=October 2020}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=March 2018}}
{{liberalism sidebar}}
{{Capitalism sidebar}}
Classical liberalism is a political tradition and a branch of liberalism that advocates free market and laissez-faire economics and civil liberties under the rule of law, with special emphasis on individual autonomy, limited government, economic freedom, political freedom and freedom of speech.{{cite web |title=Classical liberalism |url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/classical-liberalism |website=www.britannica.com |publisher=Encyclopædia Britannica |access-date=17 October 2023 |date=6 September 2023}} Classical liberalism, contrary to progressive branches like social liberalism, looks more negatively on social policies, taxation and the state involvement in the lives of individuals, and it advocates deregulation.M. O. Dickerson et al., An Introduction to Government and Politics: A Conceptual Approach (2009) p. 129
Until the Great Depression and the rise of social liberalism, classical liberalism was called economic liberalism. Later, the term was applied as a retronym, to distinguish earlier 19th-century liberalism from social liberalism.{{sfn|Richardson|p=52}} By modern standards, in the United States, the bare term liberalism often means social or progressive liberalism, but in Europe and Australia, the bare term liberalism often means classical liberalism.{{cite news |last=Goldfarb |first=Michael |date=20 July 2010 |title=Liberal? Are we talking about the same thing? |language=en-GB |publisher=BBC News |url=https://www.bbc.com/news/world-10658070 |access-date=6 August 2020}}{{cite news |last=Greenberg |first=David |date=12 September 2019 |title=The danger of confusing liberals and leftists |newspaper=The Washington Post |url=https://www.washingtonpost.com/outlook/2019/09/12/stop-calling-bernie-sanders-alexandria-ocasio-cortez-liberals/ |access-date=6 August 2020}}
Classical liberalism gained full flowering in the early 18th century, building on ideas dating at least as far back as the 16th century, within the Iberian, French, British, and Central European contexts, and it was foundational to the American Revolution and "American Project" more broadly.{{cite book |last=Douma |first=Michael |title=What is Classical Liberal History? |date=2018 |publisher=Lexington Books |isbn=978-1-4985-3610-3}}{{sfn|Dickerson|Flanagan|O'Neill|p=129}}{{cite web |last=Renshaw |first=Catherine |date=2014-03-18 |title=What is a 'classical liberal' approach to human rights? |url=http://theconversation.com/what-is-a-classical-liberal-approach-to-human-rights-24452 |access-date=2022-08-12 |website=The Conversation}} Notable liberal individuals whose ideas contributed to classical liberalism include John Locke,Steven M. Dworetz (1994). The Unvarnished Doctrine: Locke, Liberalism, and the American Revolution. François Quesnay, Jean-Baptiste Say, Montesquieu, Voltaire, Marquis de Condorcet, Thomas Paine, Thomas Malthus, and David Ricardo. It drew on classical economics, especially the economic ideas espoused by Adam Smith in Book One of The Wealth of Nations, and on a belief in natural law.{{cite book |last=Appleby |first=Joyce |author-link=Joyce Appleby |title=Liberalism and Republicanism in the Historical Imagination |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=83HlqTJjLcgC&pg=PA58 |publisher=Harvard University Press |date=1992 |page=58 |isbn=978-0674530133}} In contemporary times, Murray Rothbard, Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, Ludwig von Mises, Thomas Sowell, Walter E. Williams, George Stigler, Larry Arnhart, Ronald Coase and James M. Buchanan are seen as the most prominent advocates of classical liberalism.{{cite book |last=Dilley |first=Stephen C. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XAIQOVWz2hEC |title=Darwinian Evolution and Classical Liberalism: Theories in Tension |date=2013-05-02 |publisher=Lexington Books |isbn=978-0-7391-8107-2 |pages=13–14}}{{cite journal |last=Peters |first=Michael A. |date=2022-04-16 |title=Hayek as classical liberal public intellectual: Neoliberalism, the privatization of public discourse and the future of democracy |journal=Educational Philosophy and Theory |volume=54 |issue=5 |pages=443–449 |doi=10.1080/00131857.2019.1696303 |s2cid=213420239 |issn=0013-1857|doi-access=free}} However, other scholars have made reference to these contemporary thoughts as neoclassical liberalism, distinguishing them from 18th-century classical liberalism.Mayne, Alan James (1999). From Politics Past to Politics Future: An Integrated Analysis of Current and Emergent Paradigmss. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 124–125. {{ISBN|0275961516}}.{{cite book |last1=Ishiyama |first1=John T. |title=21st Century Political Science A Reference Handbook |last2=Breuning |first2=Marijke |collaboration=Ellen Grigsby |publisher=SAGE Publications, Inc. |year=2011 |isbn=978-1-4129 6901-7 |pages=596–603 |chapter=Neoclassical liberals}}
In its defense of economic liberties, classical liberalism may be described as conservative or right wing,{{Cite book |title=The Desk Encyclopedia of World History |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2006 |isbn=978-0-7394-7809-7 |editor-last=Wright |editor-first=Edmund |location=New York |pages=370}} while in its defense of civil liberties, it has more in common with modern liberalism (the left). Despite this, classical liberals tend to reject the right's higher tolerance for economic protectionism and the left's inclination for collective group rights due to classical liberalism's central principle of individualism.{{cite web |last1=Goodman |first1=John C. |title=Classical Liberalism vs. Modern Liberalism and Modern Conservatism |url=https://www.goodmaninstitute.org/about/how-we-think/classical-liberalism-vs-modern-liberalism-and-modern-conservatism/ |website=Goodman Institute |access-date=2 January 2022}} Additionally, in the United States, classical liberalism is considered closely tied to, or synonymous with, American libertarianism.{{Cite web |date=2023-04-06 |title=Libertarianism vs. Classical Liberalism: Is there a Difference? |url=https://reason.com/volokh/2023/04/06/libertarianism-vs-classical-liberalism-is-there-a-difference/ |access-date=2023-09-22 |website=Reason.com |language=en-US}}{{Cite web |last=Klein |first=Daniel B. |date=2017-05-03 |title=Libertarianism and Classical Liberalism: A Short Introduction {{!}} Daniel B. Klein |url=https://fee.org/articles/libertarianism-and-classical-liberalism-a-short-introduction/ |access-date=2022-03-08 |website=fee.org |language=en}}
Evolution of core beliefs
Core beliefs of classical liberals included new ideas{{snd}}which departed from both the older conservative idea of society as a family and from the later sociological concept of society as a complex set of social networks.
Classical liberals agreed with Thomas Hobbes that individuals created government to protect themselves from each other and to minimize conflict between individuals that would otherwise arise in a state of nature. These beliefs were complemented by a belief that financial incentive could best motivate labourers. This belief led to the passage of the Poor Law Amendment Act 1834, which limited the provision of social assistance, based on the idea that markets are the mechanism that most efficiently leads to wealth.
Drawing on ideas of Adam Smith, classical liberals believed that it was in the common interest that all individuals be able to secure their own economic self-interest.{{sfn|Dickerson|Flanagan|O'Neill|p=132}} They were critical of what would come to be the idea of the welfare state as interfering in a free market.Alan Ryan, "Liberalism", in A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, ed. Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1995), p. 293. Despite Smith's resolute recognition of the importance and value of labour and of labourers, classical liberals criticized labour's group rights being pursued at the expense of individual rightsEvans, M. ed. (2001): Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism: Evidence and Experience, London: Routledge, 55 ({{ISBN|1579583393}}). while accepting corporations' rights, which led to inequality of bargaining power.{{sfn|Dickerson|Flanagan|O'Neill|p=132}}{{cite book|last=Smith|first=A.|date=1778|title=An Inquiry Into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations|volume=I|chapter=8|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KpWg1DYxRTwC&q=%22public+good%22&pg=PA81|publisher=W. Strahan; and T. Cadell}} Classical liberals argued that individuals should be free to obtain work from the highest-paying employers, while the profit motive would ensure that products that people desired were produced at prices they would pay. In a free market, both labour and capital would receive the greatest possible reward, while production would be organized efficiently to meet consumer demand.{{sfn|Hunt|pp=46–47}} Classical liberals argued for what they called a minimal state and government, limited to the following functions:
- Laws to protect citizens from wrongs committed against them by other citizens, which included protection of individual rights, private property, enforcement of contracts and common law.
- A common national defence to provide protection against foreign invaders.{{sfn|Hunt|pp=51–53}}
- Public works and services that cannot be provided in a free market such as a stable currency, standard weights and measures and building and upkeep of roads, canals, harbours, railways, communications and postal services.{{sfn|Hunt|pp=51–53}}
Classical liberals asserted that rights are of a negative nature and therefore stipulate that other individuals and governments are to refrain from interfering with the free market, opposing social liberals who assert that individuals have positive rights, such as the right to vote, the right to an education, the right to healthcare, and the right to a minimum wage. For society to guarantee positive rights, it requires taxation over and above the minimum needed to enforce negative rights.Kelly, D. (1998): A Life of One's Own: Individual Rights and the Welfare State, Washington, DC: Cato Institute.{{sfn|Richardson|pp=36–38}}
Core beliefs of classical liberals did not necessarily include democracy nor government by a majority vote by citizens because "there is nothing in the bare idea of majority rule to show that majorities will always respect the rights of property or maintain rule of law".{{cite journal |last1=Ellerman |first1=David |title=Does classical liberalism imply democracy? |journal=Ethics & Global Politics |date=2015 |volume=8 |issue=1 |pages=29310 |doi=10.3402/egp.v8.29310 |doi-access=free}}Ryan, A. (1995): "Liberalism", In: Goodin, R. E. and Pettit, P., eds.: A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, p. 293. For example, James Madison argued for a constitutional republic with protections for individual liberty over a pure democracy, reasoning that in a pure democracy a "common passion or interest will, in almost every case, be felt by a majority of the whole ... and there is nothing to check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party".James Madison, Federalist No. 10 (22 November 1787), in Alexander Hamilton, John Jay and James Madison, The Federalist: A Commentary on the Constitution of the United States, ed. Henry Cabot Lodge (New York, 1888), [https://books.google.com/books?id=XcllKruLvi4C&q=%22common+passion+or+interest%22&pg=PA56 p. 56].
In the late 19th century, classical liberalism developed into neoclassical liberalism, which argued for government to be as small as possible to allow the exercise of individual freedom. In its most extreme form, neoclassical liberalism advocated social Darwinism.{{sfn|Mayne|1999|p=124}} Right-libertarianism is a modern form of neoclassical liberalism.{{sfn|Mayne|1999|p=124}} However, Edwin Van de Haar states although classical liberal thought influenced libertarianism, there are significant differences between them.{{sfn|Van de Haar|2015|p=71}} Classical liberalism refuses to give priority to liberty over order and therefore does not exhibit the hostility to the state which is the defining feature of libertarianism.{{sfn|Heywood|2004|p=337}} As such, right-libertarians believe classical liberals do not have enough respect for individual property rights and lack sufficient trust in the free market's workings and spontaneous order leading to their support of a much larger state.{{sfn|Van de Haar|2015|p=42}} Right-libertarians also disagree with classical liberals as being too supportive of central banks and monetarist policies.{{sfn|Van de Haar|2015|p=43}}
= Typology of beliefs =
Friedrich Hayek identified two different traditions within classical liberalism, namely the British tradition and the French tradition:
- The British philosophers Bernard Mandeville, David Hume, Edmund Burke, Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson, Josiah Tucker and William Paley held beliefs in empiricism, the common law and in traditions and institutions which had spontaneously evolved but were imperfectly understood.
- The French philosophers Voltaire, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Denis Diderot, Maximilien Robespierre, Louis Antoine de Saint-Just, Marquis de Condorcet, the Encyclopedists and the Physiocrats believed in rationalism and sometimes showed hostility to tradition and religion.
Hayek conceded that the national labels did not exactly correspond to those belonging to each tradition since he saw the Frenchmen Montesquieu, Benjamin Constant, Joseph De Maistre and Alexis de Tocqueville as belonging to the British tradition and the British Thomas Hobbes, Joseph Priestley, Richard Price, Edward Gibbon, Benjamin Franklin, Thomas Jefferson and Thomas Paine as belonging to the French tradition.{{cite book|first=F. A.|last=Hayek|title=The Constitution of Liberty|location=London|publisher=Routledge|date=1976|pages=55–56|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0otEBAAAQBAJ&q=The+Constitution+of+Liberty|isbn=978-1317857808}}F. A. Hayek, "Individualism: True and False", in Individualism and Economic Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), pp. 1–32. Hayek also rejected the label laissez-faire as originating from the French tradition and alien to the beliefs of Hume and Smith.
Guido De Ruggiero also identified differences between "Montesquieu and Rousseau, the English and the democratic types of liberalism"{{sfn|De Ruggiero|p=71}} and argued that there was a "profound contrast between the two Liberal systems".{{sfn|De Ruggiero|p=81}} He claimed that the spirit of "authentic English Liberalism" had "built up its work piece by piece without ever destroying what had once been built, but basing upon it every new departure". This liberalism had "insensibly adapted ancient institutions to modern needs" and "instinctively recoiled from all abstract proclamations of principles and rights".{{sfn|De Ruggiero|p=81}} Ruggiero claimed that this liberalism was challenged by what he called the "new Liberalism of France" that was characterised by egalitarianism and a "rationalistic consciousness".{{sfn|De Ruggiero|pp=81–82}}
In 1848, Francis Lieber distinguished between what he called "Anglican and Gallican Liberty". Lieber asserted that "independence in the highest degree, compatible with safety and broad national guarantees of liberty, is the great aim of Anglican liberty, and self-reliance is the chief source from which it draws its strength".{{sfn|Lieber|p=377}} On the other hand, Gallican liberty "is sought in government ... . [T]he French look for the highest degree of political civilisation in organisation, that is, in the highest degree of interference by public power".{{sfn|Lieber|pp=382–383}}
History
= Great Britain =
French physiocracy heavily influenced British classical liberalism, which traces its roots to the Whigs and Radicals. Whiggery had become a dominant ideology following the Glorious Revolution of 1688 and was associated with supporting the British Parliament, upholding the rule of law, defending landed property and sometimes included freedom of the press and freedom of speech. The origins of rights were seen as being in an ancient constitution existing from time immemorial. Custom rather than as natural rights justified these rights. Whigs believed that executive power had to be constrained. While they supported limited suffrage, they saw voting as a privilege rather than as a right. However, there was no consistency in Whig ideology and diverse writers including John Locke, David Hume, Adam Smith and Edmund Burke were all influential among Whigs, although none of them were universally accepted.{{sfn|Vincent|pp=28–29}}
From the 1790s to the 1820s, British radicals concentrated on parliamentary and electoral reform, emphasising natural rights and popular sovereignty. Richard Price and Joseph Priestley adapted the language of Locke to the ideology of radicalism.{{sfn|Vincent|pp=28–29}} The radicals saw parliamentary reform as a first step toward dealing with their many grievances, including the treatment of Protestant Dissenters, the slave trade, high prices, and high taxes.{{cite book|first=Michael J.|last=Turner|year=1999|title=British Politics in an Age of Reform|location=Manchester|publisher=Manchester University Press|isbn=978-0719051869|page=86}} There was greater unity among classical liberals than there had been among Whigs. Classical liberals were committed to individualism, liberty, and equal rights, as well as some other important tenants of leftism, since classical liberalism was introduced in the late 18th century as a leftist movement. They believed these goals required a free economy with minimal government interference. Some elements of Whiggery were uncomfortable with the commercial nature of classical liberalism. These elements became associated with conservatism.{{sfn|Vincent|pp=29–30}}
File:1846 - Anti-Corn Law League Meeting.jpg in Exeter Hall in 1846]]
Classical liberalism was the dominant political theory in Britain from the early 19th century until the First World War. Its notable victories were the Roman Catholic Relief Act 1829, the Reform Act 1832 and the repeal of the Corn Laws in 1846. The Anti-Corn Law League brought together a coalition of liberal and radical groups in support of free trade under the leadership of Richard Cobden and John Bright, who opposed aristocratic privilege, militarism, and public expenditure and believed that the backbone of Great Britain was the yeoman farmer. Their policies of low public expenditure and low taxation were adopted by William Gladstone when he became Chancellor of the Exchequer and later Prime Minister. Classical liberalism was often associated with religious dissent and nonconformism.{{sfn|Gray|pp=26–27}}
Although classical liberals aspired to a minimum of state activity, they accepted the principle of government intervention in the economy from the early 19th century on, with passage of the Factory Acts. From around 1840 to 1860, laissez-faire advocates of the Manchester School and writers in The Economist were confident that their early victories would lead to a period of expanding economic and personal liberty and world peace, but would face reversals as government intervention and activity continued to expand from the 1850s. Jeremy Bentham and James Mill, although advocates of laissez-faire, non-intervention in foreign affairs, and individual liberty, believed that social institutions could be rationally redesigned through the principles of utilitarianism. The Conservative Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli rejected classical liberalism altogether and advocated Tory democracy. By the 1870s, Herbert Spencer and other classical liberals concluded that historical development was turning against them.{{sfn|Gray|p=28}} By the First World War, the Liberal Party had largely abandoned classical liberal principles.{{sfn|Gray|p=32}}
The changing economic and social conditions of the 19th century led to a division between neo-classical and social (or welfare) liberals, who while agreeing on the importance of individual liberty differed on the role of the state. Neo-classical liberals, who called themselves "true liberals", saw Locke's Second Treatise as the best guide and emphasised "limited government" while social liberals supported government regulation and the welfare state. Herbert Spencer in Britain and William Graham Sumner were the leading neo-classical liberal theorists of the 19th century.{{sfn|Ishiyama|Breuning|p=596}} The evolution from classical to social/welfare liberalism is for example reflected in Britain in the evolution of the thought of John Maynard Keynes.See the studies of Keynes by Roy Harrod, Robert Skidelsky, Donald Moggridge and Donald Markwell.
Helena Vieira, writing for the London School of Economics, argued that classical liberalism "may contradict some fundamental democratic principles as they are inconsistent with the principle of unanimity (also known as the Pareto Principle) – the idea that if everyone in society prefers a policy A to a policy B, then the former should be adopted."{{Cite web |last=Vieira |first=Helena |date=2017-02-01 |title=The contradiction of classical liberalism and libertarianism |url=https://blogs.lse.ac.uk/businessreview/2017/02/01/the-contradiction-of-classical-liberalism-and-libertarianism/ |access-date=2023-07-03 |website=LSE Business Review}}
= Ottoman Empire =
The Ottoman Empire had liberal free trade policies by the 18th century, with origins in capitulations of the Ottoman Empire, dating back to the first commercial treaties signed with France in 1536 and taken further with capitulations in 1673, in 1740 which lowered duties to only 3% for imports and exports and in 1790. Ottoman free trade policies were praised by British economists advocating free trade such as J. R. McCulloch in his Dictionary of Commerce (1834) but criticized by British politicians opposing free trade such as Prime Minister Benjamin Disraeli, who cited the Ottoman Empire as "an instance of the injury done by unrestrained competition" in the 1846 Corn Laws debate, arguing that it destroyed what had been "some of the finest manufactures of the world" in 1812.{{cite book |author=Paul Bairoch |url=https://www.scribd.com/document/193124153/Economics-and-World-History-Myths-and-Paradoxes-Paul-Bairoch |title=Economics and World History: Myths and Paradoxes |publisher=University of Chicago Press |year=1995 |pages=31–32 |author-link=Paul Bairoch |access-date=2017-08-16 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171012060209/https://www.scribd.com/document/193124153/Economics-and-World-History-Myths-and-Paradoxes-Paul-Bairoch |archive-date=2017-10-12 |url-status=dead}}
= United States =
{{Liberalism US|schools}}
{{Libertarianism US|history}}
{{Conservatism US|principles}}
In the United States, liberalism took a strong root because it had little opposition to its ideals, whereas in Europe liberalism was opposed by many reactionary or feudal interests such as the nobility; the aristocracy, including army officers; the landed gentry; and the established church.{{cite book|first=Louis|last=Hartz|title=The Liberal Tradition in America|date=1955|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=e1bQY1CDx2IC&pg=PA3|chapter=The Concept of a Liberal Society|isbn=978-0156512695|publisher=Houghton Mifflin Harcourt|url=https://archive.org/details/liberaltradition00hart_0}} Thomas Jefferson adopted many of the ideals of liberalism, but in the Declaration of Independence changed Locke's "life, liberty and property" to the more socially liberal "Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness". As the United States grew, industry became a larger and larger part of American life; and during the term of its first populist President, Andrew Jackson, economic questions came to the forefront. The economic ideas of the Jacksonian era were almost universally the ideas of classical liberalism.{{cite book|author=Jeremy M. Brown|title=Explaining the Reagan Years in Central America: A World System Perspective|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=k9N1duU9zgMC&pg=PA25|year=1995|publisher=University Press of America|isbn=978-0819198136|page=25}} Freedom, according to classical liberals, was maximised when the government took a "hands off" attitude toward the economy.{{cite book|author=Paul Kahan|title=The Homestead Strike: Labor, Violence, and American Industry|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ctaTAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA28|year=2014|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-1136173974|page=28|quote=Called the "Jacksonian Era," this era was characterized by greater voting rights for white men, a hands-off approach to economic issues, and a desire to spread U.S. culture and government west (an outlook called "Manifest Destiny").}} Historian Kathleen G. Donohue argues:
[A]t the center of classical liberal theory [in Europe] was the idea of laissez-faire. To the vast majority of American classical liberals, however, laissez-faire did not mean no government intervention at all. On the contrary, they were more than willing to see government provide tariffs, railroad subsidies, and internal improvements, all of which benefited producers. What they condemned was intervention on behalf of consumers.{{cite book|author=Kathleen G. Donohue|title=Freedom from Want: American Liberalism and the Idea of the Consumer|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ud7TN4Asro8C&pg=PA2|year=2005|publisher=Johns Hopkins University Press|page=2|isbn=978-0801883910}}
The Nation magazine espoused liberalism every week starting in 1865 under the influential editor Edwin Lawrence Godkin (1831–1902).{{cite book|first=Gustav|last=Pollak|url=https://archive.org/details/fiftyyearsofamer00poll|title=Fifty Years of American Idealism: 1865–1915|date=1915|publisher=Houghton Mifflin Company}} The ideas of classical liberalism remained essentially unchallenged until a series of depressions, thought to be impossible according to the tenets of classical economics, led to economic hardship from which the voters demanded relief. In the words of William Jennings Bryan, "You shall not crucify this nation on a cross of gold". Classical liberalism remained the orthodox belief among American businessmen until the Great Depression.Eric Voegelin, Mary Algozin, and Keith Algozin, "Liberalism and Its History", Review of Politics 36, no. 4 (1974): 504–520. {{JSTOR|1406338}}. The Great Depression in the United States saw a sea change in liberalism, with priority shifting from the producers to consumers. Franklin D. Roosevelt's New Deal represented the dominance of modern liberalism in politics for decades. In the words of Arthur Schlesinger Jr.:Arthur Schelesinger Jr., [http://www.writing.upenn.edu/~afilreis/50s/schleslib.html "Liberalism in America: A Note for Europeans"] {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180212050753/http://www.writing.upenn.edu/~afilreis/50s/schleslib.html |date=12 February 2018}}, in The Politics of Hope (Boston: Riverside Press, 1962). {{blockquote|When the growing complexity of industrial conditions required increasing government intervention in order to assure more equal opportunities, the liberal tradition, faithful to the goal rather than to the dogma, altered its view of the state. ... There emerged the conception of a social welfare state, in which the national government had the express obligation to maintain high levels of employment in the economy, to supervise standards of life and labour, to regulate the methods of business competition, and to establish comprehensive patterns of social security.|sign=|source=}}
Alan Wolfe summarizes the viewpoint that there is a continuous liberal understanding that includes both Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes:
{{blockquote|The idea that liberalism comes in two forms assumes that the most fundamental question facing mankind is how much government intervenes into the economy. ... When instead we discuss human purpose and the meaning of life, Adam Smith and John Maynard Keynes are on the same side. Both of them possessed an expansive sense of what we are put on this earth to accomplish. ... For Smith, mercantilism was the enemy of human liberty. For Keynes, monopolies were. It makes perfect sense for an eighteenth-century thinker to conclude that humanity would flourish under the market. For a twentieth century thinker committed to the same ideal, government was an essential tool to the same end.{{cite magazine|first=Alan|last=Wolfe|url=http://www.tnr.com/blog/alan-wolfe/false-distinction|title=A False Distinction|magazine=The New Republic|date=12 April 2009|access-date=31 May 2010|archive-date=7 April 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200407070846/https://newrepublic.com/article/49001/false-distinction|url-status=live}}}}
The view that modern liberalism is a continuation of classical liberalism is controversial and disputed by many.{{cite book|author=D. Conway|title=Classical Liberalism: The Unvanquished Ideal|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=lvLMCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA26|year= 1998 |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan UK|isbn=978-0230371194|page=26}}{{cite web|url=http://reason.com/archives/2012/08/12/classical-liberalism-vs-modern-liberalis|title=Classical Liberalism vs. Modern Liberalism|last1=Richman|first1=Sheldon|date=12 August 2012|work=Reason|publisher=Reason Foundation|access-date=4 November 2016|archive-date=8 October 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181008084836/http://reason.com/archives/2012/08/12/classical-liberalism-vs-modern-liberalis|url-status=live}}{{cite web|url=http://haciendapublishing.com/articles/classical-liberalism-vs-modern-liberalism-socialism-%E2%80%94-primer|title=Classical Liberalism vs Modern Liberalism (Socialism) – A Primer|last1=Faria|first1=Miguel A. Jr.|date=21 March 2012|website=haciendapublishing.com|publisher=Hacienda Publishing|access-date=4 November 2016|archive-date=13 April 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190413153321/https://haciendapublishing.com/articles/classical-liberalism-vs-modern-liberalism-socialism-%E2%80%94-primer|url-status=dead}}{{cite book|author=Alan Ryan|title=The Making of Modern Liberalism|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KfpnzJuy1XcC&pg=PA23|year= 2012|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=978-1400841950|pages=23–26}}{{cite book|author=Andrew Heywood|title=Political Ideologies: An Introduction|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=poYdBQAAQBAJ&pg=PA59|year=2012|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|isbn=978-0230369948|page=59}}{{Dead link|date=December 2023 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes}} James Kurth, Robert E. Lerner, John Micklethwait, Adrian Wooldridge and several other political scholars have argued that classical liberalism still exists today, but in the form of American conservatism.{{cite book|author1=Nathan Schlueter|author2=Nikolai Wenzel|title=Selfish Libertarians and Socialist Conservatives?: The Foundations of the Libertarian–Conservative Debate|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=YKosDQAAQBAJ&pg=PA8|year= 2016|publisher =Stanford University Press|isbn=978-1503600294|page=8|quote=American conservatism is a form of classical liberalism.}}{{cite book|author1=John Micklethwait|author2=Adrian Wooldridge|title=The Right Nation: Conservative Power in America|url=https://archive.org/details/rightnationconse00mick|url-access=registration|year=2004|publisher=Penguin|isbn=978-1594200205|page=[https://archive.org/details/rightnationconse00mick/page/343 343]|quote=Whichever way you look at it, American conservatism has embraced a great chunk of classical liberalism-so much of it that many observers have argued that American conservatism was an oxymoron; that it is basically classical liberalism in disguise.}}{{cite book|author=James R. Kirth|author-link=James Kurth|editor=Sanford V. Levinson|others=Melissa S. Williams, Joel Parker|title=American Conservatism: NOMOS LVI|chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=XgrMCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA26|year=2016|publisher=NYU Press|isbn=978-1479865185|page=26|chapter=A History of Inherent Contradictions: The Origins and Ends of American Conservatism|quote=Of course, the original conservatives had not really been conservatives either. They were merely classical liberals. It seems to be the case in American that most so-called conservatives have really been something else. This has confused not only external observers of American conservatism (be they on the European Right or on the American Left), but it has confused American conservatives as well.}}{{cite book|author1=Robert Lerner|author2=Althea K. Nagai|author3=Stanley Rothman|title=American Elites|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=hvQ8D0Rp56UC&pg=PA41|year=1996|publisher=Yale University Press|isbn=978-0300065343|page=41|quote=Moreover, Americans do not use the term liberalism in the same way that Europeans do. In fact, classical European liberalism more closely resembles what we (and what Americans generally) call conservatism.}} According to Deepak Lal, only in the United States does classical liberalism continue to be a significant political force through American conservatism.{{cite book|author=Deepak Lal|title=Reviving the Invisible Hand: The Case for Classical Liberalism in the Twenty-first Century|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qU1f2XP_NfQC&pg=PA51|year= 2010|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=978-1400837441|page=51|quote=The major votaries of classical liberalism today are American conservatives. For as Hayek noted: "It is the doctrine on which the American system of government is based. "But, contemporary American conservatism is a novel brew which Micklethwait and Wooldridge rightly note is a mixture of the individualism of classical liberalism and "ubertraditionalism." It represents adherence to the bourgeois organization of society epitomized by that much-maligned word, "Victorian": with its faith in individualism, capitalism, progress, and virtue. Having been silenced by the seemingly endless march of "embedded liberalism" since the New Deal, American conservatism has, since the late 1960s, regrouped, and under Presidents Reagan and George W. Bush created a new powerful political movement. Thus, apart from the brief period of Margaret Thatcher's ascendancy in Britain, it is only in the United States that the classical liberal tradition continues to have political force.}} American libertarians also claim to be the true continuation of the classical liberal tradition.{{cite web |last1=McMaken |first1=Ryan |title='Libertarian' Is Just Another Word for (Classical) Liberal |url=https://mises.org/wire/libertarian-just-another-word-classical-liberal |website=Mises Wire |date=12 September 2019 |publisher=Mises Institute |access-date=6 November 2020}}
Tadd Wilson, writing for the libertarian Foundation for Economic Education, noted that "Many on the left and right criticize classical liberals for focusing purely on economics and politics to the neglect of a vital issue: culture."{{Cite web |last=Wilson |first=Tadd |date=1998-12-01 |title=The Culture of Classical Liberalism |url=https://fee.org/articles/the-culture-of-classical-liberalism/ |access-date=2023-07-03 |website=Foundation for Economic Education |language=en}}
Intellectual sources
= John Locke =
Central to classical liberal ideology was their interpretation of John Locke's Second Treatise of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration, which had been written as a defence of the Glorious Revolution of 1688. Although these writings were considered too radical at the time for Britain's new rulers, Whigs, radicals and supporters of the American Revolution later came to cite them.Steven M. Dworetz, The Unvarnished Doctrine: Locke, Liberalism, and the American Revolution (1989). However, much of later liberal thought was absent in Locke's writings or scarcely mentioned and his writings have been subject to various interpretations. For example, there is little mention of constitutionalism, the separation of powers and limited government.{{sfn|Richardson|pp=22–23}}
James L. Richardson identified five central themes in Locke's writing:
- Individualism
- Consent
- Rule of law and government as trustee
- Significance of property
- Religious toleration
Although Locke did not develop a theory of natural rights, he envisioned individuals in the state of nature as being free and equal. The individual, rather than the community or institutions, was the point of reference. Locke believed that individuals had given consent to government and therefore authority derived from the people rather than from above. This belief would influence later revolutionary movements.{{sfn|Richardson|p=23}}
As a trustee, government was expected to serve the interests of the people, not the rulers; and rulers were expected to follow the laws enacted by legislatures. Locke also held that the main purpose of men uniting into commonwealths and governments was for the preservation of their property. Despite the ambiguity of Locke's definition of property, which limited property to "as much land as a man tills, plants, improves, cultivates, and can use the product of", this principle held great appeal to individuals possessed of great wealth.{{sfn|Richardson|pp=23–24}}
Locke held that the individual had the right to follow his own religious beliefs and that the state should not impose a religion against Dissenters, but there were limitations. No tolerance should be shown for atheists, who were seen as amoral, or to Catholics, who were seen as owing allegiance to the Pope over their own national government.{{sfn|Richardson|p=24}}
= Adam Smith =
Adam Smith's The Wealth of Nations, published in 1776, was to provide most of the ideas of economics, at least until the publication of John Stuart Mill's Principles of Political Economy in 1848.{{sfn|Mills|pp=63, 68}} Smith addressed the motivation for economic activity, the causes of prices and the distribution of wealth and the policies the state should follow to maximise wealth.{{sfn|Mills|p=64}}
Smith wrote that as long as supply, demand, prices and competition were left free of government regulation, the pursuit of material self-interest, rather than altruism, would maximise the wealth of a society through profit-driven production of goods and services. An "invisible hand" directed individuals and firms to work toward the public good as an unintended consequence of efforts to maximise their own gain. This provided a moral justification for the accumulation of wealth, which had previously been viewed by some as sinful.{{sfn|Mills|p=64}}
He assumed that workers could be paid wages as low as was necessary for their survival, which was later transformed by David Ricardo and Thomas Robert Malthus into the "iron law of wages".{{sfn|Mills|p=65}} His main emphasis was on the benefit of free internal and international trade, which he thought could increase wealth through specialisation in production.{{sfn|Mills|p=66}} He also opposed restrictive trade preferences, state grants of monopolies and employers' organisations and trade unions.{{sfn|Mills|p=67}} Government should be limited to defence, public works and the administration of justice, financed by taxes based on income.{{sfn|Mills|p=68}}
Smith's economics was carried into practice in the nineteenth century with the lowering of tariffs in the 1820s, the repeal of the Poor Relief Act that had restricted the mobility of labour in 1834 and the end of the rule of the East India Company over India in 1858.{{sfn|Mills|p=69}}
{{clear left}}
= Classical economics =
In addition to Smith's legacy, Say's law, Thomas Robert Malthus' theories of population and David Ricardo's iron law of wages became central doctrines of classical economics. The pessimistic nature of these theories provided a basis for criticism of capitalism by its opponents and helped perpetuate the tradition of calling economics the "dismal science".{{sfn|Mills|p=76}}
Jean-Baptiste Say was a French economist who introduced Smith's economic theories into France and whose commentaries on Smith were read in both France and Britain.{{sfn|Mills|p=69}} Say challenged Smith's labour theory of value, believing that prices were determined by utility and also emphasised the critical role of the entrepreneur in the economy. However, neither of those observations became accepted by British economists at the time. His most important contribution to economic thinking was Say's law, which was interpreted by classical economists that there could be no overproduction in a market and that there would always be a balance between supply and demand.{{sfn|Mills|p=70}}{{cite journal|first1=Mark|last1=Blaug|title=Say's Law of Markets: What Did It Mean and Why Should We Care?|url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/40325773|journal=Eastern Economic Journal|date=1997|issn=0094-5056|pages=231–235|volume=23|issue=2|jstor=40325773}} This general belief influenced government policies until the 1930s. Following this law, since the economic cycle was seen as self-correcting, government did not intervene during periods of economic hardship because it was seen as futile.{{sfn|Mills|p=71}}
Malthus wrote two books, An Essay on the Principle of Population (published in 1798) and Principles of Political Economy (published in 1820). The second book which was a rebuttal of Say's law had little influence on contemporary economists.{{sfn|Mills|pp=71–72}} However, his first book became a major influence on classical liberalism.{{cite book|first1=Ashleigh|last1=Campi|first2=Lindsay|last2=Scorgie-Porter|title=An Analysis of John Stuart Mill's On Liberty|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qjQuDwAAQBAJ|publisher=CRC Press|year= 2017|isbn=978-1351352581|via=Google Books}}{{sfn|Mills|p=72}} In that book, Malthus claimed that population growth would outstrip food production because population grew geometrically while food production grew arithmetically. As people were provided with food, they would reproduce until their growth outstripped the food supply. Nature would then provide a check to growth in the forms of vice and misery. No gains in income could prevent this and any welfare for the poor would be self-defeating. The poor were in fact responsible for their own problems which could have been avoided through self-restraint.{{sfn|Mills|p=72}}
Ricardo, who was an admirer of Smith, covered many of the same topics, but while Smith drew conclusions from broadly empirical observations he used deduction, drawing conclusions by reasoning from basic assumptions.{{sfn|Mills|pp=73–74}} While Ricardo accepted Smith's labour theory of value, he acknowledged that utility could influence the price of some rare items. Rents on agricultural land were seen as the production that was surplus to the subsistence required by the tenants. Wages were seen as the amount required for workers' subsistence and to maintain current population levels.{{sfn|Mills|pp=74–75}} According to his iron law of wages, wages could never rise beyond subsistence levels. Ricardo explained profits as a return on capital, which itself was the product of labour, but a conclusion many drew from his theory was that profit was a surplus appropriated by capitalists to which they were not entitled.{{sfn|Mills|p=75}}
= Utilitarianism =
The central concept of utilitarianism, which was developed by Jeremy Bentham, was that public policy should seek to provide "the greatest happiness of the greatest number". While this could be interpreted as a justification for state action to reduce poverty, it was used by classical liberals to justify inaction with the argument that the net benefit to all individuals would be higher.{{sfn|Mills|p=76}}
Utilitarianism provided British governments with the political justification to implement economic liberalism, which was to dominate economic policy from the 1830s. Although utilitarianism prompted legislative and administrative reform and John Stuart Mill's later writings on the subject foreshadowed the welfare state, it was mainly used as a justification for laissez-faire.{{sfn|Richardson|p=32}}
Political economy
Classical liberals following Mill saw utility as the foundation for public policies. This broke both with conservative "tradition" and Lockean "natural rights", which were seen as irrational. Utility, which emphasises the happiness of individuals, became the central ethical value of all Mill-style liberalism.{{sfn|Richardson|p=31}} Although utilitarianism inspired wide-ranging reforms, it became primarily a justification for laissez-faire economics. However, Mill adherents rejected Smith's belief that the "invisible hand" would lead to general benefits and embraced Malthus' view that population expansion would prevent any general benefit and Ricardo's view of the inevitability of class conflict. Laissez-faire was seen as the only possible economic approach and any government intervention was seen as useless and harmful. The Poor Law Amendment Act 1834 was defended on "scientific or economic principles" while the authors of the Poor Relief Act 1601 were seen as not having had the benefit of reading Malthus.{{sfn|Richardson|p=33}}
However, commitment to laissez-faire was not uniform and some economists advocated state support of public works and education. Classical liberals were also divided on free trade as Ricardo expressed doubt that the removal of grain tariffs advocated by Richard Cobden and the Anti-Corn Law League would have any general benefits. Most classical liberals also supported legislation to regulate the number of hours that children were allowed to work and usually did not oppose factory reform legislation.{{sfn|Richardson|p=33}}
Despite the pragmatism of classical economists, their views were expressed in dogmatic terms by such popular writers as Jane Marcet and Harriet Martineau.{{sfn|Richardson|p=33}} The strongest defender of laissez-faire was The Economist founded by James Wilson in 1843. The Economist criticised Ricardo for his lack of support for free trade and expressed hostility to welfare, believing that the lower orders were responsible for their economic circumstances. The Economist took the position that regulation of factory hours was harmful to workers and also strongly opposed state support for education, health, the provision of water, and granting of patents and copyrights.{{sfn|Richardson|p=34}}
The Economist also campaigned against the Corn Laws that protected landlords in the United Kingdom of Great Britain and Ireland against competition from less expensive foreign imports of cereal products. A rigid belief in laissez-faire guided the government response in 1846–1849 to the Great Famine in Ireland, during which an estimated 1.5 million people died. The minister responsible for economic and financial affairs, Charles Wood, expected that private enterprise and free trade, rather than government intervention, would alleviate the famine.{{sfn|Richardson|p=34}} The Corn Laws were finally repealed in 1846 by the removal of tariffs on grain which kept the price of bread artificially high,George Miller. On Fairness and Efficiency. The Policy Press, 2000. {{ISBN|978-1861342218}} p. 344. but it came too late to stop the Irish famine, partly because it was done in stages over three years.Christine Kinealy. A Death-Dealing Famine:The Great Hunger in Ireland. Pluto Press, 1997. {{ISBN|978-0745310749}}. p. 59.Stephen J. Lee. Aspects of British Political History, 1815–1914. Routledge, 1994. {{ISBN|978-0415090063}}. p. 83.
Many classical liberal theorists were skeptical of democracy, believing that poor, uneducated people were not capable of governing and they might vote against economically liberal principles.{{cite book |last1=Mackert |first1=Jürgen |title=The Condition of Democracy: Volume 3: Postcolonial and Settler Colonial Contexts |date=12 July 2021 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-000-40193-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=o0QvEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2013 |language=en |chapter=A ‘master-race democracy’: Myths and lies of Western liberal civilization|location=Liberalism as anti-democratic}} The skepticism about self-governance was even more pronounced when it came to "uncivilized", non-European societies, with many classical liberal thinkers providing intellectual justifications for white supremacy, colonial rule, and the destruction of native societies via settler colonialism.{{sfn|Mackert|2021|loc=Great liberal minds: the men who believed in barbarism}}
= Free trade and world peace =
{{main|Capitalist peace}}
Several liberals, including Smith and Cobden, argued that the free exchange of goods between nations could lead to world peace. Erik Gartzke states: "Scholars like Montesquieu, Adam Smith, Richard Cobden, Norman Angell, and Richard Rosecrance have long speculated that free markets have the potential to free states from the looming prospect of recurrent warfare".Erik Gartzke, "Economic Freedom and Peace," in Economic Freedom of the World: 2005 Annual Report (Vancouver: Fraser Institute, 2005). American political scientists John R. Oneal and Bruce M. Russett, well known for their work on the democratic peace theory, state:{{cite journal|first1=J. R.|first2=B. M.|title=The Classical Liberals Were Right: Democracy, Interdependence, and Conflict, 1950–1985|journal=International Studies Quarterly|volume=41|issue=2|pages=267–294|year=1997|last1=Oneal|doi=10.1111/1468-2478.00042|last2=Russet|doi-access=free}} {{blockquote|The classical liberals advocated policies to increase liberty and prosperity. They sought to empower the commercial class politically and to abolish royal charters, monopolies, and the protectionist policies of mercantilism so as to encourage entrepreneurship and increase productive efficiency. They also expected democracy and laissez-faire economics to diminish the frequency of war.}}
In The Wealth of Nations, Smith argued that as societies progressed from hunter gatherers to industrial societies the spoils of war would rise, but that the costs of war would rise further and thus making war difficult and costly for industrialised nations:Michael Doyle, Ways of War and Peace: Realism, Liberalism, and Socialism (New York: Norton, 1997), p. 237. {{ISBN|0393969479}}. {{blockquote|[T]he honours, the fame, the emoluments of war, belong not to [the middle and industrial classes]; the battle-plain is the harvest field of the aristocracy, watered with the blood of the people. ... Whilst our trade rested upon our foreign dependencies, as was the case in the middle of the last century...force and violence, were necessary to command our customers for our manufacturers...But war, although the greatest of consumers, not only produces nothing in return, but, by abstracting labour from productive employment and interrupting the course of trade, it impedes, in a variety of indirect ways, the creation of wealth; and, should hostilities be continued for a series of years, each successive war-loan will be felt in our commercial and manufacturing districts with an augmented pressure|Richard CobdenEdward P. Stringham, [https://ssrn.com/abstract=1676244 "Commerce, Markets, and Peace: Richard Cobden's Enduring Lessons"], Independent Review 9, no. 1 (2004): 105, 110, 115.|source=}}
{{blockquote|[B]y virtue of their mutual interest does nature unite people against violence and war, for the concept of cosmopolitan right does not protect them from it. The spirit of trade cannot coexist with war, and sooner or later this spirit dominates every people. For among all those powers (or means) that belong to a nation, financial power may be the most reliable in forcing nations to pursue the noble cause of peace (though not from moral motives); and wherever in the world war threatens to break out, they will try to head it off through mediation, just as if they were permanently leagued for this purpose.|Immanuel KantImmanuel Kant, The Perpetual Peace.}}
Cobden believed that military expenditures worsened the welfare of the state and benefited a small, but concentrated elite minority, summing up British imperialism, which he believed was the result of the economic restrictions of mercantilist policies. To Cobden and many classical liberals, those who advocated peace must also advocate free markets. The belief that free trade would promote peace was widely shared by English liberals of the 19th and early 20th century, leading the economist John Maynard Keynes (1883–1946), who was a classical liberal in his early life, to say that this was a doctrine on which he was "brought up" and which he held unquestioned only until the 1920s.Donald Markwell, [http://global.oup.com/academic/product/john-maynard-keynes-and-international-relations-9780198292364;jsessionid=4B0FEAE67C6CC2944F0147AFD5045F62?cc=au&lang=en& John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace] {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170901225622/https://global.oup.com/academic/product/john-maynard-keynes-and-international-relations-9780198292364;jsessionid=4B0FEAE67C6CC2944F0147AFD5045F62?cc=au&lang=en& |date=1 September 2017}}, Oxford University Press, 2006, ch. 1. In his review of a book on Keynes, Michael S. Lawlor argues that it may be in large part due to Keynes' contributions in economics and politics, as in the implementation of the Marshall Plan and the way economies have been managed since his work, "that we have the luxury of not facing his unpalatable choice between free trade and full employment".[https://eh.net/book_reviews/john-maynard-keynes-and-international-relations-economic-paths-to-war-and-peace/ John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace] {{webarchive |url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171005051008/https://eh.net/book_reviews/john-maynard-keynes-and-international-relations-economic-paths-to-war-and-peace/ |date=5 October 2017}} Donald Markwell (2006), reviewed by M S Lawlor (February 2008). A related manifestation of this idea was the argument of Norman Angell (1872–1967), most famously before World War I in The Great Illusion (1909), that the interdependence of the economies of the major powers was now so great that war between them was futile and irrational; and therefore unlikely.
Notable thinkers
{{see also|List of liberal theorists}}
{{Original research|date=September 2023|reason=}}{{div col|colwidth=33em}}
- Thomas HobbesLucien Jaume, "Hobbes and the Philosophical Sources of Liberalism", The Cambridge Companion to Hobbes' Leviathan, 211 (1588–1679)
- James Harrington (1611–1677)
- John Locke (1632–1704)
- Montesquieu (1689–1755)
- David Hume (1711–1776)
- Voltaire (1694–1778)
- Benjamin Franklin (1706–1790)
- Adam Smith (1723–1790)
- Edmund Burke (1729–1797)
- Edward Gibbon (1737–1794)
- Immanuel Kant (1724–1804)
- Anders Chydenius (1729–1803)
- Thomas Paine (1737–1809)
- Cesare Beccaria (1738–1794)
- Marquis de Condorcet (1743–1794)
- Thomas Jefferson (1743–1826)
- Jeremy Bentham (1748–1832)
- Gaetano Filangieri (1753–1788)
- Benjamin Constant (1767–1830)
- David Ricardo (1772–1823)
- Alexis de Tocqueville (1805–1859)
- Giuseppe Mazzini (1805–1872){{cite book |editor=Bertrand Badie |editor2=Dirk Berg-Schlosser |editor3=Leonardo Morlino |title=International Encyclopedia of Political Science |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Vn2iCQAAQBAJ&dq=classical+liberal+Giuseppe+Mazzini&pg=PT1811 |quote= ... thought of classical liberal figures such as John Locke, Adam Smith, Immanuel Kant, Giuseppe Mazzini, and John Stuart Mill. ...|date=2011 |page=44 |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-1483305394}}
- John Stuart Mill (1806–1872)
- William Ewart Gladstone{{cite news |title=Liberalism rediscovered |url=http://www.economist.com/node/112302 |date=5 February 1998 |access-date=28 June 2017 |magazine=The Economist}} (1809–1898)
- Horace Greeley (1811–1873)
- Fukuzawa Yukichi{{cite book |author=James Mark Shields |date=2017 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ce10DgAAQBAJ&pg=PA160 |title=Against Harmony: Progressive and Radical Buddhism in Modern Japan |publisher=Oxford University Press |page=169 |isbn=9780190664008}} (1835–1901)
- Henry George (1839–1897)
- Friedrich Naumann{{cite book |author=Robert Leeson |date=2018 |title=Hayek: A Collaborative Biography: Part XI: Orwellian Rectifiers, Mises' 'Evil Seed' of Christianity and the 'Free' Market Welfare State Archival Insights into the Evolution of Economics |publisher=Springer |page=468 |quote=Friedrich Naumann was regarded as a classical liberal while also promoting National Socialism |isbn=9783319774282}}{{cite book |author1=P. G. C. van Schie |author2=Gerrit Voermann |date=2006 |title=The Dividing Line Between Success and Failure: A Comparison of Liberalism in the Netherlands and Germany in the 19th and 20th Centuries |publisher=LIT Verlag Münsters |page=64 |quote=By the turn of the century, the left liberals Friedrich Naumann and Barth sought to redefine classical liberalism for the needs of the rising industrial society.}} (1860–1919)
- Ludwig Von Mises (1881–1973)
- Friedrich Hayek (1899–1992)
- Karl Popper{{cite book |date=2015 |title=After the Soviet Empire: Legacies and Pathways |publisher=BRILL |page=143 |quote=They had all forgotten that the classical liberal Karl Popper was definitely opposed to the big bang of rapid changes in whole societal systems. He assumed that changes of this type were bound to cause massive human suffering. |isbn=9789004291454}}{{cite book |author=Walter B. Weimer |date=2022 |title=Retrieving Liberalism from Rationalist Constructivism, Volume II: Basics of a Liberal Psychological, Social and Moral Order |publisher=Springer Nature |page=255 |isbn=9783030954772}}{{cite book |author=Christian Delacampagne |date=2022 |title=A History of Philosophy in the Twentieth Century |publisher=JHU Press |page=255 |quote=Among these figures one finds two defenders of the classical liberal tradition, Karl Popper and Raymond Aron; ... |isbn=9780801868146}} (1902–1994)
- Raymond Aron (1905–1983)
- Milton Friedman (1912–2006)
- Robert Nozick{{cite book |author=John Gray |date=2018 |title=Liberalisms: Essays in Political Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |isbn=9780415563758}} (1938–2002)
{{div col end}}
Classical liberal parties worldwide
While general libertarian,{{efn|Example: the U.S. Libertarian Party, KORWiN, etc.}} liberal-conservative{{efn|Example: the Christian Democratic Union of Germany, Les Républicains, etc.}} and some right-wing populist{{efn|Example: Progress Party (Norway), People's Party of Canada, enc.}} political parties are also included in classical liberal parties in a broad sense, only general classical liberal parties such as Germany's FDP, Denmark's Liberal Alliance and Thailand Democrat Party should be listed.
= Classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions =
{{div col|colwidth=32em}}
- Argentina: Republican Proposal, Liberty Advances,{{cite web |url=https://www.lanacion.com.ar/economia/punto-por-punto-el-plan-de-gobierno-que-presento-javier-milei-nid02082023/ |title=Punto por punto: el plan de gobierno que presentó Javier Milei |date=4 August 2023}}
- Australia: Liberal Party of Australia,{{cite book |first=Kuo-Tsai |last=Liou |title=Handbook of Economic Development |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cxxJkKYAzioC&pg=PA357 |year=1998 |publisher=CRC Press |isbn=978-1461671756 |page=357}} Libertarian Party{{cite web |url=https://www.spectator.co.uk/australia/australia-features/9029251/in-praise-of-the-liberal-democrats/ |title=In praise of Australia's Liberal Democrats » The Spectator}}
- Austria: NEOS – The New Austria and Liberal Forum, Freedom Party of Austria (factions)
- Belgium: Open Flemish Liberals and Democrats, Reformist Movement
- Brazil: New Party{{cite web |url=https://novo.org.br/novo/posicionamentos/|title=Posicionamentos}}
- Canada: Liberal Party, Conservative Party (factions), Libertarian Party, People's Party{{cite web|url=https://www.cbc.ca/news/politics/liberals-conservatives-people-s-1.4822178|title=Maxime Bernier's new party stakes out classical liberal values: Don Pittis|access-date=21 July 2022|archive-date=23 May 2022|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220523030442/https://www.cbc.ca/news/politics/liberals-conservatives-people-s-1.4822178|url-status=live}}
- Chile: Evópoli{{cite web|url=https://www.evopoli.cl/un-manifiesto-liberal/|title=Un manifiesto liberal|date=24 September 2018}}
- Denmark: {{Lang|da|Venstre|italic=no}},{{cite book|editor=Thomas J. DiLorenzo |title=The Problem with Socialism |date=2016 |page=82 |publisher=Simon and Schuster}} Moderates, Liberal Alliance{{cite book|editor=Marco Lisi |title=Party System Change, the European Crisis and the State of Democracy |date=2018 |publisher=Routledge}}{{cite book|editor=Mark Salmon, Culture Smart! |title=Denmark – Culture Smart!: The Essential Guide to Customs & Culture |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=WuiIDwAAQBAJ&dq=classical+liberal+Liberal+Alliance&pg=PT37 |quote= Liberal Alliance Formerly New Alliance, Liberal Alliance are a center right, classical liberal party formed in 2007 by former members of the Social Liberal Party and the Conservative People's Party. |date=2019 |publisher=Kuperard|isbn=978-1787029187}}
- Estonia: Estonian Reform Party{{cite book |editor=Arturo Bris |title=The Right Place: How National Competitiveness Makes or Breaks Companies |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9fMxEAAAQBAJ&dq=Iceland+classical+liberal+Reform+Party&pg=PT314 |date=2021 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1000327793}}
- Finland: Liberal Party – Freedom to Choose
- France: Renaissance{{cite book|editor=Christopher J. Bickerton, Carlo Invernizzi Accetti |title=Technopopulism: The New Logic of Democratic Politics |date=2021 |page=60 |publisher=Oxford University Press}}{{cite news|url=https://www.thedailybeast.com/macron-scrambling-to-salvage-liberal-reputation-worldwide-after-targeting-islam |title=Macron Scrambling to Salvage Liberal Reputation Worldwide After Targeting Islam |work=The Daily Beast |date=12 November 2020 |access-date=11 December 2021}}{{cite book|editor=Slavoj Zizek |title=Like a Thief in Broad Daylight: Power in the Era of Post-Human Capitalism |date=2019 |publisher=Seven Stories Press}}{{cite book|editor=William Smaldone |title=European Socialism: A Concise History with Documents |date=2019 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefields}}
- Georgia: Girchi — More Freedom,{{cite web |url=https://www.aldeparty.eu/girchi_more_freedom |title=Girchi-More Freedom |publisher=aldeparty.eu }}{{Dead link|date=May 2025 |bot=InternetArchiveBot |fix-attempted=yes }} Girchi
- Germany: Free Democratic Party{{cite book|editor=Brian Duignan|title=The Science and Philosophy of Politics|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ye-cAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA121|year=2013|publisher=Britannica Educational Publishing|isbn=978-1615307487|page=121}}
- Iceland: Viðreisn
- India: Lok Satta Party{{cite web|url=http://www.loksatta.org/loksatta-government-people|title=Loksatta - Government 'by' the people|website=Loksatta Party|access-date=2016-04-11|archive-date=15 March 2018|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180315001151/http://www.loksatta.org/loksatta-government-people|url-status=dead}}
- India: Swatantra Bharat Paksh{{Cite web |title=Why SBP – Swatantra Bharat Party |url=https://www.swatantra.org.in/why-swarna-bharat-party/ |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240302000051/https://www.swatantra.org.in/why-swarna-bharat-party/ |archive-date=2024-03-02 |access-date=2024-10-26 |language=en-US}}
- Latvia: For Latvia's Development, Movement For!
- Lithuania: Liberals' Movement
- Luxembourg: Democratic Party
- Netherlands: People's Party for Freedom and Democracy, Belang van Nederland
- New Zealand: New Zealand National Party,{{cite book|editor=Natacha Gagné |title=Being M?ori in the City: Indigenous Everyday Life in Auckland |date=2013 |page=3 |publisher=University of Toronto Press}} ACT New Zealand{{cite speech|title=Our classical liberal tribe|url=http://www.act.org.nz/posts/speech-our-classical-liberal-tribe|website=www.act.org.nz|publisher=ACT New Zealand|access-date=8 February 2017|date=23 February 2015|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170211075239/http://www.act.org.nz/posts/speech-our-classical-liberal-tribe|archive-date=11 February 2017|url-status=dead}}
- Norway: {{Lang|no|Venstre|italic=no}},{{cite book|author=Jens Rydström|title=Odd Couples: A History of Gay Marriage in Scandinavia|url=https://library.oapen.org/bitstream/handle/20.500.12657/34648/381654.pdf;jsessionid=DE789FAC51B1C4767310C2A1E0FFCE91?sequence=1|page=97|date=2011|publisher=aksant|isbn=9789052603810}} Progress Party
- Poland: Modern,{{cite book |editor=Marek Payerhin |title=Nordic, Central, and Southeastern Europe 2016–2017 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-v_lDAAAQBAJ&dq=classical+liberal+Nowoczesna+Poland&pg=PA339 |quote= Another new movement was the Modern of Ryszard Petru, later styled as Modern (Nowoczesna) or simply ".N." This classical liberal party created by an economist, Ryszard Petru, received 7.6% of votes and 28 seats in the Sejm (it later gained an additional deputy who left Kukiz'15) |date=2016 |page=339 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield|isbn=978-1475828979}} Civic Platform{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=S8ICDAAAQBAJ&q=%22Civic&pg=PA207|author=Alan G. Smith|title=A Comparative Introduction to Political Science: Contention and Cooperation|publisher=Rowman & Littlefield|year=2016|page=207|isbn=9781442252608}}
- Portugal: Liberal Initiative, {{cite web |url=https://observador.pt/programas/emissao-especial/il-nao-ganhou-estas-eleicoes-mas-ganhou-o-futuro/ |title=Cotrim Figueiredo: Iniciativa Liberal "não ganhou estas eleições mas ganhou o futuro" |website=Observador.pt}} Social Democratic Party
- Romania: National Liberal Party
- Russia: Yabloko, PARNAS
- Serbia: Liberal Democratic Party of Serbia
- Slovakia: Freedom and Solidarity{{cite web|work=Online-Slovakia|title=Political parties and elections in Slovakia|accessdate=3 April 2018|url=http://www.online-slovakia.com/politics/elections.html|archive-date=6 October 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231006230227/http://www.online-slovakia.com/politics/elections.html|url-status=dead}}{{cite web|url=http://www.efddgroup.eu/images/publications/Who_Is_Who.pdf|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20190328224828/http://www.efddgroup.eu/images/publications/Who_Is_Who.pdf|archivedate=28 March 2019|quote=Freedom and Solidarity (Slovak: Sloboda a Solidarita, SaS): Limited government, EU-sceptic, Euro-critical, classical-Liberal/Libertarian|title=Who is Who? On the EU-Critical Right of Centre|work=Europe of Freedom and Direct Democracy|page=43|year=2018}}
- South Africa: Democratic Alliance,{{cite journal|url=http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/78243/3/Manuscript-Ideology%20and%20the%20good%20society%20in%20South%20Africa-%20The%20education%20policies%20of%20the%20Democratic%20Alliance.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190819072334/http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/78243/3/Manuscript-Ideology%20and%20the%20good%20society%20in%20South%20Africa-%20The%20education%20policies%20of%20the%20Democratic%20Alliance.pdf |archive-date=2019-08-19 |url-status=live|title=Ideology and the good society in South Africa: the education policies of the Democratic Alliance|author=Yusuf Sayed and Robert Van Niekerk|journal=Southern African Review of Education, 23 (1)|pages=52–69|issn=1563-4418}} ActionSA{{Cite web |title=South Africa • Africa Elects |url=https://africaelects.com/south-africa/ |access-date=21 January 2025 |website=Africa Elects |language=en}}
- Spain: Citizens, People's Party
- Sweden: Liberals,{{cite web|url=https://www.sv.se/globalassets/sv-region-skane/dokument/liberalismens-grundvarden.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200808040019/https://www.sv.se/globalassets/sv-region-skane/dokument/liberalismens-grundvarden.pdf |archive-date=2020-08-08 |url-status=live|title=Liberalismens grundvärden|website=Sv.se|access-date=21 February 2022}} Classical Liberal Party, Moderate Party
- Switzerland: FDP.The Liberals
- Thailand: Democrat Party{{Citation |first=Evan S. |last=Medeiros |title=Pacific Currents: The Responses of U.S. Allies and Security Partners in East Asia to China's Rise |publisher=RAND |year=2008 |page=130}}
- Turkey: Liberal Democratic Party
- United Kingdom: Liberal Democrats, Liberal Party,{{cite web|url=https://liberal.org.uk/introduction-to-the-liberal-party-policies/|title=Introduction to The Liberal Party Policies|website=liberal.org.uk|access-date=12 July 2022|archive-date=24 May 2022|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220524051332/https://liberal.org.uk/introduction-to-the-liberal-party-policies/|url-status=live}} Conservative Party (factions)
- United States: Democratic Party (factions), Republican Party (factions), Liberal Party USA, Libertarian Party
- Venezuela: Come Venezuela{{Cite web|url=https://www.ventevenezuela.org/nosotros/|title=Nosotros|date=23 May 2023}}
{{div col end}}
= Historical classical liberal parties or parties with classical liberal factions (since 1900s) =
{{div col|colwidth=32em}}
- Belgium: Liberal Party, Party for Freedom and Progress, Liberal Reformist Party
- Chile: Liberal Party, Amplitude
- Germany: German Democratic Party{{cite book |last=Mommsen |first=Hans |author-link=Hans Mommsen |year=1996 |title=The Rise and Fall of Weimar Democracy |publisher=University of North Carolina Press |page=[https://archive.org/details/risefallweimarde00momm/page/n76 58] |isbn=0807822493 |url=https://archive.org/details/risefallweimarde00momm |url-access=limited}}
- India: Swatantra Party,{{cite book|title=The Elephant Paradigm|page=244|year=2002|publisher=Penguin|first=Gurcharan|last=Das}} Indian Liberal Party{{cite journal|last=Smith|first=Ray T.|title=The Role of India's Liberals in the Nationalist Movement, 1915–1947|jstor=2642630|journal=Asian Survey|volume=8|issue=7|date=July 1968|pages=607–624 |doi=10.2307/2642630}}
- Ireland: Progressive Democrats
- Japan: Liberal Party (1998), Liberal League
- Netherlands: Freedom Party
- New Zealand: New Zealand Liberal Party, United Party, New Zealand Party
- South Korea: New Democratic Party
- Switzerland: Free Democratic Party of Switzerland,{{cite book|author1=Jan-Erik Lane|author2=Svante O. Ersson|title=Politics and Society in Western Europe|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Qw62oX96310C&pg=PA101|access-date=19 July 2013|year=1999|publisher=Sage Publications|isbn=978-0761958628|page=101}} Liberal Party of Switzerland
- United Kingdom: Liberal PartyThe Times (31 December 1872), p. 5.
{{div col end}}
See also
{{Portal|Liberalism|Politics}}
{{div col|colwidth=20em}}
- Age of Enlightenment
- Austrian School
- Bourbon Democrat
- National Democratic Party
- Classical economics
- Cultural liberalism
- Classical radicalism
- Modern liberalism
- Classical republicanism
- Constitutionalism
- Constitutional liberalism
- Conservative liberalism
- Corporate liberalism
- Economic liberalism
- Fiscal conservatism
- Friedrich Naumann Foundation
- Georgism
- Gladstonian liberalism
- Jeffersonian democracy
- Liberal conservatism
- Liberal democracy
- Liberalism in Europe
- Libertarianism
- Left-libertarianism
- Right-libertarianism
- List of liberal theorists
- Neoclassical liberalism
- Neoliberalism
- Night-watchman state
- Opportunist Republicans
- Orléanist
- Physiocracy
- Political individualism
- Rule of law
- Separation of powers
- Whig history
{{div col end}}
Notes
{{notelist}}
References
{{reflist|30em}}
Sources
{{refbegin|30em}}
- {{cite encyclopedia|last=Conway|first=David|title=Liberalism, Classical |author-link=David Conway (academic)|editor-first=Ronald|editor-last=Hamowy|editor-link=Ronald Hamowy|encyclopedia=The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yxNgXs3TkJYC|pages=295–298|doi=10.4135/9781412965811.n179|year=2008|publisher=Sage; Cato Institute|location=Thousand Oaks, CA|isbn=978-1412965804|oclc=750831024|lccn=2008009151|ref=CITEREFConway|access-date=27 January 2016|archive-date=9 January 2023|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230109234738/https://books.google.com/books?id=yxNgXs3TkJYC|url-status=live|url-access=subscription}}
- {{cite book|first=Guido|last=De Ruggiero|author-link=Guido De Ruggiero|title=The History of European Liberalism|location=Boston|publisher=Beacon Press|year=1959|ref=CITEREFDe_Ruggiero}}
- {{cite book|first1=M. O.|last1=Dickerson|first2=Thomas|last2=Flanagan|first3=Brenda|last3=O'Neill|title=An Introduction to Government and Politics: A Conceptual Approach|year=2009|publisher=Cengage Learning|isbn=978-0176500429|ref=CITEREFDickersonFlanaganO'Neill|url=https://archive.org/details/introductiontogo0000dick_h1m6}}
- {{cite book|author-link=John Gray (philosopher)|first=John|last=Gray|year=1995|title=Liberalism|location=Minneapolis|publisher=University of Minnesota Press|isbn=0816628009|ref=CITEREFGray}}
- {{cite book|last=Heywood|first=Andrew|year=2004|title=Political Theory, Third Edition: An Introduction|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|isbn=0333961803}}
- {{cite book|first=E. K.|last=Hunt|year=2003|title=Property and Prophets: The Evolution of Economic Institutions and Ideologies|location=New York|publisher=M. E. Sharpe, Inc.|isbn=0765606089|ref=CITEREFHunt}}
- {{cite book|first1=John T.|last1=Ishiyama|author-link1=John Ishiyama|first2=Marijike|last2=Breuning|year=2010|title=21st Century Political Science: A Reference Handbook|volume=1|location=London|publisher=Sage Publications|isbn=978-1412969017|ref=CITEREFIshiyamaBreuning}}
- {{cite book|author-link=Francis Lieber|first=Francis|last=Lieber|title=The Miscellaneous Writings of Francis Lieber, Volume II: Contributions to Political Science|url=https://archive.org/details/miscellaneouswri01lieb|location=Philadelphia|publisher=J. B. Lippincott & Co.|year=1881|ref=CITEREFLieber}}
- {{cite book|first=John|last=Mills|year=2002|title=A Critical History of Economics|location=Basingstoke, England|publisher=Palgrave Macmillan|isbn=0333971302|ref=CITEREFMills}}
- {{cite book|first=James L.|last=Richardson|year=2001|title=Contending Liberalisms in World Politics: Ideology and Power|location=Boulder, Colorado|publisher=Lynne Rienner Publishers|isbn=155587939X|ref=CITEREFRichardson}}
- {{cite book|last=Turner|first=Rachel S.|year=2008|title=Neo-Liberal Ideology: History, Concepts and Policies: History, Concepts and Policies|location=Edinburgh|publisher=Edinburgh University Press|isbn=978-0748632350}}
- {{cite book|last=Van de Haar|first=Edwin|year=2015|title=Degrees of Freedom: Liberal Political Philosophy and Ideology|location=New Brunswick, NJ|publisher=Transaction Publishers|isbn=978-1412855754}}
- {{cite book|first=Andrew|last=Vincent|year=2009|title=Modern Political Ideologies|edition=Third|location=Chichester, England|publisher=Wiley-Blackwell|isbn=978-1405154956|ref=CITEREFVincent}}
{{refend}}
Further reading
{{refbegin|30em}}
- Alan Bullock and Maurice Shock, ed. (1967). The Liberal Tradition: From Fox to Keynes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.{{ISBN?}}
- {{cite book |last=Epstein |first=Richard A. |author-link=Richard A. Epstein |title=The Classical Liberal Constitution: The Uncertain Quest for Limited Government |publisher=Harvard University Press |location=Cambridge, MA |year=2014 |isbn=978-0674724891}}
- Katherine Henry (2011). Liberalism and the Culture of Security: The Nineteenth-Century Rhetoric of Reform. University of Alabama Press; draws on literary and other writings to study the debates over liberty and tyranny.{{ISBN?}}
- Donald Markwell (2006). John Maynard Keynes and International Relations: Economic Paths to War and Peace. Oxford: Oxford University Press. {{ISBN|978-0198292364}}.
- {{cite book |last=Mayne |first=Alan J. |title=From politics past to politics future: an integrated analysis of current and emergent paradigms |date=1999 |publisher=Greenwood Publishing Group |location=Westport, CT |isbn=0275961516}}
- Gustav Pollak, ed. (1915). [https://archive.org/details/fiftyyearsofamer00poll Fifty Years of American Idealism: 1865–1915]; short history of The Nation plus numerous excerpts, most by Edwin Lawrence Godkin.
- {{cite book |last1=van de Haar |first1=Edwin |title=Classical Liberalism and International Relations Theory: Hume, Smith, Mises, and Hayek |date=2009 |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |location=New York |isbn=978-0-230-62397-2 |pages=17–40 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230623972_2 |language=en |chapter=What Is Classical Liberalism?|doi=10.1057/9780230623972_2 }}
{{refend}}
External links
- {{Wikiquote-inline}}
- {{Wiktionary-inline}}
- {{Commons category-inline}}
{{Liberalism}}
{{Philosophy topics}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Classical Liberalism}}
Category:19th-century introductions
Category:History of libertarianism